THE MASCULINE CENTURY
PART 2
COPYRIGHT
MICHAEL ANTONY
May 2007
CHAPTER
FOUR
THE
GROWTH OF THE CULT OF AGGRESSION
1) GETTING OUR BEARINGS
We are almost at
the half-way point of our journey and it is time to see where we have been and
where we are going. We have looked at how men were portrayed in Western art and
literature over the past few centuries and how their image changed. We argued
that what can be seen over the past hundred and fifty years is a process of
masculinization of Western man, which has now largely come to an end and is
partly (or at least tentatively) being reversed. We examined how men were
depicted in sexual relationships in literature, and how male behaviour in love
changed radically over the past two centuries, in a more masculine direction:
that is to say, towards more detached, cynical sexual exploitation, and less
sentimentality, less emotional involvement, and less verbal expression of
feelings. We then looked at attitudes to war in Western literature and how they
too evolved in modern times, from humanist protest to cynical acceptance – until stoic
indifference to acts of violence and massacre, a kind of stony insensitivity in
the face of horror and atrocity, becomes the prevailing mid-20th century male
style. We saw how this cult of toughness, of not flinching at atrocity,
facilitated the gargantuan programmes of mass-murder of the two totalitarian
ideologies which emerged from the First World War – rival ideologies
of total revolution, of abolishing the past, of starting history again from
zero after exterminating all opponents. And we saw how these ideologies of
revolutionary destruction were expressed in the arts, and above all the visual
arts – Futurism in the case of Fascism, Constructivism and Suprematism in the
case of Communism. A cult of perpetual revolution, sweeping away the heritage
of the past, invaded all the arts. But while literature escaped the worst of
it, because of the influence of the market and the taste of the reader, the
academia-controlled visual arts were dominated by this cult throughout the
century. A fashion for abstraction, dehumanization, a hatred of nature and
beauty, a cult of the machine and the industrial, of non-feeling,
non-expression and nihilism, made the arts of painting and sculpture more and
more autistic, sterile and life-hating until they finally descended into the
cult of rubbish and manufactured junk known as conceptual art. We tried to show
how much of this is related to the extreme masculinization of man’s sensibility
during the century of war, with its psychological concomitants: autism,
inability to empathize, emotional sterility, obsession with the mechanical and
the abstract, psychopathic aggression, and ideological fanaticism.
But militarism,
total war and the cult of revolution in the 20th century were merely
the culmination of a development that had been going on for much longer. It is
time to look in more detail at its roots, at how this masculinization of man
developed during the nineteenth century and made total war and mass murder on a
colossal scale possible. We will examine the influence on the Anglo-Saxon
character of the colonial, pioneering experience both of the British empire and
of frontier America,
the role of the British public school culture, and the growth of the Victorian
cult of “manliness”. And we will then look at
the development of the underlying ideologies of violence and struggle in the
latter half of the 19th century, in particular Darwinism and
Marxism, which inspired the 20th century programmes of mass murder. We will
conclude by looking at the most recent off-shoot of Marxism, feminism. We will
consider to what extent this movement can be seen as part of the general
process of masculinization of Westerners, a determination by women to adopt the
masculine role and character which are deified in the modern age. And we will
discuss whether this movement is preventing any attempt to move back towards a
more balanced way of life.
2)
THE TRANSFORMATION OF THE ENGLISH
When did the
English become what they are? Reserved, taciturn, keeping a stiff upper lip,
unable to express their feelings adequately, down-to-earth, practical, solid,
phlegmatic, stubborn, unimaginative, unpoetic, and no-nonsense? In short,
Conan-Doyle’s Dr Watson, the stolid companion of Sherlock
Holmes. This is substantially the same picture of the “ideal Englishman” of the early 20th
century offered to us in a recent book, The
English, by the journalist Jeremy Paxton. Describing “the Breed”, the private
school-educated upper and middle classes who ran the empire, he says they were “bold,
unreflective, and crashingly pragmatic, men you could trust”. He throws in as
extras (in a roundup of previous writers’ categorisations of the
type, including stolid, self-controlled, repressing all emotion and so on)
these qualities: a serenely complacent sense of national superiority, contempt
for foreigners, ignorance of literature or the arts, suspicion of
intellectuals, love of sport, all-round athletic ability, stoicism, and an
astonishing lack of interest in sex. 1
Now apart from
sporting ability, patriotism and contempt for foreigners (which the English
apparently displayed even in the 16th century) it is doubtful if Shakespeare
would have recognized any of these characteristics as typical of the Englishman
of his day. In all the amazing range of Shakespeare’s creations,
there is not a single character who embodies the traits which have been thought
to be typical of Englishmen for the past two centuries. Polonius is too
garrulous and fussy, Sir Toby Belch too fantastical and exuberant, Falstaff too
eloquent, cowardly, sly, boastful and mendacious, and his friend Prince Harry
too fun-loving, mocking, witty, cynical and calculating. Hotspur, though he
comes close in his taciturnity and contempt for the Welsh, is too choleric,
impetuous and quarrelsome. None of them have that element of bluff stolidness,
of stiff upper lip reserve, of unromantic pragmatism, which characterized “the Breed” of Victorian and
Edwardian times. Shakespeare’s young romantic heroes, from Romeo to Florizel, are
by our standards exuberant, demonstrative, spontaneous, witty, garrulous,
eloquent, sensual, poetic and emotional creatures, who wear their hearts on
their sleeves. What strikes us, in short, is their effeminacy – something commented
on by the actor Richard Burton, who called Shakespeare’s young heroes “ladies” and hated to
play them. They are, in fact, far more like modern Italians than modern
Englishmen. But the whole character and atmosphere of England in that age was far more like today’s Italy than today’s England.
Shakespeare’s England
was apparently the only place in Europe at
that time where women greeted male acquaintances with a kiss. The manners of
Englishwomen, described with delight by Erasmus a century earlier in 1499,
resembled those of Frenchwomen today (and were far freer than Frenchwomen at
that time, since Erasmus had already studied in Paris, and this did not prepare him for the
effusiveness of Englishwomen):
Wherever you come
you are received with a kiss by all. When you take your leave, you are
dismissed with kisses. You return, kisses are repeated. They come to visit you,
kisses again; they leave you, you kiss them all round. Should they meet you
anywhere, kisses in abundance; in fine wherever you move there is nothing but
kisses. 2
The historian Christopher Hibbert comments:
It was a habit
that persisted. In 1620 it was said that saluting strangers with a kiss was
considered immodest in a foreigner but merely civil in England, and at
the end of the eighteenth century it was still considered “the form of
salutation peculiar to our nation.” 3
What went wrong? What
happened at the beginning of the nineteenth century? Suddenly, from being at the cutting edge of
liberated, free-and-easy, demonstrative manners, sensual and “tactile” (as the Lonely
Hearts adverts now call someone who doesn’t flinch when touched), the
English underwent an abrupt change and veered to the other extreme. By the
mid-nineteenth century Englishmen had become a byword on the continent for
reserve, stiffness, and inhibition – men who shook hands with
their own children. How and why did this radical transformation come about?
It has always
astonished me how little this change has astonished anyone else. It is sometimes noted in passing by social
historians, but little attempt is made to explain it or even comment on its
significance. And yet it is a change in character so fundamental that in the
history of the nation it is almost as important as the industrial revolution – with which it
coincided in time. It is of course the outward sign of the coming to power of
the industrial middle class, with their puritan leanings. These were much the
same people who had just seized power in France by force – and it was the
French revolutionaries who had the most striking effect on the clothes, manners
and hairstyles of the time. The short hair and the introduction of trousers can
be traced to the sartorial sobriety made fashionable by the middle class
revolutionaries in Paris.
An English observer of the time, Sir Nathaniel Wraxall, recalled the “era of Jacobinism” in 1793-4:
It was then that
pantaloons, cropped hair and shoestrings, as well as the total abolition of
buckles and ruffles, together with the disuse of hair powder, characterised the
men; while the ladies having cut off those tresses which had done so much
execution, exhibited heads rounded à la
victime et à la guillotine, as if ready for the stroke of the axe. 4
Of course, during the
Terror, extravagant clothes, make-up, and long hair on men or even women were
dangerous marks of aristocratic fashion, and quickly disappeared off the
streets of Paris.
Conversely, for a while in the 1790’s in England, short
hair for men was seen as a subversive symbol of revolutionary sympathies. Then
it gradually won the day as a mere fashion, in the manner of long hair in the
1970’s. Within ten years Beau Brummel was setting the new fashion for
trousers and an entirely black uniform for men – dark colours
having begun to creep in for Englishmen over the previous decades, in contrast
with the mid-18th century when gold and silver cloth, pink silk and
diamond-hilted swords were all the rage. The sudden obsolescence of the old
aristocratic look is what is astonishing. The sense of a sudden cleavage in the
fashion and behaviour of generations is as marked in the writings of the period
(Pushkin for example) as it was to be in the 1970’s. The demise of
the old aristocratic manners, the hand-kissing, the kiss as greeting, rapidly
followed the clothes. A sort of anti-aristocratic spirit seems to take hold of
Europe, and above all England,
after the Revolutionary and Napoleonic wars. As so often happens, the
revolutionary ideas of the vanquished seem to have conquered the minds of the
victors (as we can see with Marxism today.)
But, as we
suggested, what lay behind this change of fashion was not merely revolutionary
ideas, but the coming to power in England of the same middle class which had
made the revolution in France. This was a trade and industry-based class which
had risen with the industrial revolution. They were often of Nonconformist
religion (that is, belonging to radical Protestant, non-Anglican denominations,
such as Calvinists or Methodists.) They were the spiritual descendants of the
anti-aristocratic, middle-class Puritans, the short-haired Roundheads, who had made the
English Revolution and Civil War in the 17th century. After the
parliamentary Reform Bill of 1832 this class gained considerable political
power as well, and they gradually infiltrated the aristocracy, by marriage and
the buying of estates. This middle class carried out in a peaceful, gradual way
the same social change that the French middle class had imposed by
revolutionary violence and dictatorship. The gradual step-by-step change in England was
made possible because Protestantism and parliamentary supremacy had already
modified the old order, allowing more freedom of thought and social mobility.
In France
the suppression of Protestantism (which represented a degree of religious
pluralism and dissent) along with the absence of parliamentary power had left
no way of opposing absolutism peacefully. But the tastes of the rising middle
classes in both countries were similar: anti-aristocratic, against extravagant
display and sensuality, Puritanical, work-oriented, fascinated by science and
technology, pragmatic and down-to-earth. In short, what is thought of today as
the traditional English character (what was called “The Breed” in Edwardian
times) is essentially the Puritan middle-class English character of the 19th
century. The 18th century aristocrat, with his dandyish dress and
exuberant lifestyle, his rakish sexuality and outrageous self-indulgence, was
now seen, in a combination of democratic sentiment and Puritan zeal, as a
parasite who had not worked for his wealth and had no right to these
extravagant displays of it. His whole lifestyle was abolished with startling
speed, along with his way of dressing. By the mid-19th century
everybody was in black suits and short hair; there was not a half-hose, a wig,
a lace cuff, or a colourful silk cloak to be seen, and the new sober fashion
reigned triumphant from Lisbon to St Petersburg.
It may be noted
(as a matter of curiosity) that about this time the fashion for both men and
women shifted (for the first time in at least eight hundred years) from blond
hair to black hair, and modish ladies began darkening their hair with a variety
of oils and unguents, instead of lightening it.5 This could have had
many causes: the romantic and Gothic-novel fascination with Italy, the brief
reign of Napoleon’s mulatto empress, Josephine, and the fashion for
classical Greek and Roman styles in Napoleonic France. But it also makes one
think of the descriptions in the medieval chronicler Froissart, depicting the lower
classes as not only smaller but darker than the aristocrats – who both in England and Normandy
were of Norman,
that is, Scandinavian, origin. Elsewhere in France the ruling class in his time
were mostly descended from the Germanic Franks, and a good part of the common
people were descended from darker-haired Gallo-Romans, or Latinized Celts. Even
in Venice in
the 15th century there was such a fashion for blond hair that women spent
fortunes trying to achieve the fairness of the ancestral Germanic Lombard
conquerors, to whom all the leading families traced their lineage. The sudden
fall from grace of blondness after the French Revolution coincides with the
demise of aristocratic fashions all over Europe.
It could lead to interesting (if unfashionable) speculation about a shift in
the actual blood line (or ethnic origin) of the dominant classes. The English,
like the French, being a mix of successive invading European tribes, it is
conceivable that the rise of the middle class was the rise of a non-Norman
origin element, a bit darker than their betters. This is of course pure
speculation, but the fierceness of class hostilities in Britain has
always had a tinge of something curiously akin to racism.
The
transformation of the English, and in their wake all Europeans, from a nation
dominated by the extravagant and colourful fashions of the aristocracy, into a
drab, black-suited middle-class nation might seem of no great importance. But
if style is the man (as a French critic remarked in a more literary context)
then this change of style represented a far deeper change. The colourful
clothes and long hair of the aristocratic male up till the end of the
eighteenth century showed a certain concept of masculinity which was perfectly
compatible with display, refinement, vanity, sensuality, and a degree of sexual
exhibitionism. The man’s legs were exposed in skin-tight stockings for the
admiration of women – not, it is true, right up to the padded crotch as
in Shakespeare’s day, but at least till the knee. Make-up was worn
by men and long wigs supplemented at need a full-flowing head of hair (English
judges’ wigs are simply 18th century
hairstyles.) An early eighteenth-century fop is described as wearing:
A coat of shot
silk, a pink satin waistcoat, breeches covered with silk net, white stockings
with pink clocks, and pink satin shoes with large pearl buckles. His hair was
dressed to a remarkable height and stuck full of pearl pins. 6
This kind of display by men
is no longer conceivable in our day except in homosexual circles, and even
there only for drag queen parties. Even the long-hair revolt of the late 1960’s
failed to break the taboo against heterosexual men wearing make-up, colours
like pink or displaying their bodies (particularly their legs) in an overtly sensual
manner. It is a peculiar paradox that only women are allowed to expose their
legs today; while in the past women had to keep their legs covered, and men
exposed theirs. The last hundred and fifty years have seen a concept of
masculine dress more drab, sober and sexless than anything ever seen before,
except perhaps in the dress of the poorest medieval peasants. Trousers were a
peasant fashion, widely worn by the serfs of Eastern
Europe and probably influenced by the Ottoman Turks. What is
striking in 19th and 20th century fashion is the banning
of any form of sensual display of the contours of men’s bodies. It is
this which represents a repressive, Puritanical notion of masculinity which any
previous age in Europe, certainly from the 14th
to the 18th century, would have found astonishing. It reflects the
new concept of masculinity as associated exclusively with strength and martial
vigour, not with sensual or aesthetic display – a male image reflecting at once the new
militarism, the work ethic of industrialism, and later on the tough pioneering
traditions of the New World.
The utter refusal
of men for the past century and a half to consider themselves or allow
themselves to be considered as sexual objects by displaying their physical
attractions (especially legs) was accompanied of course by a progressive
transfer of this function onto women, who gradually began to dress like sex
objects and nothing else. The extreme sexiness of women’s dress in our
age (in the late 1960’s revealing their legs almost to their crotch like men in
the 16th century), and the continuing drabness and repressiveness of
men’s clothes, symbolizes the polarization of active and passive roles. It
is one more sign of that distortion of masculinity, and by implication of
femininity, which has gradually occurred over the past two hundred years. Tom
Jones’ clothes resembled Sophia’s much more closely than
James Bond’s resembled Pussy Galore’s. Apart from the
fact that Tom’s legs were displayed in stockings, while Sophia’s were covered up
(and her neck and shoulders were displayed) their clothes were probably similar
in quality of cloth, colours, frilliness and general style. Tom wore colours
that James Bond would not have been seen dead in. Just as the characters of men
were much more like women’s in the eighteenth century, so were their clothes.
The
masculinization of English male dress and behaviour in the 19th
century was one aspect then of the rise to power of a puritanical, radically
Protestant industrial middle class. For them ornamentation and sensual display
were sinful, and kissing as a way of greeting was a licentious and depraved
practice. These were the same shorthaired Roundhead elements who, in Taliban
fashion, had closed the theatres in the seventeenth century, smashed statues of
saints and stained glass in churches, banned dancing as wicked, and fined women
for lewd dress. Now they were to start covering up carved piano legs to prevent
young women from having wanton thoughts. But though we might laugh
condescendingly at the excesses of Victorian prudery, it should be emphasized
again to what extent we still share their concept of masculinity, male dress,
and social behaviour. The Anglo-Saxons still do not kiss as a greeting, as we
used to in the 18th century. We have still not returned to a world
where a young man can wear pink stockings without being seen as gay. In fact
the gay liberation movement has merely ghettoized and in a sense stigmatized
any attempt by men to change this prevailing Puritan repressiveness. The very
desire to change it is now simply dismissed as a sign of being gay, and is
sidelined as a sexual sub-culture. Looking at young men’s casual
summer-wear at the start of the new millennium – the baggy
Bermuda shorts down to the mid-calf, the baggy T-shirts with sleeves down to
the elbow, the fat, clumsy sports shoes – the effect is completely
asexual. All evidence of the muscles of arm or leg carefully cultivated in the
fitness centres is hidden from sight. The whole effect is one of
infantilization – young men look like four year-olds dressed in their
older brothers’ clothes. Is it the fear of appearing gay that
imposes these drab, shapeless, sexless fashions? Is there a fear that a male
emphasizing the sensual contours of his body will be thought to be trying to
attract male eyes, not female eyes? Or is it a fear of provoking other males
into violence by escalating male rivalry in the display of muscles? Yet women
clearly appreciate the male form; one has only to see the following that soccer
has gained among American women because they can see men’s legs and the
shape of their backsides in their tight shorts (unlike in American football and
baseball where Victorian-era
knickerbockers are worn.) Yet none of this display of male bodies, so
appreciated by women, has been transferred from the sports field into men’s fashions. The
only male display allowed in normal street clothes at the moment is a kind of
minimalist hair display – relatively restrained hairstyles held carefully in
place with hair gel. The hair has returned to Roundhead shortness, but a token
form of display is allowed by showing that one has in fact used hair gel. That
minor advertisement of male vanity is the only modern sign of freedom from the
puritan straitjacket of the Victorians. It is even worse for formal clothes.
Dark suits are still the only formal dress allowed for men. Recent attempts by
the Germans at Berlin
receptions to restore some colour to their formal dress in the shape of bright
sashes or cumberbunds provoke only derision among British journalists. In
short, all the Victorian inhibitions about allowing the slightest hint of
effeminacy in men’s clothes, hairstyles or behaviour are still
overpoweringly strong today, and still determine male fashions to an
extraordinary degree. We are still wholly under the influence of the Victorian
Puritan counter-revolution which banned sensuality and display from male dress
as morally unacceptable, in a complete reversal of male fashions for the
previous five hundred years.
The so-called sexual
liberation that started in the late 1960’s has therefore been quite
limited in scope. It has not liberated our attitudes to male fashion, and the
burden of the nineteenth century puritanical concept of manhood still weighs
heavily upon us. How that concept developed, spread and perpetuated itself is
still something we have not fully understood. But in the success of all
ideologies, there is usually a key institution that embodies and promotes it.
In the case of the repressive, stiff-upper-lip Puritan-militarist ideology,
that key institution is clearly the British public school.
3)
THE ENGLISH PUBLIC (PRIVATE) SCHOOL
To the eternal confusion of the rest
of the world, the oldest private schools in England came to be known as public
schools because they were incorporated and governed by statutes. Developing out
of the old monastic schools, they were founded by kings or merchant
corporations in the Middle Ages, originally to educate the children of the
poor. By the 16th century fee-paying pupils were being accepted by
most of them for financial reasons (with the disappearance of the monasteries
and the church’s wealth in the Reformation), and there was a
gradual shift to boarding in the course of the 18th century. While
some children of landowners continued to be educated by tutors at home or in
the home of a neighbouring lord or squire (like Tom Jones), by the
mid-eighteenth century most of the lower gentry were sending their sons to
boarding schools. Dryden, Locke, Wren, Gibbon, and Bentham went to Westminster; Fielding and Gray went to Eton,
where a generation later Shelley was bullied mercilessly to the point of being
driven into hysterical rages. Sheridan and Byron went to Harrow.
These institutions probably played a formative role in the character of
Englishmen from the eighteenth century until the late twentieth. They may be
partly responsible for the transformation of character we have been discussing.
The salient characteristic of these
schools was their violence. Educationally they were narrow and inefficient.
Latin and Greek were virtually the only subjects taught until the mid-19th
century, and the huge classes (sometimes over a hundred) meant a reliance on
rote-learning and beatings as a way of instilling a minimum of knowledge. “Many a white and
tender hand, which the fond mother had passionately kissed a thousand times,
have I seen whipped until it was covered with blood,” recalled one old
Etonian of the early 18th century, “perhaps for
smiling, or for going a yard and a half out of the gate, or for writing an O
for an A, or an A for an O.” 7 Scholars were often lodged all together in huge dormitories,
several to a bed, without supervision, and left to their own nocturnal
amusements. These amusements were largely getting drunk, sodomy, sadism,
beatings, and the torture and rape of smaller boys. Since the boys ranged in
age from six to twenty (prep schools only began to separate off the
pre-pubescent boys in the late 19th century), opportunities for
cruelty were considerable. Boys were occasionally killed. Long Chamber, the
dormitory at Eton, became a byword for
brutality. It was the scene not only of orgies of violence but was overrun with
rats and excrement. Till 1784 it had no heating, and snow drifted in the broken
windows and covered the beds. Anyone who survived it was treated in later life
with the respect accorded a war veteran. A report in 1834 stated that “the inmates of a
workhouse or gaol are better fed and lodged than the scholars of Eton.” 8 Given the conditions of those institutions at the time, this would
put it in a class not far removed from a Nazi concentration camp. There was
some reform of schools in the mid 19th century and an attempt to
stamp out sodomy and drunkenness, but only by reinforcing the brutal regime of
control. The practice of flogging remained at a level of brutality that was
pathological. Some masters managed to flog a hundred pupils a day. Beatings
were often on bare buttocks till they were a mess of blood and lacerated flesh.
Blood routinely spattered the walls and floor. Floggings were sometimes
administered with bundles of branches containing sharp buds to cut the flesh – not quite the
cat o’ nine tails, but based on the same principle. Many boys were physically
scarred for life. The prevalence of flogging made it almost a cult, and some
boys grew so used to it that as men they became masochists, craving beatings as
the only way to find sexual satisfaction. Continental prostitutes referred to
flagellation as the English vice. A good number of English brothels specialised
in it.
But
flogging was not only carried out by masters. From the end of the 18th
century it was also done by prefects, as enforcement of discipline was
delegated to them. This was the legalisation of systematic, arbitrary sadism by
the equivalent of concentration camp kapos, the chief prisoners given licence
to beat weaker prisoners. Charles Lamb (of Tales
from Shakespeare fame) wrote: “The oppressions
of these young brutes are heart-sickening to call to recollection. I have been
called out of my bed and waked for the purpose, in the coldest winter nights – and this not
once but night after night – in my shirt, to receive the discipline of the
leather thong, with eleven other sufferers.”9 A Westminster boy recalled
more briefly: “I have been woken
many times by the hot points of cigars burning holes in my face.”10 The system of
“fagging” meant that younger boys had to act as personal servants of older
boys, often waiting on them till late in the night, and beaten mercilessly for
small failings, such as making a bed with a seam the wrong way. 11
The opportunities for the sexual abuse of fags by older boys were unlimited.
The experience of the upper-class Englishmen who went to these schools was not
unlike spending their childhood in a particularly brutal prison.
The Duke of
Wellington is famously believed to have said that the battle of Waterloo was won on the playing fields of Eton. This apocryphal statement was often enlisted in
later years as an argument for the moral benefits of team sports. But in fact
school games at the time of Waterloo
were merely a disorganized brawl with no official status. Rather the point
being made (if in fact Wellington
ever said this) was probably that the general harshness of public school life
was good preparation for the conditions of war. The brutality, the
pitilessness, the physical misery and discomfort, the endless bullying,
violence and persecution that prevailed at public schools were excellent
training for the military life. This was a world without women, where there
were no shoulders for the small boys to cry on. The first lesson was never to
show emotion or weakness. There was no one it was safe to show it to. They must
get used to swallowing injuries, insults, beatings, degradation, humiliation,
injustice, pain and betrayal without blenching, and without the comfort of a
mother or an older sister to whom they could pour out their woes. James
Fitzjames Stephens, a judge and historian of English law, wrote in 1840 that
the violence of Eton “taught me for life
that to be weak is to be wretched, that the state of nature is a state of war,
and Vae Victis the great law of nature.” 12 This is the sense in which “the playing
fields of Eton” were the training ground for Britain’s military
successes – the psychological toughening of boys to endure to
the end in a world without pity.
4)
THE ABSENT MOTHER
The British
public school, where boys were sent as young as six or seven, represents the
most extreme and precocious process of weaning known to man. Not even the
ancient Spartans separated boys from their mothers so young or so completely
(since Spartan boys at their military academies usually remained in the same
town as their family.) It argues a peculiar lack of maternal instinct in
British upper and upper-middle class women that they accepted this separation
with such docility. Is this at the root of that lack of sympathy and
understanding for women among Englishmen of the last two centuries which so
many observers have commented on? Betrayal, cold abandonment by his mother,
from whom the child expects unconditional love, is perhaps the one sin a man
never forgives. One thinks of lower-class Dickens’ bitter sense of
emotional betrayal when he overheard his parents arguing and realized his
mother was more in favour than his father of sending him to the bottle factory
at the age of ten. The British public school tradition probably instilled that
sense of betrayal into generations of upper-class males. Not that the men
openly blamed their mothers. A latter-day public school-boy, the actor Stephen
Fry, emphatically defends his mother from a charge of heartlessness, because
the pain she felt at each separation was only too clear to him. 13
Rather it is the demonstration of the mother’s powerlessness within the
system, the overruling of her maternal love by the harsh male laws of the
outside world, that impressed itself on the English public schoolboy from an
early age. The Englishman of the last two hundred years up to the late 20th
century seemed to expect little of that warm affection and selfless devotion
from women which men on the continent have always taken for granted. This is
perhaps because he saw his mother as a helpless, ineffectual figure, unable or
unwilling to stand up for him. The lack of spontaneous sensuality in the
Englishman’s relationship to women is perhaps due to the lack
of maternal love, a lack of instinctive trust of the female, and above all his
perception of the powerlessness of maternal love to protect him from the world.
Man’s sensuality and love of women is rooted in the memory of the warmth of his
mother’s breast as a place of total security, total sensual
satisfaction and emotional comfort. One thinks of Stendhal’s reminiscence of
his sensual obsession with his mother at the age of six: “I loved to cover
her with kisses, and I preferred her naked.” 14 This is a man for whom love between the sexes, in all its emotional
refinements, became literally a religion, the path to salvation. Some of
Stendhal’s most powerfully drawn love relationships are
between young men and older women whose feelings have a strong maternal
element. The young Rousseau’s relations with women were similar – he exploited
their maternal tenderness towards him. Women played an enormous role in the
lives of continental European boys throughout this period. Continental
pornography is often turned towards incest between growing boys and young aunts
or older sisters. We find this in Apollinaire’s erotic
novellas, which centre on bath time for the adolescent boy, shared with aunt
and sister, and ending up in sexual games. Sisters play a large role in the
European male’s erotic and emotional imagination – haunting even
such innocuous works as Kafka’s Metamorphosis.
Mothers, sisters and aunts have not usually had this sensual role in the young
Englishman’s imagination. The female family members seem almost
marginal to the boys’ lives – since they were separated
for most of the year. Upper class mothers are distant, like vaguely benevolent
aunts. But even when mothers are physically and emotionally present, as in the
lower-middle class world of Dickens, they are ineffectual, sickly and often
loveless. David Copperfield’s mother, a pitiable, weeping jellyfish, helpless to
protect her son from the thrashing of a bullying step-father, is a symbol of
English motherhood and the ineffectualness of maternal love. In much Victorian
literature mothers are absent. The typical Victorian hero or heroine is an
orphan (and often an abused one, like Heathcliff or Jane Eyre.) Pip is brought
up by a fearsome older sister. It is similar in America. In Mark Twain’s great novels of
rough and tough boyhood, mothers are replaced by stern aunts who are repressive
authority figures from whom the boy is always seeking to escape into his
wilderness. In the twentieth century, major American fiction portrays women as
cold, manipulative bitches, devoid of real love. As Camilla Paglia and others
have pointed out, one reason for this negative image of women is the absence of
the mother goddess Mary in Protestant America. You have only to walk into a
medieval cathedral to see that the main icon of European Catholicism is a young
mother and her baby. The central human relationship of continental European
culture is that of mother and son, the tragedy of maternal love in a cruel
world which makes the mother watch her son being tortured to death. In the
Protestant Anglo-Saxon world the central relationship is that of man to God:
austere, abstract and authoritarian – Robinson Crusoe on his
island addressing his prayers to Providence.
The Holy Family as a model for all human families, and the mother of Christ as
a model of maternal love, are strikingly absent from the Anglo-Saxon mental
world-picture. And this mirrors the very real marginalisation of the mother in
English life after the rise of the public school. Unlike the Virgin Mary, she
doesn’t watch her son being tortured, because she is hundreds of miles away. Boarding school from the age of
seven represents the most complete transfer of childcare away from the family
and towards collective institutions that has ever been carried out since
ancient Sparta.
(The Israeli kibbutz system comes nowhere near it, as mothers can spend time with their children every
evening.) For anything remotely approaching the collectivist child-care of the
British public school one has to turn to the fantasy projects of Plato’s Republic, or the early Soviet minister
Alexandra Kollantai, who also advocated collectivist child-raising, separated
from parents. One of the reasons Kollantai’s scheme was never put into
general practice may have been that Russian mothers, notoriously possessive and
protective, would never have stood for it.
Bertrand Russell,
watching the way mothers took leave of their sons at railway stations to go to
the First World War, concluded that parents do not love their children: they
merely want an opportunity to be proud of them. If the mothers had felt real
love, he implies, they would have tried to prevent their sons being taken from
them (as on the continent they often did.) But the public school system had
already inured Englishwomen to this violation of maternal instinct. If they
have watched a seven-year old son leave for boarding school, it is not so hard
to watch a nineteen-year old leave for war. Instead of the love that seeks to
preserve life comes the peculiar muddle of sentimentality and patriotic drivel
cited by Robert Graves in the famous letter to The Times of the “Little Mother”, self-pityingly glorying in
her own sacrifice of her sons as a heroic contribution to the great cause. 15
In the one war which history has judged to have been utterly unnecessary and
unjustifiable, Englishwomen joined enthusiastically in the pressuring of
adolescent boys to go and get killed. Feminist organisations converted
instantly into patriotic ones: the Pankhursts’ magazine was
renamed Britannia. Many feminists
recycled themselves as white feather brigades to taunt the young men who did
not volunteer by handing them a symbol of cowardice. The civilian pressure to
keep the war going embittered young soldiers like Robert Graves and Siegfried
Sassoon home on leave. So false was the atmosphere of moralistic jingoism at
home that they couldn’t wait to get back to the stoicism and realism of
the trenches. The women and men went through the war separately, and the women
had no real grasp of the shattering nature of the men’s experience.
Though the war gave women new independence as they filled the factories and
offices to replace the men, and it won them the vote, it did little to bring
men and women together in sympathy or understanding. One has a sense in Graves and others that the war left a legacy of
bitterness and mutual incomprehension between the sexes, and a vague sense of
betrayal. Graves’ own doomed marriage to a bigoted feminist, absurdly
and blindly convinced that women had suffered more than men in the war, was a
good example. The root of the male sense of betrayal may well lie in the
demonstration of the Englishwoman’s utter lack of
protectiveness towards her sons, brothers and lovers as they were sent to
slaughter. She manifested all the hardness of the ancient Spartan mother, who
presented a shield to her adolescent son with the words: “Come back with it
or on it.” The almost total submission of even radical women
to the war-mongering propaganda of the establishment, their lack of any strong
motherly instinct that the killing of hundreds of thousands of eighteen
year-old boys must be wrong, has probably left an effect even to this day.
The lack of a
warm, loving relationship with their mothers (which the public school culture
probably caused) and the consequent lack of any deep male emotions for women,
seems to be reflected in the growing tepidness and ineptness of English writers
on the subject of love after the eighteenth century. The last really great
celebration both of love and of women in English literature is in Shakespeare.
Both Chaucer and Shakespeare show us a society where women are at the emotional
centre of things, and the female characters they create are magnificent. This
is of course before the public school destroyed family life. From then on love
begins to shift from the centre of interest. Dryden’s All for Love already feels like a
rhetorical exercise, devoid of the sensual fascination Shakespeare shows for
Cleopatra. Byron’s Don Juan is
not quite serious – it is a cynical-sentimental backward look at the romantic
love of youth. Byron, though he was sexually addicted to women, was slightly
patronizing in his view of them:
Man’s love is of man’s life a thing apart;
’Tis woman’s whole
existence. 16
His perspective is that of a
good-natured serial seducer and whoremaster, rather sorry for the women whose hearts he has broken. But despite
a life given over to seduction, he creates no great female characters. The
women in his poems are mostly shallowly drawn, with few real human traits.
There is in English romanticism no trace of that spiritual idolatry of women
(and ability to draw their characters) which you find in Stendhal, or which is
reflected in Goethe’s line: “Eternal Woman draws us ever
higher.” It is doubtful if any Englishman of the last three
centuries could ever have said that, any more than he could have come out with Aragon’s line: “Woman is the
future of man.” There is a cult of the feminine character on the
continent which is not found in England
after Shakespeare.
Among English
novelists too, love loses its force at the end of the 18th century.
The same is not true of the Scots. Walter Scott in his novels, like Burns in
his poetry, portrays both love and women with passion as well as realism.
Neither of them went to boarding school, and Scott married a French girl,
daughter of a royalist refugee. Samuel Richardson, son of a joiner, who hardly
went to any school at all let alone a public one, is one of the last English
male novelists (along with Fielding) who seems capable of understanding the
character of women and making love seem the central passion of existence.
Though his flights of feminine sensibility (and lower-middle class morality) were
too much for the Eton-educated Fielding, who mercilessly parodied him, Richardson was greatly
admired on the continent. He deeply
influenced Rousseau and Goethe. Love was treated in the early 19th
century by four women authors, Jane Austen and the three Brontë sisters, all
daughters of clergymen and all lifelong virgins (Charlotte married after her last novel was
written and died within months – one can only hope the two events were not
related.) The Bronte sisters were also motherless from very early childhood,
and mothers are largely absent from their novels. Their portrayal of love,
while passionate, is unreal and fantasized, since none of them had ever
experienced it physically. Their male characters especially seem to us unreal.
Despite Jane Austen’s sophisticated analysis of relationships, one can’t help
feeling that for her love and marriage (at their best) appear to be about a
sort of mild friendship based on intellectual and moral respect, backed by a
suitable unearned income. Women characters in male fiction likewise become
increasingly vapid and fantasized, or else, at the other extreme, malicious and
manipulative. Thackeray’s greatest female creation, Becky Sharp, is a sly,
scheming vamp. Dickens’ Stella, object of Pip’s unrequited
lifelong passion, is a kind of phantasm, unattainable not just for reasons of
her initial class superiority, but because she represents a female sexuality
that is inherently teasing, beyond reach, tormenting, essentially sadistic – since Miss
Haversham has given her the mission of breaking Pip’s heart in
revenge for her own jilting. The original ending of the book, where he meets
Stella briefly in a passing carriage and then hears that she has married a man
who beats her and has thus learned the suffering that she herself inflicted on
him, is a psychologically necessary resolution to what is in effect a
masochistic love story. The tormentor must be beaten in her turn, to ease the
victim’s pain. Dickens’ relationship with women is
one of heartbreak and unrequited love (perhaps reflecting his own unfulfilled
love for his wife’s sister, who died young.) That remains the dominant
tone of most English portrayals of love which followed – all the way to
Maugham’s Of Human
Bondage, where the pain fairly leaps off the page.
The feeling
throughout the 19th century is of English novelists (both men and
women) writing of the opposite sex as though it were an alien species. There is
a chasm of mutual incomprehension, filled up by vapid fantasies and by
resentments that are the product of wounded or stunted sensibilities. There is
nothing comparable to the power or naturalness of Tolstoy’s portraits of
Anna Karenina and Natasha. One cannot help relating all this to the rigid
separation of boys and girls that boarding school education imposed in England. It is
significant that the few English male novelists who dealt in any way deeply
with love in the late 19th and early 20th centuries – Thomas Hardy,
George Meredith and D.H.Lawrence – did not go to boarding
school. With Lawrence in particular, one senses that the strong Oedipal
attachment to his mother – something impossible to maintain if one were sent
to boarding school at the age of seven – was a major source of his
inspiration and of his lifelong preoccupation with relations between the sexes.
It is not too sweeping a judgement to conclude that among the public-school
educated Britons up until the last forty years, the sexes were by and large
ignorant of each other, lacking in mutual sympathy or trust, and inclined to
idealize or despise each other to an extent not found in other European
cultures. This typically produced the goddess or whore syndrome (woman as
idealized phantasm, or vicious, disillusioning reality), or, for women, the
Heathcliff or Linton syndrome – dark, romantic, dangerous stranger or pallid,
conventional wimp. These deep-seated stereotypes, the fantasies of a
centuries-long gender-separated upbringing, have left their traces even in the
supposed sexual cornucopia of the present age.
This lack of sympathy between the sexes in England is
reflected in English manners over the last three centuries, as commented on by
foreigners. Chief among these was the peculiar upper class custom of the men
dismissing the women after dinner to retire to another room while they got down
to drinking and discussing men’s affairs: politics, business, hunting and war. It was a subject of ironical
commentary by baffled foreign visitors, such as César de Saussure in the 18th
century. He concluded that the men “generally prefer drinking
and gambling to female company.” He also thought Englishwomen much nicer than men,
because they did not despise foreigners and often preferred them to their own
countrymen. Another Frenchman, Joseph Fiévée, commented with indignation in
1802:
It is because they
want to get down to drinking that Englishmen get the women to withdraw after
dinner. Often at eleven o’clock at night they’re still sat
around the same table while the women are yawning their heads off in some
upstairs drawing-room. 17
The rudeness or
indifference of Englishmen towards their women is what now struck the
continental visitor, whereas two hundred years before it had been all the
contrary. In 1575 another visitor, Emmanuel Van Meteren, had reported:
Women are
entirely in the power of their husbands … yet they are not kept as strictly as Spain
or elsewhere. Nor are they shut up, but they have free management of the house
and housekeeping. They are well dressed, fond of taking it easy and commonly
leave the care of household matters and drudgery to their servants. In all
banquets and feasts they are shown the highest honour, they are placed at the
upper end of the table where they are the first served. …That is why England is
called the Hell of Horses, the Purgatory of Servants and the Paradise of
Married Women. 18
This is indeed a
contrast. Observers seem to concur that Englishwomen in the earlier period
(perhaps up until the Civil War, since we find the same comments in 1617 by a
German traveller) were the centre of attention, and in the later period
(perhaps after the victory of militant Protestantism in 1688) were gradually
marginalized and less esteemed. It is in the 18th century that we
start to find Englishwomen complaining about their treatment. Mary Astell in
1700 stigmatized marriage as slavery, and portrayed men as taking themselves
for God. 19 Her friend Lady Mary Wortley Montagu complained that
English marriage laws were far less fair to women in matters of property than
the Roman law generally in force on the continent (hence Van Meteren’s remark
about being “in the power of their husbands”.) 20 England,
paradoxically, was at this time regarded by other European countries as a model
of liberal, constitutional government, because of the 1688 revolution which had
installed a constitutional monarchy and an all-powerful, if unrepresentative,
parliament. The relative political freedom of England contrasted, as we shall see
in a later section, with a legal position of women that was worse than on the
continent. Part of this may be related
to the separation of the education of upper class boys from any female
influence whatsoever. They scarcely got to know even their sisters. The smug,
contemptuously sexist, over-masculinized culture which became so insufferable
in the Victorian period already had its roots in the England of the 18th
century. Later of course it spread its influence all over Europe, as the widely
adopted Napoleonic Code imposed the same legal disadvantages on women as they
suffered from in England.
5)
HIERARCHY AND BAUBLES
We have suggested the English public
school system was above all violent and pitiless, and instilled a sense of life
as a ruthless combat. It tended to brutalize the boys psychologically into a
suppression of all emotion and a hiding of all weakness. We have also noted how
it estranged the sexes from each other and made Englishmen ill at ease in
expressing love for women, and seemingly more superficial in their love than
the exuberant continentals. But there are other important influences of the English
public school system. It gave boys a sense of tribal loyalty, and not just to
the school but even to their particular house within the school – which translates
in the real world into a kind of loyalty to gang or clique. There were young
men who died in the trenches of the First World War with the name of their
school house on their lips. This narrow loyalty certainly prepared them well
for the regimental system, whereby the British army has developed group
solidarity to a rare degree by the simple device of making the group that is
the focus of loyalty very small. But above all the public school trained boys
in a deep respect for a complex, subtle system of rank and hierarchy. It imbued
a reverence for institutional hierarchies which overrode all other notions of
social status or personal worth. This was vitally important training for
institutions such as the army. One’s social rank in the outside
world had little relevance to the position one occupied in the ranking of the
school. Stories have circulated even in quite recent times of princes at public
schools having their heads shoved down toilets on a regular basis. Whatever you
were outside the institution did not protect you from the harsh rules and
pecking order inside. The public schools evolved a peculiar hierarchy of
distinctions and honours, often involving the right to particular variations in
the school uniform, depending on one’s year or on one’s membership in
the top sports teams. This was extraordinarily similar to the cult of
regimental honours and the various ranks and distinctions in the armed forces.
Here is Robert Graves’ description of some of the more Byzantine aspects
of the dress code at his school, on the eve of the First World War.
The social code
of Charterhouse rested on a strict caste system; the caste marks or post-te’s, being slight
distinctions in dress. A new boy had no privileges at all; a boy in his second
term might wear a knitted tie instead of a plain one; a boy in his second year
might wear coloured socks; the third year gave most of the main privileges – turned down
collars, coloured handkerchiefs, a coat with a long roll, and so on; fourth
year, a few more such as the right to get up raffles; but peculiar distinctions
were reserved for the bloods. These included light grey flannel trousers,
butterfly collars, jackets slit up the back, and the right of walking
arm-in-arm.21
He then recounts a sort of
revolution, which he calls “the bravest deed ever done at Charterhouse”, when three
sixth form scholars (who happened to be good boxers) usurped the privileges of
the bloods (the members of the cricket and football first elevens) by walking
arm-in-arm into Chapel one Sunday wearing the light-grey flannel trousers, slit
jackets and butterfly collars reserved for the sporting heroes. The failure of
the bloods to exact retribution for this act of caste rebellion led to a
decline in their prestige from which they never recovered.
This petty war
over dress makes comical reading today. But it accurately mirrors the obsession
with dress privileges of the regimental system. Graves
took this obsession quite seriously. He proudly related an incident involving
the “flash”, the bunch of ribbons once used to tie the pigtails
of soldiers (who had long hair till the early 19th century.) “The flash is
stitched to the back of the collar, and only the Royal Welch are privileged to
wear it.” This is the result of an incident in the 1830’s, when the
regiment were reprimanded for not having cut off their pigtails in line with
the new orders, which they had not in fact received in their overseas posting.
Their incensed commanding officer rode at a gallop to London and obtained the right to wear the
flash from King William IV in recognition of the regiment’s “exemplary service
during the Napoleonic wars”. Graves recounts
with evident pride that once in 1917 when an officer of his company went to be
decorated with the Military Cross at Buckingham palace, King George as
Colonel-in-Chief of the regiment took a personal interest in the flash. After
ordering the man to turn around so he could look at it, he remarked. “You’re still wearing
it, I see.” And then in a stage whisper: “Don’t let anyone take
it from you.” 22
Again the
obsession with the symbolism of trivialities of dress is difficult in this day
and age to comprehend. It appears to be an infantilization of grown men, to
make them obsessed with ribbons and baubles as the highest honours. Napoleon,
instituting the Légion d’Honneur, France’s highest
decoration, cynically remarked that men are ruled by means of baubles (the
French word he used, hochet, in fact
means a baby’s rattle.) But the point here is the extraordinary
similarity of the world of the public school and the world of the regiment.
They are worlds where life-and-death concepts of honour, pride, and caste
superiority are attached to symbols of an almost comical silliness. One is
reminded of Swift’s satire on the murderous dispute of the Big and
Little-Endians over how to eat a boiled egg. But one can see how the entire
public school culture prepared men for the army as a simple progression from
one caste-based, symbol-ridden, ritual-obsessed, rigidly hierarchical
institution to another.
6)
FRIENDSHIP OVER LOVE
The relative
absence of maternal or sisterly love in the experience of Anglo-Saxon boyhood
is compensated for by a cult of friendship. In all the great books about life
at English public schools, from Tom Brown’s Schooldays to Kipling’s Stalky and Co., the main positive value
is friendship. Friendship and all the virtues that go to make it up – loyalty,
generosity, forgiveness, tolerance of faults, self-sacrifice, courage, support
in adversity – redeem all the evils, the suffering, the
persecution, the bullying. It is hard to avoid concluding that friendship
becomes a cult in Anglo-Saxon literature of the Masculine Century – from Victorian
times to the Vietnam war – precisely because of the absence, or rather the
tepidness, of love between the sexes or within the family. You find it already
in Dickens, in poignant relationships like that between the orphan Pip and his
brother-in-law, Joe (presented less as a family member than a true friend.) It
is the dominant subject of Mark Twain, and figures prominently in the works of
Melville and Jack London as they explore the masculine world of men fighting
the elements. In the adventure and seafaring stories of Stephenson, Maryatt,
Kipling and Conrad (also largely worlds without women), friendship plays a
similar leading role. In novels like Tolkien’s Lord of the Rings, friendship is the main emotional relationship,
the source of the courage of the heroes as well as the poignancy of the story.
It is central to The Wind in the Willows
and almost all children’s stories of the past hundred and fifty years. Enid
Blyton based most of her stories on friends, from the Secret Seven and Famous
Five to Noddy and Big-Ears. The situation of three or four friends is the
foundation of much English writing in this period, to the same extent that the
premise of boy meets girl is the basis of most continental writing. The
isolation of boys from their families in the British public school, as well as
situations such as life at sea, and the American theme of a special male
destiny of revolt and combat with the wilderness, are the main contexts for
this cult of friendship. It is in many ways a throwback to the early medieval
period (The Niebelungenlied turns much on male friendship and betrayal, with
women as cause of conflict) and beyond that to the classical society in which
women were marginalized. The notion that men’s friendship is more
reliable and constant than women’s love is a commonplace of
classical literature, which finds an early expression in Hesiod (who recommends
boys over women, and not just as friends.) It is partly eclipsed by the long
period of the cult of love between the sexes beginning in the 12th
century, but we still find echoes of it later – in Hamlet’s choice of
Horatio as his special friend, after casting off the weak, manipulated Ophelia.
Friendship emerges centre-stage in the Victorian age, and reaches its
apotheosis in Ian Forster: “If I had to choose between betraying my country and
betraying my friend, I hope I would have the guts to betray my country.” As a famous
critic of Forster pointed out, this is the result of the closet homosexual
feeling encouraged by the public school system, and Forster is really
idealizing not friendship but the memory of his first romantic crush
on another schoolboy. An atmosphere of heavily emotional friendship informs
much of the secret intelligence community of the 1930’s, with its
famous homosexual traitors and double agents – all of it echoed
more recently in the spy novels of John Le Carré. Male friendship was of course
given a huge boost by the two world wars, where it seemed to be the only human
element left in a world gone mad. The kind of card-playing masculine fellowship
established during tedious wartime confinement in bunkers and ships had a long
afterlife, especially in the Anglo-Saxon countries. Its institutionalization in
America
in customs like the weekly men’s card night even provoked the fury and jealousy of
the Women’s Liberation movement – and the need for
male bonding was vigorously defended by the Lionel Tiger school of
anthropology. Today the cult of same-sex friendship plays a role in comforting
the convictions of the newly emerged homosexual sub-culture. Friendship becomes
life’s chief value for gay philosophers like Michel Foucault. The gay
sub-culture has sought to interpret many of the famous male friendships of the
past as closet homosexual ones. It is almost a litmus test of political
correctness for academics to accept that Shakespeare was the homosexual lover
of his patron, the Earl of Southampton, and that Homer’s Achilles was
the lover of Patroclus – even though the only solid evidence of sexual
relationships in both cases is of heterosexual ones (a wife, mistress and
daughter in one case, a captive girl concubine and son in the other.) There is
an attempt by the gay culture of today to reduce all male friendship to homosexuality,
but this reductionism distorts the variety and complexity of relationships in
various cultures. Teenage boys in the villages of Crete
in the 1970’s walked hand-in-hand in the streets, while denying
indignantly that they were homosexual lovers. The cult of friendship has often
been strongest in societies (such as the ancient German or the modern
Australasian) which were violently intolerant of homosexuality. Friendship has
a long history as an institutionalized custom quite distinct from homosexual
relations (conscious or unconscious), just as friendship exists in some other
species, where it generally has nothing whatever to do with sex.
7)
FRIENDSHIP AND AGGRESSION
Friendship is analysed by the famous ethologist and
zoologist Konrad Lorenz as inherently dependent on a culture of aggression.
Lorenz observed that friendships do not form in non-aggressive species, such as
most large herbivores. For an antelope all the other antelopes in the herd are
interchangeable: they have no special friends. Among geese, on the other hand,
there are friendships – and geese are exceptionally aggressive creatures.
They gang up on one another and fight continually, and their alliances and
friendships are long-term. Geese that are friends perform a ceremonial greeting
which Lorenz called “the triumph ceremony”. He analysed it as a symbolic
aborted attack : one goose feints an attack on an imaginary enemy, and then
together they celebrate their joint victory over this enemy. The friendship
greeting is thus a mock attack, followed by shared expressions of triumph. 23
Now Lorenz does
not go into the echoes of this behaviour among human beings, but it is clear
that the mock attack as friendship greeting is a widespread human custom.
Almost all gestures of friendship among men in the English-speaking world today
are mock attacks. The slap on the back, the punch on the chest, the high five
slap of the palm, even the strong handshake, especially the recently popular
vertical handshake which mimics an arm-wrestling grip, are all aggressive
gestures used as a sign of friendship. Among African-Americans (who seem to
have originated such greetings as the high-five slap) it is becoming common to
point a finger at the other, in the shape of an imaginary pistol – the greeting is
a mock shooting. The idea behind these greetings seems to be that in
demonstrating one’s capacity for aggression, one demonstrates the
value of one’s friendship. It is then a cause for mutual
celebration that this aggressive potential is not to be used against the other,
but is there for the purposes of common defence. This mirrors exactly what
takes place among geese and cranes, and for the same apparent purpose.
Most of these
aggressive forms of friendship greeting are relatively recent, and particularly
associated with Anglo-Saxon and Germanic cultures as they entered their
militaristic phases over the past hundred and fifty years. All military salutes
are mock threats of a slap, and are used playfully this way among schoolboys.
The mock attack as greeting culminates in the Nazi salute, where the arm is
extended like a sword, spear or bayonet, accompanied by a grim expression of
hostility. The spread of these greetings in the last hundred years or so is a
striking symbol of the masculinization and militarization of culture. Before
that the commonest greeting in Europe, which
still remains common in the South, was the kiss, a symbolic imitation of the
caresses of lovers or parents. This was also the customary greeting in England until
the end of the eighteenth century, when it abruptly disappeared, as we have
seen. The disappearance of the kiss, its replacement by the more aggressive
handshake, was part of that enormous change of style, from colourful cloaks and
long hair to sober black suits and short hair, which marked the start of the
nineteenth century, the beginning of the shift towards a militaristic,
over-masculine age. Even though this new sartorial sobriety spread across
Europe, the extreme anti-sensuality which banished even the kiss as greeting was
confined largely to Britain
and the Protestant north. It represents the triumph of Puritan middle-class
culture, repressive of all emotional display and replacing sensuality by
aggression – the same culture which had played a key role in
founding the United States.
The two societies (which Hawthorne had
contrasted in The Scarlet Letter, set
in the 17th century, when England still had a libertine
aristocratic culture) align themselves closely in the 19th century,
where the Anglo-Saxon world seems to form a unity, based on the shared values
of aggressive masculinity, emotional and sexual repression and male
friendship.
This whole
Victorian culture is still to an extraordinary degree what we instinctively
think of as “modern” in the Anglo-Saxon world.
We still have short hair, and dark suits are still the only formal dress
allowed for men. We still have a horror of physical contact among men and
cannot bring ourselves to kiss one another’s cheeks in greeting. Any
move to do so would at once be regarded as “gay” – one of the many
ways in which the new homosexual cult has in fact barred the way to any change
in men’s behaviour by appropriating and branding various
forms of behaviour as belonging to its own sub-culture. There are some signs
that the kiss as greeting between men and women is making a tentative come-back
among trendy younger people in London – as a
demonstration of their continental chic. The same thing could be observed among
young “alternative” people in Berlin in the
1970’s – determined to bring back home the customs acquired
on their Mediterranean holidays (not only was there much kissing of cheeks, but
ciao tended to displace tschüss.) But it is being counteracted
by the spread of the aggressive African-American palm slap among teenagers
today all over the continent of Europe. It has
been observed that the kiss as greeting is giving way to the palm slap even in France, among
those young people who identify with the hip-hop music craze. This is more
important than it might seem. A culture based on extreme aggression, a culture
of gang violence, is making inroads into the last areas of Europe
where the ancient, non-aggressive, affectionate greeting, the kiss, still
reigns (even frequently between men, especially in the south.) A form of
greeting which is a challenging expression of mock aggression is edging out the
old expression of affection. It has been observed in studies of children in
MacDonald nurseries world-wide that American children touch one another
affectionately only half as many times as French children, and express
aggression thirty times more often. Lack of kissing and cuddling in childhood
is now recognized as one of the root causes of violent behaviour in later life.
It is vitally important therefore that the kiss as greeting should survive in
Europe and resist the violent trends of America, which are being
insidiously exported under the banner of a rebellious ghetto “black culture”. These black
American ghetto fashions do not reflect African values: they represent the
trickling down into the black American underclass of the aggressive, puritan
culture of the Anglo-Saxon pioneers. Whether these trends will be resisted in Europe for long remains to be seen. What is clear is that
in the United States,
the levels of violent street crime and the fashion for rap music glorifying the
culture of gang violence, militate strongly in favour of the spread of
over-masculine aggressive behaviour. The palm slap, the most aggressive of
greetings, looks set to remain firmly in power there and to make progress
world-wide against the kiss on the cheek.
8)
THE TRIUMPH OF THE INARTICULATE
Another aspect of the aggressive, over-masculinized
culture that gradually rose to dominance in the course of the nineteenth
century was a tendency towards the inarticulate, the taciturn, a cult of
silence and the non-verbal. Along with the suppression of sensual display (the
colourful clothes and long hair of the 18th century), the suppression of
affectionate gestures (the kiss replaced by the handshake), went the suppression
of emotional display and verbal expressiveness. Men became strong silent types – more taciturn,
laconic, terse of utterance, less eloquent, articulate or verbal than any men
before them. We have come to see this as so much a part of modernity that we do
not even pause to question it or look for its origins. Yet like all things it
has causes, roots, a history; it did not spring from nowhere. How did modern
Western men (and above all English-speakers) become a tongue-tied race?
The disease is
recent. The thing that strikes any modern reader of eighteenth and even
nineteenth century English literature is the extraordinary verbosity of the
characters. They do not merely talk; they make long speeches to one another.
Their pronouncements are not merely lengthy; they are also extremely
well-turned, elegant and rhetorical. Our first thought is to put this down to
the style of writing of the time, which was perhaps less attuned to noting the
exact way people spoke, and how it differed from written discourse. But the
emergence in nineteenth century literature of talented mimics of class and
regional accents and personal idiosyncrasies of speech, who also represented
the speech of the educated classes as extremely well-formed, eloquent and
rhetorical, removes any doubt that this was in fact the way people spoke. Over
the past hundred years then we have seen a striking decline in the eloquence
and loquacity of people – in the copiousness of discourse, its complex
sentence structures, and its elegance of style. The twentieth century has seen
the triumph of the inarticulate.
Since verbal
expressiveness and talkativeness have been found by researchers to be above all
feminine qualities, and inversely related to levels of male hormone, this
decline of articulate speech can be seen as an important part of what we have
called the masculinization of Western humanity over the past hundred or so
years. Language is in fact acquired differently by men and women, using
different parts of their brains. The language skills related to grammar,
spelling and writing are all more specifically located in the left side of a
woman’s brain. In a man they are spread in the front and back part of the
brain. As with mathematical and spatial skills, it seems to be the sex that
concentrates this ability in one area of the brain that has an advantage. Girls
on average learn to talk earlier than boys and master a much bigger vocabulary
and more complex sentences at an earlier age. Women generally achieve higher
scores than men on verbal IQ tests, while men achieve better scores on spatial
ones. Language school teachers have long noticed that the top classes are
always full of girls. Girls seem both abler and more motivated to achieve the
highest level of proficiency in a foreign language. Popular attitudes associate
loquacity with femininity. We think instinctively of the very masculine man as
being a “strong silent type”, and the
feminine woman as being a chatterbox. A man who talks too much, especially when
others aren’t really listening and he doesn’t use this skill
to dominate, is thought of as rather effeminate and lightweight. A woman who
talks too little, unless it is through shyness, seems rather masculine and
dour. Whole peoples seem more masculine or feminine than others through their fondness
or lack of fondness for conversation. Tight-lipped Nordic men seem somehow more
masculine (at least in their own eyes) than chattering Italians. The degree of
animation in talking is also an indicator of femininity. Women typically move
their hands more, have a greater range of facial expressions as they speak,
have a greater variety of tone and pitch of voice. A man who displays any of
these traits is thought of as effeminate. Women in conversation seem to take
far longer to tell a story than men and tell it with far more dramatic detail.
Their talk is more emotional, more personal and confiding, and is used more
subtly to express their relations with each other, making more use of irony,
mimicry, sarcasm as well as emotion. The single biggest complaint of women
about their husbands is: “He doesn’t talk to me.” Men are hardly
ever heard to make this criticism of their wives.
Anyone trying to
project a masculine image will simplify his language and not use too many long
words. John Wayne (a bright schoolboy and avid reader) was notorious among
interviewers for asking with a sneer: “What the hell does that
mean?” when a word longer than two syllables was used. 24
Despising fancy talk and egghead words was part of his tough-guy image. George
Bush junior based his presidential campaign on a country-boy image of down-home
language and contempt for intellectual subtleties. His dyslexia and frequent
mistakes in the use of words, far from making him ridiculous in the eyes of
ordinary Americans, reinforced his rough-hewn, no-nonsense populist image. In
the roughest, most masculine cultures (Texas,
the Australian outback), a facility in using big words is considered not just
bookish and pretentious, but above all sissy and faggish.
It seems then that the decline over the past century of
eloquence and verbal expressiveness represents again a growing preponderance of
masculine traits in the Western (and especially
the Anglo-Saxon) character. The question becomes: what are the
mechanisms through which this new inarticulacy has come about? In the course of
the 20th century we can identify
several social trends in this direction : the rise of working class
culture as opposed to a better-spoken upper class culture (the cowboy,
gangster, or chorus girl replace the sophisticated socialite as cinema hero in
the 1950’s); the new influence of country and regional cultures as opposed to
urban cultures (notably in the cult of the Western, with its glorification of
the rural labourer); and in the Anglo-Saxon world, the increasing dominance of
American culture as opposed to British culture, with its more refined, literary
tastes and verbal sophistication. As America
asserted its place in the world, it emancipated itself from the cultural
influence of Britain,
stopped trying to imitate British aristocratic culture, and asserted its own
tough pioneering, cowboy traditions as a new cultural ideal. This was reflected
in the change towards more American, less Anglicized, accents and speech
patterns in the cinema in the 1950’s. British culture had, as we have seen,
also undergone a transformation of the male image throughout the 19th
century as the empire expanded. The time spent by men at sea or in the army or
on colonial postings in a rough man’s world, and the stiff upper lip culture of
the public school, all contributed to a more taciturn, inarticulate way of
speaking. But by far the most important element in the toughening of men’s
image and speech in the 20th century was the influence of war. The
trenches were a place where eloquence suddenly became misplaced and a tough
laconic style of speech took over. British officers began talking more like
their men. There was at least a partial breakdown in the huge class gap in ways
of speaking, as swearing became universal and non-saying became the new code.
The world wars, which made the ordinary soldier a hero, played a crucial role
in the democratization of culture and the rise in influence of working class
speech. The laconic style of Hemingway in his war books became hugely influential
throughout the English-speaking world. Finally we have the fashionableness of
women imitating men’s behaviour, which the war partly brought about. We
notice after 1918 women adopting more laconic speech, along with short hair,
sun tans, cigarettes and greater sexual freedom. This masculinization was also
part of the women’s emancipation movement – a rejection of
the feminine stereotype derived from the old aristocratic culture, and a sense
that a masculine style was the only way to get respect. In the novels of
Hemingway (as well as Chandler,
Hammet and others) we see women speaking in the same laconic, tough-guy way as
men, and they do the same in films.
9)
THE WORKING CLASS HERO
When we talk of the rise of working class culture, what
we mean is its increasing influence on mainstream literature, theatre, film and
fashion, and therefore on the way people of other classes spoke and behaved.
Nineteenth century American writers such as Fenimore Cooper, Herman Melville,
Mark Twain, Stephen Crane and Jack London draw many of their characters from
the poorly educated labouring class (frontiersmen, trappers, sailors,
farm-boys, vagabonds, cowboys, gold-diggers.) Starting with the early Indian
stories of Cooper, the Western gradually develops into a major literary genre
after the Civil War, and in the twentieth century becomes a major cinema genre.
The Western hero is typically a working class hero, and through this film genre
the speech and behaviour of the American rural labourer, the cowboy, came to
have a major influence (in its fictionalized form) on American culture as a
whole. The values of courage, physical strength, fighting ability, pugnacity,
endurance, as well as honesty and loyalty to friends – the typical
values of any labouring class – are consecrated as the values of American manhood.
The understated, laconic speech of this uneducated cowboy hero thus becomes a
model of masculine speech in general. The same is true with the rise of the
gangster movie in the 1930’s and the film
noir in the 1950’s, where the laconic, slangy insults and put-downs
of street hoodlums became a fashionable way of talking. The war film, more
often about ordinary soldiers than officers, adds to the range of working class
heroes. It is interesting to compare the relatively polished, British-sounding
accent favoured in most American films of the 1930’s with the far
rougher, more pronounced American accent beginning in movies of the 1940’s and 1950’s. And in this
latter period we also see the emergence of actors who play working class roles
well, because they were in fact working class: James Cagney, Humphrey Bogart,
Marilyn Monroe, Clark Gable, John Wayne. Films stop being mostly about high
society millionaires taking midnight dips in their swimming pools and begin
dealing with less well-bred people – low-life detectives,
waitresses, barroom dancers, petty criminals, soldiers, gangsters, pioneers and
cowboys. And their language changes accordingly. In the American literature of
the period there is a similar interest in “low-life” characters,
speaking the language of the mean streets, and many of the famous detective
films are based on novels by popular writers like Dashiel Hammet, Raymond
Chandler or Mickey Spillane, who took delight in hard-bitten, colourful street
language. In novels about the countryside there is a similar concentration on
the lives of ordinary Americans, and Faulkner and Steinbeck make the speech
rhythms of the rural working class something familiar to the whole world. This
emergence of the working class as a subject of literary and cinematic
treatment, and their speech as a new element in literature, was not confined to
America.
The same thing happened in Britain
at about the same time.
10) THE VOICE OF THE PEOPLE
After a brief
appearance in the subplots of Elizabethan comedy, the working classes made a
triumphant re-entry into literature in the mid-nineteenth century with Dickens.
His cockney characters, like Sam Weller, became instant favourites. Even more
significant is the figure of Joe in Great
Expectations, because Joe’s heavy, droll, muddled, incoherent way of speaking,
and his long meditative silences, become a symbol of the true virtues of
honesty, fidelity, and goodness of heart, which the hero, with his social and
class aspirations, has foolishly turned his back on, under the influence of his
fatal attraction to the snobbish little minx next door. Pip’s ascent in
society, due to the money mysteriously left him by the convict he once saved,
is symbolized by the increasing refinement of his language and manners. These
are hilariously mocked by the vulgar young thug, Trab’s boy, who
attacks him for his airs and graces when he goes back home. Along with his
upper class speech, Pip adopts an attitude of snobbery towards his own origins,
which he finally comes to recognize as insufferable, as he understands the rare
loyalty and decency of Joe. Here we have a striking literary alignment of
inarticulate, laconic speech with honest virtue, while fancy speech is
associated with falsehood and pretension. This pattern is to have a long and
rich history over the next century and a half.
Dickens had already worked the vein thoroughly in Hard Times. The girl from the circus, Sissy, when asked by the
teacher Gradgrind to define a horse, is struck speechless. She is quite
incapable of defining a horse in words, even though her father trains horses
and she works with them every day. Bitzer, the boy who turns out to be a minor
villain, can rattle off the verbal definition of a horse without any real
knowledge of them at all.
“Quadruped.
Gramnivorous. Forty teeth, namely twenty-four grinders, four eye-teeth and
twelve incisors. Sheds coat in the spring…..”etc.
“Now, girl number
twenty,” said Mr Gradgrind, “you know what a
horse is.” 25
Sissy’s muteness before
the idiocy of the question becomes a comment on the futility and superficiality
of book-learning, as opposed to the real experiences of life. This becomes
another aspect of the cult of the inarticulate: a lack of words shows not
merely greater honesty, but closer contact with real experience. The major
villain of this novel is of course the smooth, suavely voluble young aristocrat
who uses his gift of the gab to try to seduce an honest girl. On the side of
the angels are the honest worker, Stephen, with his excruciating local dialect
and incoherent repetitive speech (“It’s aw a muddle”) and the
lower-class circus characters with their quaint cockney slang and hearts of
gold. With the alignment of evil with the aristocracy and the factory owners,
and good with the honest working classes, we have a pattern of class morality
that will be a recurrent theme in literature well into the 20th
century. But for our purposes it is important to note how the good characters
are laconic and tongue-tied while the bad are well-spoken and voluble. There is
perhaps in this a hint of the old Puritan distrust of language as the
instrument of the serpent, the subtlest beast of the field, who conned our
mother Eve with fancy words. The English Puritans of the 17th
century closed the theatres as the instruments of Satan. And the working class
movements of the nineteenth century, as well as the rising entrepreneurial
class of Non-conformist Protestant religion, are direct descendants of the
Puritans of the 17th century, and heavily imbued with their
attitudes. Fancy speech is as much distrusted as fancy dress in the peculiar
class war of the age.
A new dimension
is added by DH Lawrence. Here the working class, in the person of Lady
Chatterley’s gamekeeper, becomes the repository not merely of
honesty and earthy reality, but also of deep sexual wisdom and potency. The
decadent, effete, over-sophisticated and impotent aristocracy can only be
redeemed by a torrid sexual encounter with the inarticulate working class,
expressing itself in guttural provincial dialect, generously laced with
four-letter words. Redemption for the aristocratic lady (married frustratingly
but also symbolically to a man crippled in the war) consists (as we saw
earlier) of being sodomized in the mud by a foul-mouthed gamekeeper. She must
also adopt his poverty of language and taciturnity for the therapy to work.
Lawrence’s preference for anal intercourse may well be a
personal idiosyncrasy, but in the dog position normally adopted for this
purpose it is arguably the sexual act which involves the least communication
between the parties. They do not even make eye contact during proceedings, let
alone talk. Lawrence
throughout his work shows an ambivalence towards words, which can never get as
close to emotion as gesture and act. In Women
in Love the lovers Birkin and Ursula argue themselves to exhaustion before
abandoning the verbal game in a sort of despair and proceeding, without any
intermediate show of emotion, to the physical act. Male friendship in the book
is expressed by wrestling naked rather than the usual verbal banter. Words are
a deception, a veil over reality, and for Lawrence
the deepest experiences are always wordless. It is no accident that his work
ends with the progressive reduction of the vocabulary of the protagonists, as
Lady Chatterley and the gamekeeper fashion a sort of private baby-talk out of
his dialect and pet words for their sexual organs. No adult language is really
needed any longer, since only the sexual act itself is an adequate expression for
the new, holy, primitive bond that unites them.
As the century
progresses we have the rise of working class authors by the shoal, and the
establishment of working class language in both Britain and America as the
dominant literary dialect. There are differences. America’s popular
language was first famously exploited for literary purposes by Mark Twain, and
it was the language of rural schoolboys and vagabonds. In twentieth century
American fiction, the popular language is more heavily influenced by the slang
of the criminal underclass, and becomes the hard-boiled style of writers like
Dashiel Hammet and Damon Runyon between the wars. In Britain there is a current of rural
dialect exploited in Hardy and others to provide local colour, but urban
working class language emerges later as part of a new politically-tinged class
consciousness. The working class way of talking comes to the fore as part of
the social and intellectual movement of non-upper class writers after the
Second World War, including playwrights such as Pinter, Arden, Osborne and
Wesker. This working class speech is not only seen as politically progressive
but also as more real, earthy, closer to the hard reality of life as it is
lived. The strong sense that low-life experiences are more real than high-life
ones, that the rich live in a sheltered cocoon while the poor face gritty
reality, runs deep through twentieth century attitudes. Jack Kerouac’s street-language
celebration of a drug-centred subterranean youth culture has spawned offspring
right into the nineties, notably in Britain, where the generation of
Ecstasy and cocaine have simply borrowed his old clothes. But the new writers
have given up Kerouac’s attempt (notably in The Subterraneans) to invent a new poetic language, a style of riffs
and jazz rhythms that owes much to Céline. Instead they merely reduce their
characters’ vocabulary to a few hundred words, many of them
polyvalent swear-words, without any particular striving for inventiveness. Here
is an opening two lines from Irving Welsh:
There’s us fucking
sitting out in the car-park, in the back of the van. No cunt wants our fucking
gear; it’s all been a waste of bleeding time. 26
Without making any judgement
about the literary merits of this, one is struck by the narrowing of the range
of language. And this kind of writing reinforces the central tenet of the cult
of the inarticulate: that the working class, marginal, lumpenproletariat or
criminal class are really there, in the centre, living; the fancy bourgeois
verbalizers are only watching life from the sidelines. To get inside late 20th
century experience as it really is you have to get rid of the verbal veil –
reduce your vocabulary to three hundred words, many of them with four letters.
Here we see the crossroads of inarticulateness with all the other masculine
preoccupations – violence, aggression, toughness, drug-addiction and
sexual promiscuity – that have given the last half-century its peculiar
flavour. It is one of the paradoxes that we get the extreme form of this cult
of the masculine and the inarticulate in literature when the 20th
century is at an end, and this entire cult has become not much more than a
pose. In Bonfire of the Vanities, Tom
Wolfe hilariously shows the lawyers of New
York City, graduates of famous universities, sitting
around with knees splayed like football jocks, confining their talk to
four-letter words, slang and the grammatical errors of illiterate, black street
dialect – all in the cause of gritty machismo. One wonders if
this ever happened in any other age – if Cicero and his friends from the law courts
slouched about rapping in the slang of the gladiators. It is highly doubtful.
This is a peculiar and unique twentieth century phenomenon, and it is confined
largely to the Anglo-Saxon world, not merely because of the tough pioneer cult
of the Americans, but partly because of the peculiarities of the English
language.
11)
ENGLISH AS THE LANGUAGE OF CLASS WAR
There is a
dimension of the cult of inarticulateness, of taciturnity, of distrust of
verbal expressiveness, that is specifically Anglo-Saxon. It has always
surprised me how little attention has been given to the peculiar relationship
that English-speakers have with their language because of its hybrid nature.
English developed after the Norman invasion as a kind of merger between the
French of the Norman conquerors, the new landowners, and the Germanic dialect
spoken by the Saxons (as the Angles, Saxons, Jutes, Danes and assimilated
Celtic remnants who made up the mass of peasantry tended to be called from then
on.) This linguistic fusion did not happen by design or in any planned way. In
fact nobody knows exactly how it happened. We know that the Normans
in England
kept speaking French for over two hundred years as their native language, but
their geographic isolation from the continent made their French seem more and
more bizarre to continental ears. They imposed French on England as the
language of government and the law courts, which it remained till the
mid-fourteenth century. But the Normans were a
small minority, and after the loss of Normandy
to the French king in 1204 would have begun to feel more of an English
identity. Presumably the need for the two peoples of England to communicate would have
led to efforts on both sides to learn the other language. Somehow during this
process a merging of languages took place, and Old English got Frenchified into
Middle English. It may have happened in two ways. We may surmise that as the
French-speaking Normans began in the 12th and 13th centuries
to learn to speak what had been Old English, they transferred into it masses of
words from their native French, supplying the gaps in their vocabulary and
transforming English grammar and sentence structures in line with their own
language. Or, we may equally speculate that the better-off and more upwardly
mobile among the Saxons found themselves obliged to learn French, the language
of law and government in England for three hundred years, and from their
bilingualism they introduced into their native Anglo-Saxon a mass of French
words – much as educated Algerians today pepper their
Arabic with French words, or educated Indians sprinkle their Hindi with English
expressions. Whether it was the bilingualism of the Normans or of the Saxons that was the main
agent of change it is perhaps no longer possible to discover. But the
bilingualism of one or the other or of both is the only explanation for the
profound transformation of the English language between the 11th and
14th centuries, from a purely Germanic language to one that had (as
it still has today) a roughly equal number of words of French and Germanic
origin, and a sentence structure similar to French. Only with these changes did
English become a sophisticated enough language to express complex abstract
ideas as easily as French or Latin, something essential for it to begin
displacing these rivals as the speech of the educated class in England.
This process took
nearly three hundred years. It was probably not till about 1300 that the Norman ruling class overwhelmingly
adopted English as their everyday speech. A decree of parliament in 1332 urges
that “lords, barons, knights and honest men of good towns should exercise
care and diligence to teach their children the French language,” making clear
that French had ceased to be their mother tongue. 27 Even from the
mid 13th century we find treatises for teaching French (as a foreign
language), and a little later monastery rules insisting that French and not
English should be spoken by the monks. 28 When it came to writing
literary works Chaucer in the latter half of the fourteenth century could still
have chosen French, which remained the language of the court (because Richard
II, like many Plantagenet kings, was raised in France) and, during his
childhood, of the law. Only in 1362 were proceedings in courts of law finally
switched to English, in recognition that this was now the majority language
even of the upper class. The Hundred Years War with France (which really lasted
250 years) began (in its first phase) in the 12th century reign of
Henry II (who was born in France, the Duke of Normandy and Count of Anjou, and
never learned to speak English) as a war between two French-speaking
aristocratic classes both with roots and family estates in France. It ended up
200 years later as a war between Frenchmen and Englishmen, as the new language
spread to the ruling class in England
and gradually transformed them into a nation apart. (It was Joan of Arc’s brilliant
discovery that the English were foreigners, and not French at all; she must
have heard English Norman knights jabbering their new language.) The adoption
of a single tongue finally unified England as a nation, and French
began to be stigmatized as a foreign language, which Shakespeare would soon
take pleasure in belittling: “The chopping French we do not understand.” 29 And as the Norman ruling elite adopted English, they were at the
same time being gradually expelled from the lands they held on the French
mainland, till the Channel was finally established as the boundary between the
two nations. The Hundred Years War may be described not so much as an English
attempt to conquer France,
but as a war of expulsion from France
of the French conquerors of England,
and the ending of their territorial rights in France. Such an expulsion was made
inevitable by feudal law. The Plantagenet kings of England
kept trying to tie their ancestral French possessions to the English crown
instead of the French one – since they refused to do
homage to the French king – which meant in effect annexing parts of France to England. The French refusal to
accept the fairly solid claim of Edward III to the throne of France, preferring
a Frenchman of less direct line, was a sign that they no longer regarded the
Normans of England as part of the wider French-speaking world (as they did the
Burgundians, the Occitans and the Provencals.) The rupture was consummated by
war.
But the period of
nearly three hundred years during which Early Middle English was spoken by the
native Anglo-Saxons and French by the Norman ruling class, and the radical
degree to which French influenced the native language, have both left their
mark on the way the different elements of the language are perceived. It is
often forgotten that the Norman occupation was, in the early days, one of the
cruellest and most brutal in European history. We may surmise that the
innovations introduced into English, either by the French-speaking Normans or by the class
of upwardly mobile (“collaborationist”) Saxons – the transfer of
thousands of French words into the old English language – encountered a
certain resistance on the part of the mass of resentful and oppressed Saxon
natives. The latter may well have avoided using these new words and stigmatized
them as “foreign”. As the Normans and the
class of collaborationist Saxons (an inevitable accompaniment of any foreign
occupation) began speaking between them a form of English laced with French
words, it would have been natural for the mass of native Saxons – subjugated,
dispossessed and embittered – to despise and reject these new words as foreign
gobbledegook. Any Saxon peasant who used the new French borrowings may well
have been seen not merely as pretentious, but as a traitor, identifying himself
with the hated occupiers. It is perhaps to this experience of linguistic
conquest and resistance that we can trace the peculiar attitudes which English
speakers have to their language even to this day. The French (or Latin)
elements in the English language are still instinctively regarded as
pretentious and snobbish by a good part of the working class. “Posh” or upper-class
language is essentially vocabulary of French origin. Popular speech is
dominated by the Anglo-Saxon element. A child learns first of all the Germanic
words of English. The basic verbs: come, go, see, hear, run, laugh, make, do,
and the basic nouns: milk, butter, bread, mouse, cat, cow, land, man, wife,
son, daughter, brother, sister, house, home are all Germanic, and easily
comprehensible to a modern German, who at once relates them to kommen, gehen,
sehen, hoeren, Milch, Butter, Brot, Maus, etc. A children’s story is told
largely in Germanic words (and most of our children’s tales, thanks
to Anderson and the Brothers Grimm, have a distinctly Nordic or Germanic feel
about them.) But when an English-speaking child gets to ten or eleven, he
begins to learn an abstract vocabulary, most of which comes from French. The
entire sentence you are focusing your attention on at the moment contains an
exclusively French (ultimately Latin) vocabulary, except for the articles,
pronouns, conjunctions, and prepositions, and a solitary auxiliary verb. You
will notice that all the Germanic words in that sentence have just one short
syllable, and several of the French words have four syllables and as many as
twelve letters (almost half the alphabet). Many people of low education never
achieve a comfortable mastery of the French element of our language. In
self-defence, they continue to despise it as the posh language of a “foreign” ruling class.
It is noticeable
that the British upper classes still use far more words of French origin in
their vocabulary than the lower classes do. Any yokel wanting to talk in a “posh” or “educated” way will start
using longer, French-origin words, and the tendency to get them wrong is mocked
as early as Shakespeare’s Much Ado
About Nothing in the figure of Dogberry. This incompetence in using the
long Latinate words will be mocked later in the figure of Mrs Malaprop in Sheridan’s The Rivals, and even in the person of
Baldrick in the TV series Blackadder.
It becomes therefore almost a mark of lower class allegiance, a kind of tribal
loyalty, to refuse big words, to confine oneself to the familiar Germanic words
learned in childhood – those that are instinctively felt to be the “simple” words of the
language, because they are short and are familiar to those with even the most
basic education. To use big words is to be a show-off, pretending to higher
education – as when people (especially Americans) say “utilize” instead of
“use”, or “terminate” instead of “end”. This kind of
pretentiousness may even be resented as a kind of betrayal of one’s class – especially when
a working-class person has left home to go to college and comes back talking
differently. It may even be seen as a badge of allegiance to the upper class
enemy. And given the cultural bias whereby the ruling class were considered
softly brought-up sissies, unable to stand the hard life of the labourer, there
is an association (among men) of big words with effeminacy. This gut instinct
about the language appears to be felt in all the nations which speak English,
particularly in Australia, New Zealand and rural North
America. It goes some way towards explaining the cult of
inarticulateness (and anti-intellectualism) among modern Anglo-Saxons – the association
of the inarticulate with manliness and toughness. If tough guys don’t dance, they don’t use big words
either. As we have seen, John Wayne, that macho icon, used to sneer at big
words as the mark of eggheads and sissies. It takes an effort of imagination
(or a great familiarity with other cultures) to realize that speakers of other
languages do not have these attitudes. They do not divide their language into
tough, plain, virile short words and sissy, egghead or stuck-up long ones. A
Frenchman or a German or an Italian uses long words or short words without
distinction. He has no sense of using different elements in the language, with
different class associations, because there are no different elements. Only
English is a hybrid language, carrying into the twenty-first century the mutual
resentments of Saxon and Norman of nearly a thousand years ago.
It is partly
because of this anchoring of class hatreds in language that the English class
system remains so incredibly tenacious. And it is this that gives a sort of
class basis, one might almost say a basis of tribal loyalty, to the cult of
inarticulateness and in a broader sense the whole cult of anti-intellectual,
brutish masculinity among the English-speaking working classes. It is a form of
self-inflicted cultural and intellectual privation, and the latest to suffer
from it are the American black underclass with their rejection of sissy “white” education. It is
one of history’s incredible ironies that young Chicago ghetto
blacks – clinging defiantly to their impoverished
one-syllable language against any attempt to educate them – are still out
there batting for the Saxons of the twelfth century against their stuck-up,
plummy-voiced, long-word-spouting, faggish, foreign-sounding Norman
rulers.
12)
THE RISE OF MORONIC LANGUAGE
There
is therefore a peculiar linguistic-class dimension to the gradual rise of
inarticulateness in the literature of the masculine century. The working
classes of the Anglo-Saxon world are verbally inept, taciturn, monosyllabic and
brutishly ignorant with a defiant pride unknown to the speakers of other
languages. A French worker aspires to speak like the middle classes. A French
mechanic will be highly articulate in explaining what is wrong with your car,
and he will elucidate the technical terms for you with the same quiet
professional condescension as a doctor. There is no reverse snobbery on the
continent of Europe, no perverse pride in a
lack of education. There is among English-speakers. This gives a peculiar
linguistic edge to the transition to a democratic, working-class dominated
society in the twentieth-century English-speaking world. As the age grew more
democratic with the victory of the mass conscripted armies of the two world
wars, and the glorification of the ordinary soldier hero – with the
accompanying rise of worker-based political parties – the shift of
literature to working class heroes and working-class language was inevitable.
But in terms of culture this meant the new assertion of crudeness and roughness
of speech and a reverse class snobbery, expressed in a contempt for
book-learning and in openly anti-intellectual attitudes. A person of low
educational achievement was no longer apologetic about it, but defiantly
asserted his ignorance and rudeness as the new dominant forces in society: the “yob” was born. The
assertion of brute ignorance in the name of democratic values was stronger or
weaker in different parts of the English-speaking world. In Australia it was
perhaps strongest because of the influence of the 19th century gold
rushes, which overnight made ignorant labourers and ex-convicts into rich men,
who saw themselves as the equals of anyone. More recently the spread of
assertive crassness depended on how “progressive” education
systems were – that is, how much they pandered to working class
ignorance and self-brutalization, instead of trying to overcome it. But one of
its consequences was the gradual disappearance over the last half century of
the sophisticated language – the eloquence and crafted wit – of an aristocratic
verbal culture that had its origins in the classical rhetoric of Greece and Rome.
We
have seen how at the turn of the century Oscar Wilde’s obsession with
being a gentleman gave way to Hemingway’s obsession with being a
man. Hemingway’s style owes nothing to the classics. Oscar Wilde’s is almost
impossible to imagine without Horace, Martial, Juvenal, Bacon, La
Rochefoucauld, Congreve and the whole line of practitioners of the epigram in
the background. To be a gentleman is to speak as heir to a long tradition of
highly ritualized utterance. To be a man (a “real man”) is to speak as
an animal would speak. The destruction
of the upper class tradition of speech in the democratic century is an
essential part of that masculinisation of language we have referred to as the
growth of inarticulateness. The taciturn replaces the loquacious; silence
replaces the word. The long cadenced speeches of Jane Austen’s or George Eliot’s characters give
way to the monosyllabic, tipsy exchanges of Hemingway’s Brett, to the
pithy wisecracks of Hammett’s Sam Spade, and finally to the “fucking-fucked-up-fucker” dialect of
Irving Welch’s housing estate hooligans. In drama the pregnant
pause replaces wit. Pinter and Beckett replace Wilde and Shaw. The pauses in
Pinter’s work take up twice as much time as the actual
dialogue. Not that the characters can be assumed to be thinking between lines;
they are mostly morons who have not yet reached the threshold of thinking. When
they do talk, it is in clichés, platitudes, advertising slogans. Beckett’s last dramatic
work consists of four minutes of silence. This comes close to the kind of
inanity we find in the visual arts towards the end of the twentieth century :
the blank canvases, the vacuous installations, the empty room with the lights
going on and off, the crumpled sheet of paper, the chewing gum, the pickled
fish. Or in trendy “serious” music, the silent orchestra
staring at the audience. What they all have in common is a flaunting of their
own inability to communicate anything, and their complete lack of interest in
doing so. Non-communication becomes an end in itself, as if this were some
profound insight to be reflected on – not just once, but over and
over again. Silence becomes one of the key elements and concepts not only of
twentieth century art, but of theatre, music, cinema. The cult of silence
represents the complete triumph of masculine inarticulateness over feminine
expressiveness; of masculine autism over the feminine passion to
communicate.
13) THE FORGING OF THE
AMERICAN CHARACTER
All of these cultural changes in the English-speaking
world over the past two centuries were occurring within the context of two
major historical developments: the rise of America
as a separate society with its own specific culture, and the expansion of the British empire and its influence on the imagination of
all English-speakers. The imagination of Englishmen as well as Americans became
increasingly obsessed with that long undeclared war on large parts of the globe
which the Anglo-Saxon peoples in particular waged throughout the 18th
and 19th centuries as they colonized other continents, plundered
their wealth or ransacked the oceans for their riches. The colonial and imperialist
experience was largely a masculine experience. Sailors in ships (whether Conrad’s trading ships
or Melville’s whalers), Kipling’s soldiers or
engineers on colonial postings, Cooper’s frontier Indian-fighters,
or Jack London’s gold prospectors and trappers, lived their lives
mostly separated from women. They were locked in a struggle to survive against
the forces of nature, or in conflict with other men in a world without law.
This inevitably widened the psychological chasm between men and women. It
marginalized women and feminine qualities, shifted the character of men in a
one-sidedly masculine direction, and substituted male friendship for the
man-woman relationship as the main human bond.
The settlement of America
exposed the settlers to continual dangers and hardships of a kind that in Europe were associated only with periods of war, plague
or famine. Conditions of survival in the colonies were grim: of a hundred
colonists who settled Jamestown,
Virginia, in 1607 only thirty-two
survived the first winter. The
privations of hunger and disease were not followed immediately by war with the
Amerindians, but when war came it was ferocious. The Amerindian habit of
torturing captives to death, while not indulged in systematically, was frequent
enough to cause terror in their enemies and a spirit of no quarter on their
side also. In their war with the Pequots in 1637 the settlers did not hesitate
to set fire to a village, even though it killed hundreds of women and children
as well as warriors. But their own fears of annihilation were not groundless.
King Philip’s War in 1675-76 killed more of the total white
population proportionately than any war Americans have fought since. Over half
of New England’s 90 towns were
attacked by the Indians, 17 razed to the ground, and 25 pillaged. One in ten
combatants died. Sneak attacks on sleeping villages became current. Heads and
body parts were displayed on poles by both sides. The need for Indian allies
led to an acceptance of the native practice of scalping, as bounties were paid
to Indian allies for each enemy they could prove they had killed. Now these
cruelties were not out of proportion with the general horrors of war at that
time. Displays of the heads of rebels were common in Europe
in the 17th century. The fall of Magdeburg in the Thirty Years War led to the
massacre, torture and mass burning of civilians on an altogether larger scale
than any massacre in American history. What was different was that in Europe this kind of horror was somewhat rare, in that war
was not a constant fact of life. The Thirty Years War was an exceptional
calamity. Although it killed off millions of Germans through massacre, famine
and disease, as towns and crops were burned, in other cities in neighbouring
countries life went on as normal. Elsewhere in Europe
these huge losses were treated as a far-off cataclysm. For the English
colonists in America,
living side by side with Indian tribes, war was a constant low-intensity threat
which they had to be ready for at any time. In the ninety years between King
Philips’ War in 1675 and the end of the French and Indian
War in 1763, the colonists were at war with the French or the Indians or both
(since the French fought largely through their Indian allies) for thirty-nine
years. The longest period of peace was nineteen years. Every colonist had to
have a firearm and powder at home ready to use at any time. Moreover, this
threat remained a fact of American life until the end of the 19th century, with
a growing ferocity in popular attitudes towards the Indians, fed by a constant
diet of atrocity stories. The worst massacres of Indians occurred in Colorado and California
in the mid 19th century, carried out by maverick settlers, not
troops. There were rarely pitched battles between armies alone, and tit for tat
civilian massacres by both sides continued intermittently till 1890, by which
time disease had so reduced Indian numbers that all will to fight collapsed. By
contrast, after 1650 nobody in England
was ever killed in his own home by enemy armed forces until the Blitz of 1940.
Throughout most of that period, American men grew up with an instinctive sense
that their role as males was to be ready to fight and kill to defend home and
family against sudden sneak attack. This led to a very different attitude to
violence. 30
In the early,
difficult days of settlement, dogged by hunger and disease, many American
hunters, fur trappers and traders lived similar backwoods lives to the Indians.
It was inevitable that some would even join tribes – it provided them
with wives and safety in numbers, and may have been useful to the Indians in
providing them with interpreters for their dealings with the whites. American
school history books tend to concentrate on the Puritan settlers of New England
as the founders of America,
since they left the most documents and became politically dominant in the
nation. But there were large numbers of settlers who flocked to places like Virginia without having
any religious motivations. What drove them was a desire for quick wealth,
plunder or adventure. These tough, often wild frontier adventurers, renegades
both to law and their own civilization, sometimes joining Indian tribes,
remained a permanent element in the settler population. Even after there arose
towns and cities on the Eastern seaboard with a more elaborate and civilized
pattern of living on a European model, the ranks of the desperadoes were
swelled by immigration. The anarchic movement of settlers westwards prolonged
the way of life of the half-savage hunters, trappers, scouts, and
Indian-fighters, and ensured that these remained among the quintessential
Americans, despite the veneer of civilization being laid in their rear. The
westward moving settlers built makeshift, lawless frontier towns and struggled
to wrest a living from a hostile land. The discovery of gold led half the
desperate ruffians of the planet to join in gold-rushes to California,
South Dakota, Montana,
and Idaho,
where, after Indian resistance had been crushed by the army, they set up
primitive shanty-towns rife with violence. An American army officer wrote: “There never was a
viler sort of men in the world than is congregated around these mines.” 31 The pattern of American life outside the largest Eastern cities
continued for a couple of centuries to be more dangerous, lawless and violent
than anything Western Europe had seen since the early Middle Ages – apart from times
of war. And the characters it forged, the men of the backwoods, the mining
towns, the fur-trade, those who fought in the Indian wars or made the long
cattle drives, were men essentially different from the men of eighteenth or
nineteenth century Europe. They were mostly
men not used to civilized society or the company of respectable women, men who
were hard, aggressive, quarrelsome, who went about armed, and did not recoil
from violence. In short many of them were closer to the rough Vikings who
settled Greenland with Eric the Red than they
were to the city-dwelling contemporaries of Mozart, Coleridge, or
Tennyson.
Of course there
were also educated men in early America,
and their writers engaged in literary and philosophical writing of a similar
sort to that going on in Europe. But the
common man in America was a
different breed from that of Europe, a harder,
tougher, more violent breed, more willing to take the law into his own hands,
because he often lived beyond its reach. And this character of the American
common man became in the literature of the nineteenth century, as American
writers asserted their independence of European models, a figure that even the
educated American admired. The glorification of the rough, tough, ignorant,
uncultivated American hero, which begins with Fenimore Cooper’s backwoodsmen
and Indian fighters, moves through Melville’s whalers, Crane’s Civil War
soldiers, on to the gold-rush adventurers of Jack London, and finally to the
cowboys of Zane Grey, is a development whereby a new model of man, radically
different from his European contemporary, is gradually imposed as the archetype
of masculinity upon the Western world.
Leslie Fiedler
first drew attention to the absence of love in the American novel, the
substitution of man’s relationship with nature and death for man’s relationship
with woman, the latter being the chief theme of most European literature from
the 12th century onward. He speaks memorably of American man’s obsession with
violence and his embarrassment before love. He cites Fenimore Cooper’s Natty Bumpo,
the eternal bachelor, wedded to the dark goddess, the wilderness. He remarks
how the young heroes of Mark Twain or of Melville were innocent of all sexual
knowledge but on intimate terms with death. These are very different heroes
from those in continental European novels at the time, concerned mostly with
falling in love. But there is a tendency in Fiedler to look at this purely in
terms of literary movements, to see the American novel merely as a disturbed,
adolescent local branch of Western romanticism, the cult of innocent nature and
the noble savage. He sees American society as a neo-classical enterprise of
rationalism, with its Enlightenment constitution and imitation Roman
institutions, which gave birth paradoxically to the romantic saga of the
ever-expanding frontier. 32 But he does not seem to see the element
that is neither classical nor romantic – neither an imitation of
past civilization, nor a romantic cult of nature – but a very real
return to an era of savagery. For the underlying reality of the conditions of
survival of pioneer America, with its ferocious Indian wars, its vast areas of
lawlessness, are a throwback to the culture of the so-called Dark Ages, one
which had not yet emerged into civilization from the savage anarchy of the
great volkswanderung, the Germanic
tribal migrations of the 5th and 6th centuries, where
force was the only law. American society imitated in its Eastern towns (and
among its educated class) certain of the outward forms of European
civilization, but it contained in its Western heartland a profound atavism, a
reprimitivization of man almost as extreme as that which separates Clovis from
Cicero.
14)
WOMEN IN A MAN’S WORLD
The return to a
kind of primitive natural man, struggling with the wilderness as Ahab struggles
with the white whale, means a loss of most of the qualities which we have come
to think of as civilized. And many of those qualities we would also think of as
feminine. It is because of this return to a violent and savage state of nature,
where man’s brutal struggle to survive precludes all sympathy
for the feminine virtues, where an entirely masculine ethos rules, in which
strength, courage, aggressiveness, endurance, killer instinct are the only
virtues, and grace, wit, elegance, sensitivity, and compassion have no place,
that women have found America such a difficult world in which to find a
satisfactory role. This was a land where women fitted in merely as marginal
adjuncts for reproductive purposes, where they had to choose forever between
conforming to a male ethos that distorted their nature, or keeping that nature
and remaining marginalized and patronized, if not despised. It is highly likely
that the discontents of women which gave rise to the feminist movement of the
late twentieth century (long after political and legal equality had been
achieved) had a lot more to do with American culture and its traditional
marginalization of women than they did with modern civilization in
general.
Relations between
the sexes in 19th and early 20th century America never
seem entirely satisfactory. This is partly due to the Puritan heritage. Hawthorne’s great novel, The
Scarlet Letter, shows the fate of the American woman in early Puritan New
England who dared aspire to sexual fulfilment in an illicit relationship of the
kind many upper class women in Europe took for
granted. Because of this no-go area, the American woman over the next two
centuries has a much more limited choice of roles. She is either a perpetual
naive child in her femininity, an eternally immature flirt, never seriously
sexual, like Henry James’ Daisy Miller, or she abandons femininity and
becomes like Annie Cordy, circus sharp-shooter, out-riding and out-shooting the
men. Either she creates for herself a feminine world in works like Little Women which seems curiously
infantile by comparison with the world of Anna Karenina, or else she belongs to
a masculine pioneer world in which she has been hardened and toughened till
little of woman remains in her. In neither role does she seem entirely
fulfilled. One of the paradoxes of hard and brutal conditions is that suffering
and hard work harden women, and then men resent that hardening. Men never
forgive the disappearance of the soft maternal affections that these hard
circumstances (and their own hard characters) have destroyed. Here is how
Faulkner describes (through her husband’s eyes) Mrs Armstid in Light in August. Her husband has just
brought home to shelter for the night a pregnant girl who is on foot far from
home seeking her runaway fiancé.
She is still there the grey
woman with a cold, harsh, irascible face, who bore five children in six years
and raised them to man- and womanhood…….. And now he knows that she
is watching him, the grey woman not plump and not thin, manhard, workhard, in a
serviceable grey garment worn savage and brusque, her hands on her hips, her
face like those of generals who have been defeated in battle.
“You men,” she says.
“What do you want to do about
it? Turn her out? Let her sleep in the barn maybe?”
“You men,” she says. “You durn men.” 33
In this simple exchange lies
the infinite distrust and bitterness between the sexes in America. There
is the wife’s cold suspicion of her husband’s generous
motives in bringing home the girl, her harsh contempt for the girl for being
such a naive, trusting fool and getting pregnant, her bitter resentment of all
men for the trouble the girl has got into. But beyond it, unspoken, is a
resentment of the life she leads, the poverty, the hard labour, and it is the
man she blames for this too, as if her hard life is the result of a swindle, a
confidence trick the man has pulled on her. And the man’s sexual urges
are somehow at the back of this dirty swindle. She has had to bear and raise
the children of his lust – a lust probably not accompanied by much in the way
of tenderness. Her entire life has been a defeat, and she seems to see it as a
defeat at the hands of men. And her resentment is implacable, shown in her cold
refusal to give the affection, sensuality and love which alone could redeem
their harsh existence. Her refusal of any attempt at prettiness or seduction (“the serviceable
grey garment worn savage and brusque”) is almost a form of
revenge. There is in this woman something not so much broken as worn down and
whittled away by time, hard work, disappointment, a harsh environment,
suffering, lack of tenderness, lack of romance – her identity as
a woman. And it has left in its place only hardness and bitterness. The chasm
between the sexes in this portrait is absolute, not because they are too
different but because they have become the same, and the instincts of both
crave the difference, and cannot relate to each other without it.
We have suggested that the violence and hardship of the
pioneer experience made Americans (and
to some extent other colonial peoples such as Canadians and Australians) a different
breed from Englishmen or other Europeans of the time. But the English began to
catch up with this change as the nineteenth century advanced. The experience of
the expansion of the empire into exotic places influenced the imagination of
Englishmen too and gradually the way of life of many of them. From the
mid-nineteenth to the mid-twentieth century, the Englishman (and particularly
the English boy) lived an imaginative life that was rooted in the Yukon, the Australian outback, the Khyber Pass, the Oriental
seaports, or the jungles of Africa far more than it was in the towns and
countryside of England.
The boys’ stories of the time are full of the lure of the
exotic, and a whole crowd of British authors, led by Stephenson, Kipling,
Maryatt and Conrad, recount with fascination the experience of the colonies, of
the sea, of the great trading ports of the new colonial globalization. These
are books about empire, and the Englishman begins to see himself as at the
heart of a global empire rather than as a citizen of a European nation. And
like their American counterparts, these authors write mainly about men and men’s undertakings.
You can read hundreds of pages of their novels without coming upon a
significant woman character or a romantic love plot. Compare that with the
novels being written on the continent at the same time, by Stendhal, Balzac,
Flaubert, Zola, Tolstoy, and the central part occupied by women and love in
their stories. You can see the degree to which the Anglo-Saxon mental world
picture diverges from European continental civilization in the course of the 19th
century. But it contrasts also with what English culture had been in a previous
age – the love-obsessed, woman-centred world of Shakespeare’s comedies – a society where
the height of social aspiration was to join a royal court whose tone was set by
feminine intrigue. The combination in the Victorian age of a public school
upbringing separated from women and girls, and the prospect of a career of
action and adventure in the colonies – whether in the navy, the
merchant navy, the army, the colonial civil service, or as a colonist trying
his hand at farming, mining or trading – meant that many Englishmen’s lives were now
lived almost entirely in male company and according to male rules. Women hardly
impinged upon this world at all. When we finally begin to see women introduced
into it, the dismal failure of most male attempts at relationships with them – which we find
recounted in Orwell’s Burmese Days,
or some of the novels of Conrad, or later on the stories of Maugham – only testifies
to the chasm between the male world and
the female sensibility in that age. Well into the 20th century,
woman remains an alien in this colonial world of soldiers, sailors, policemen,
engineers or administrators. She is always portrayed as having just got off the
boat from England,
and being utterly out of place in what amounts to an alien culture, even if it
is that of her expatriate countrymen. She is unable to understand its rules or
its spirit, and invariably disturbs its harmony, usually by a display of
incomprehensible female emotions. The great colonial adventure was a world of
masculine values, and its success reinforced those values a thousand-fold in
Anglo-Saxon culture. Masculinity became in the 19th century not
merely a quality or set of qualities: it became the very essence of human
worth. “Manliness” became the chief virtue,
extolled by moralists and novelists alike. The purpose of morality, of
education, was to inculcate manliness. One can see that in this society women
would not have a very easy time asserting the value of their own characters, or
making any recognized contribution to the world except by becoming clones of
men. The very definition of “virtue” had gone back to its Roman
origins in the word “vir” , a man.
15)
THE CULT OF MANLINESS
As we move
through the nineteenth century this new cult of manliness reaches the
proportions almost of an obsession. The word “manly” itself is one of
the most hackneyed, worked-to-death adjectives in all writing throughout the
entire century. A few examples must suffice. Early in the century Byron is
praised by a friend for being “candid and manly” in calling off a duel with
his friend Tom Moore. Dickens describes Martin Chuzzlewit’s temper as “free and manly”; he is
particularly fond of the adjective. Trollope has a woman character describe his
hero as “manly and handsome”, and the author
himself describes him as having a mouth “in which was ever to be
found that expression of manliness which of all characteristics is the one
which women love the best.” 34 MacCaulay praised the English yeomanry of a previous age as “an eminently
manly and truehearted race.” Thackeray, speaking of Robert Fleury’s paintings, admires “the manliness of the artist”. Even literary
style is praised as manly by Victorians, whether it is that of Julius Caesar or
Machiavelli. Woodrow Wilson’s father praised him for being manly: it was one of
the standard compliments men paid their sons, and seems to have represented an
educational ideal. The definition of manliness exercised many minds. Some
sought to distinguish it from mere aggressiveness. Others associated it with
self-control, as in Thackeray’s description of the hero of Pendennis: “He had the passions to feel and the manliness and
generosity to overcome them.” 35 “Manly honour” was defined by one writer
as the refusal to take advantage of the love of a pure girl. Thomas Arnold,
headmaster of Rugby, was seen as the
incarnation of “manly piety”. One of his most famous
pupils, Thomas Hughes, author of the best-selling Tom Brown’s Schooldays, praised his old headmaster
for having taught his boys to strive “against whatever was mean
and unmanly and unrighteous”. 36 This apparently included drinking.
The effort to moralize the notion of manliness, to make it include every
desirable virtue, or else to recommend various virtues by associating them with
manliness, runs through all the moral exhortations of the age. The trend
culminates in an attempt to repackage Christianity as a “manly” religion.
Twenty years after his success with Tom
Brown’s Schooldays, Hughes, by now a leading
moral pundit on both sides of the Atlantic,
published The Manliness of Christ.
Hughes had
acquired an enormous popular and moral following with his bestseller based on
his days at Rugby public school. The book is a
document of the values of the time (1857, two years before Darwin’s opus.) His hero Tom Brown’s manliness is
defined first and foremost as pugnacity. The reader is assured of his
possession of this trait in the opening pages. “The Browns are a
fighting family. One may question their wisdom, or wit, or beauty. But about
their fight there can be no question.” 37 Tom is introduced to Rugby
School in the midst of a
strenuously contested football match, which is lovingly depicted as a brawl.
(Rugby rebelled against the sissy new rules of football known as the Cambridge
Rules laid down in 1848 by the universities, and continued with its more
vigorous and combative version of the sport which has carried the school’s name ever
since.) Tom, already a tough young urchin in his own neighbourhood, is soon
initiated into the physical rigours of school life, and a succession of
graphically described fist-fights fills the book, culminating in his epic
thrashing of the most objectionable school bully. This saga became a cult book
in its age, not only in Britain
but in America.
Hughes became the spokesman of a manly current of opinion favouring tough,
martial training for boys, which the age enthusiastically embraced. Hughes’ own work with
the London Working Men’s College, which he helped to found in order to
reclaim the wayward, underprivileged youth of the city for Christianity, led
him to see that Christ himself had an image problem. As traditionally depicted,
the Saviour was quite simply not manly enough. This led Hughes to rewrite the
New Testament story expunging all traces of effeminate weakness and sissy
pacifism from its message. In The
Manliness of Christ he aimed to show “manliness as the perfection
of human character” and Christ as the perfect exemplar of this
masculine vigour. 38 His Christ becomes a warrior manfully wrestling
with hydra-headed evils: the arrogance of priests, the temptations of the
devil, and betrayal by friends. Thus rebranded, he was clearly a more congenial
role model for the tough slum kids and street hoodlums of Hughes’ secular
flock.
Hughes’ friend Charles
Kingsley became an even more extreme spokesman for what came to be known as “muscular
Christianity”. Kingsley’s invective against the
effeminacy of High Church Anglican and Roman Catholic clerics is an interesting
throw-back to the Reformers’ original revolt against the degenerate sensuality
of Renaissance Rome in the 16th century. Just as Luther’s and Calvin’s rebellion was
partly directed against the sensual vices and love of pleasure, luxury and
ceremony carried over into the church by admirers of the rediscovered classical
culture, so Kingsley voices the new Victorian Puritanism, revolting against a
church too long under the influence of a decadent aristocratic class given over
to pleasure and display in the same way as their Renaissance forefathers. “Effeminate” became the worst
insult of the age just as “manly” was the highest compliment.
Much of this
rhetoric of manliness seems to have developed because of a perceived trend in
the age in the opposite direction. The shift from an aristocratic to a
middle-class culture, symbolized in the shift from stockinged legs and
colourful cloaks to drab suits, was seen by many of the pundits of the time as
a shift from rule by a military caste to rule by tradesmen. While from our
point of view, looking at images of manhood, the long-haired, powdered,
silk-wearing 18th century aristocrat looks decidedly more effeminate
than his sober, dark-suited, shorthaired successor, what the Victorians saw in
this fop was a man wearing a sword and prepared to use it. Now this traditional
wearing of arms by aristocrats ceased in Victorian Britain. Duelling, that
deadly defence of aristocratic honour, came under moral and legal attack and by
the mid-nineteenth century had disappeared. Despite, or perhaps because of, the
English abandonment of “the right to bear arms”, the streets
actually became safer with the introduction of Robert Peel’s policemen or
Bobbies to defend against muggers and footpads. Now this new safety in the
streets worried the advocates of manliness like Kingsley. He wondered “whether the
policeman is not demoralizing us” and whether the “protection of
body and goods” would not “reduce the educated and
comfortable classes into that lap-dog condition in which not conscience, but
comfort, doth make cowards of us all.” He feared that the lives of the majority
would become “mean and petty, effeminate and dull”.39
There was, in short, not enough crime and violence to stimulate manly virtues.
The age was going to the dogs and breeding up sissies because it was too safe.
This debate
extended into contemporary efforts to reform the law and make punishments less
cruel. After successfully banning torture, the slave trade and then slavery
itself throughout the empire, the humanitarian lobby mounted a major campaign
against public executions. The subject aroused violent passions, as the issue
of the death penalty still does in America. When Sir Henry Taylor
published a book, Crime and its
Punishment, which took a hard line, Kinglsey wrote to him expressing his
support, but predicted gloomily that his cause would be noisily opposed due to
the “effeminacy of the middle class, which never having in its life felt
bodily pain (unless it has the tooth-ache) looks on such pain as the worst of
evils.” He went on with some criticism of Taylor’s arguments.
My experience of
the shop-keeping class (from which juries are taken) will hardly coincide with
yours. You seem to think them a hardier and less dainty class than ours. I find
that even in the prime of youth they shrink from (and are often unable to bear,
from physical neglect or training) fatigue, danger, pain, which would be
considered as sport by an average public schoolboy. 40
Here we have the crux of the
culture war of the time: the upper class products of the public school system
of brutal hardening of boys feared the debilitating influence of a new
shop-keeping class of wimps who hadn’t been through the same
tough mill. The new humanitar-ianism, the softening of punishments, the
abolition one by one of such invigorating practices as torture, slavery,
branding, mutilation and flogging, spelt a weakening of the race. This
attitude, that the advance of civilization has an effeminizing and weakening
effect on man’s primitive vigour, is widespread in the age. It
informs a good deal of what came to be called Social Darwinism. This attitude
was given classic formulation by Theodore Roosevelt in a speech at the University of Berlin in 1910:
One of the prime dangers of civilization has always
been its tendency to cause the loss of virile fighting virtues, of the fighting
edge. When men get too comfortable and lead too
luxurious lives, there is
always danger that the softness eats like an acid into their manliness of
fibre. 41
For an American ex-president
to solemnly warn German youth of the danger of losing their “virile fighting
virtues” four years before the Great War is one of the
superb ironies of history.
Roosevelt is an extreme,
one might say a pathological case, of the cult of masculinity. A sickly
asthmatic weakling needing thick glasses to see, he reacted to weakness with a
ferocious determination to live and strengthen himself. An incident of bullying
in his youth provoked him to learn boxing, which, along with hunting, became
his favourite pastime. “The strenuous life” was his motto:
he became a fanatical devotee of every form of toughening up. He entered
politics partly because he was warned how tough and brutal it was. His career
in manliness reached its apogee in his participation in the war against Spain. As
assistant secretary of the Navy he was a loud advocate of war, and he was
disgusted at the government’s reluctance to declare war in 1898 after the
sinking of the USS Maine in Havana harbour. He left Washington to raise a cavalry regiment known as the Rough
Riders, and when war was declared, he took them to Cuba. There they enjoyed a
triumphant campaign, achieving glory in their storming of San Juan Hill, during
which Roosevelt boasted of killing a Spaniard
with his own hands. The popularity of these heroics made him a shoo-in for
governor of New York,
and Vice-President in 1900. He succeeded McKinley the following year on the
latter’s assassination.
This was an American president who owed his electoral success almost entirely
to his macho posturing, and he was not the last to do so.
America was of course a
society prone to macho excesses because of its colonial history. The cult of
male honour, in which the aristocratic duelling code of Europe
was freely adapted to the habits of violence of a frontier society, was
especially strong in the southern states before the Civil War – and may have
contributed to its outbreak. The militarist code of this society may be
illustrated by the statement of Sam Houston’s mother, when he joined the
army to fight against the British in the war of 1812. As she handed him a
musket, she warned him: “Never disgrace it; for remember, I had rather all my
sons should fill one honourable grave than that one of them should turn his
back to save his life.” 42 This Spartan sentiment reflected something of a cult of classical
martial attitudes at the time, notably in the south, where Christian names like
Virgil and Homer were popular. As the civil war was heating up in 1861, one
Lucius Quintus Cincinnatus Lamar (perhaps the culminating point of the
classical names fashion), a secessionist politician, provided the following
curious justification: “The fight had to come, we are men not women The
quarrel had lasted long enough. We hate each other – the fight had to
come. Even Homer’s heroes, after they had stormed and scolded enough,
fought like brave men, long and well.” Having invoked these
classical precedents, he then recalled a scene on the senate floor five years
before when a southern politician had beaten unconscious a northern senator,
Sumner, for insulting his uncle. If, he said, “the athlete
Sumner had stood on his manhood and training and struck back when Preston
Brooks assailed him, Preston Brooks’ blow need not have been the
opening skirmish of the war. Sumner’s country took up the fight
because he did not.” 43 This is a curious reduction of the civil war to an extension of a
feud of honour between two politicians. But it is symptomatic of the ethos of
the times that this fist-fight could even be evoked as relevant. It is almost
as if it could all have been settled by a duel between principals if the code
of manly honour had operated as it should have.
The American civil
war was in many ways the first modern war, both because of the enormous numbers
mobilized (3 million men, or a tenth of the population, of whom 600,000 died,
mostly of disease – more than the total of American deaths in all the
wars since then put together) and because of the importance of railways and
logistics in winning what became an unexpectedly long war. It led to a popular
revulsion from war for a generation – which, as we have seen, was
largely over by the time of the jingoism of the Spanish war at the turn of the
century. But in retrospect the war came to be seen by some public figures as a
heroic demonstration that the ideals of chivalry were not dead in the age of
bourgeois comfort. Oliver Wendell Holmes, addressing veterans on Memorial Day in
1884, praised their martial virtues as a throw-back to past glory:
High breeding, romantic
chivalry – we who have seen these men can never believe that
the power of money or the enervation of pleasure has put an end to them…. New England is not dead yet. She is still the mother of a
race of conquerors – stern men. 44
Here we see war extolled as
the reassuring proof of the moral health of a society. There is again the
obsessive fear, expressed by Roosevelt, of the
loss of “virile fibre” in the comfort of a
prosperous age. This was an obsession equally felt in Europe, particularly in
nations that expected a military showdown with their neighbours in the near
future, such as France and Germany. This
obsession with physical and moral preparedness for war lay behind the rising
cult of sport.
16)
SPORT AS MILITARY TRAINING
Sport was seen
quite explicitly as a sort of military training, just as Baden-Powell’s scout movement
was an attempt to prepare youth for the kind of guerrilla tactics, living off
the land, seen in the Boer War (and which the Boers had been so much better
at.) In 1879, a few years after the humiliating defeat of France by Germany, the president of the
recently founded French Alpine Club expressed the hope that it would become a
school of physical energy and moral vigour, to make young Frenchmen “more virile, more
apt to bear military life, more prepared to face a long conflict without
discouragement.” 45 Physical
exercise was seen as inherently linked to patriotic education. In Germany, the development of gymnastics as a mass
sport by Frederick Jahn was bathed in an atmosphere of nationalistic fervour
(it had been started in Berlin
during the Napoleonic occupation as part of the resistance.) The first festival
of gymnasts from all over Germany
was hailed by newspapers as a “moral victory” for the German
nation. In England
the process by which the various popular sports such as football and boxing
were brought under uniform rules at this time launched a lively debate as to
how much brutality should be allowed in them. The banning of kicking in the
shins in football was considered a particularly wimpish reform. “If you do away
with it,” declared one enthusiast, “you will do away
with all the courage and pluck of the game, and I will be bound to bring over a
load of Frenchmen who could beat you with a week’s practice.” 46 One of the reasons for the breaking away of the Rugby
code and its initial mass popularity was because it allowed such manly acts of
violence. Everywhere the cult of sport was closely linked to development of the
martial virtues.
Readers familiar with Mein
Kampf will recall the echoes of this in Hitler’s long
disquisition on education. He is another proponent of vigorous sports in
boyhood, and for the same reasons as the Victorians. Not only does sport
develop martial virtues, but it stops boys thinking about sex and developing a
precocious sexuality. Hitler does not go on about masturbation as such; but it
lies beneath the surface just as it underlies the late Victorian public school
ethos of cold baths and long daily runs. The peculiar combination of the
Puritan cult of manliness, militarism, and a concern for health and a proper
hygiene of life which animates the Victorian enthusiasm for sport is faithfully
reproduced in the pages of Mein Kampf.
Sport was initially encouraged for factory workers in England as a
way of channelling their energies into something less dangerous than political
agitation. If they were given footballs to kick, it was thought, they would be
less likely to kick policemen. French factory owners thought the same in
encouraging their workers’ interest in rugby: they would put less energy into
union politics. But sport did not always lead to the harmless channelling of
aggressions which it was intended to. From the start it aroused crowd passions
and hostilities that sometimes turned violent. In 1913, a rugby match in Paris
between France and Scotland led the French crowd to invade the pitch after the
game to try to attack the English referee, accused (improbably) of favouring
Scotland.47 The sort of nationalist passion aroused by sport was
deliberately encouraged and incited as the military competition between nations
grew. Famous sportsmen became publicists for national bellicosity. The great
cyclist Henri Degrange, originator of the Tour
de France and editor of a popular sports magazine L’Auto, exhorted his readers like a coach on the
outbreak of war in 1914. “Mes p’tits gars français! Listen
to me! … The Prussians are a bunch of bastards! …. This is the big
match that you have to play and you must use every trick that you’ve learned in
sport. When your bayonet is at their heart and they beg for mercy, don’t give in. Run
them through!” 48 This might
strike us as a curious lesson to have learned from sport, especially a sport
like cycling. But the passage illustrates extraordinarily clearly the close
link between the spirit of sport and martial ardour during the period of
militarist hysteria.
The decades before the Great War saw the development of a
popular enthusiasm for manly sports as a preparation for war that seemed to
call for the cataclysm to occur which eventually did. Roosevelt’s conviction that
“a nation that has trained itself to a cancer of unwarlike and isolated
ease, is bound in the end to go down before other nations that have not lost
the manly and adventurous virtues” is echoed everywhere. 49
The Spanish political philosopher Juan Donoso-Cortes had expressed the same
idea in the middle of the 19th century:
When a nation shows a
civilized horror of war, it receives directly the punishment of its mistake.
God changes its sex, despoils it of its common mark of virility, changes it
into a feminine nation, and sends conquerors to ravish it of its honour. 50
The Prussian strategist
General Von Moltke thought war was divinely ordained: “Perpetual peace
is a dream – and not even a beautiful dream – and war is an
integral part of God’s ordering of the universe.” 51 The Swiss historian Jakob Burckhardt saw war as essential to
psychological health: “Lasting peace permits the rise of a mass of
precarious, fear-ridden, distressful lives which….. degrade the
nation’s blood. War restores real ability to honour.” 52 The Irish revolutionary poet Patrick Pearse saw bloodshed as not
only healthy but holy: “Bloodshed is a cleansing and a sanctifying thing,
and the nation which regards it as a final horror has lost its manhood.” He later hailed
the First World War as providing a wonderful renewal of Western manhood. 53
Filippo Marinetti’s “Futurist Manifesto”of 1909, the
foundation of modern art, shows how deeply these feelings underlay the new
artistic movement that was to give us abstractionism, the glorification of the
machine, and the contempt for all ideas of feminine prettiness and love of
nature.
We are out to glorify war:
The only health-giver of the
world!
Militarism! Patriotism!
The Destructive Arm of the
Anarchist!
Ideas that kill!
Contempt for women! 54
The association of this
militarist urge for violence with the revolutionary anarchist urge is
significant: the same impulse of destruction runs through both. And underlying
it is a contempt for women as embodying a set of soft, sentimental, pacifist
values which are despised as weakness. It has sometimes been argued that the
fear of the rising women’s movements may have been a major cause of this
belligerent spirit. But the quotations from Donoso-Cortes and Von Moltke
predate any such movements, which became militant only late in the century. The
cult of war in the period does not seem to have been caused by the women’s movements,
though it may have been reinforced by them as the century advanced. In
individual cases men’s fear of increasing female independence and
strength of character may have played a role in a certain misogyny, shown for
example in a writer like Strindberg. But the constant theme of the advocates of
war at that time is the contempt for the new lifestyle of peace, security,
comfort and prosperity of the new bourgeois order, which meant that a man never
had to strike a blow in anger from cradle to grave. There was a curious fear
that men in such an era of peace and comfort were no longer capable of war – as if they had
lost the primitive vigour necessary. They had lost an essential part of their
identity and vitality as men. War was a return to something healthy, natural,
liberating and almost holy. Mussolini summed up this new, philosophical and
aesthetic conception of war as a force for regeneration, for enabling man to
surpass himself:
War alone keys up the
energies of man to their greatest pitch and sets the mark of nobility on those
nations which have the bravery to face it. 55
It is clear that fascism and
Nazism derive directly from this cult of war, which built up to fever pitch at
the turn of the century. The philosophical glorification of war in the fascist
movement was not a new departure. For fifty years politicians, writers and
journalists had in fact been pushing war as an ideal, as the very basis of
life. This was not mere vulgar demagoguery. The most respected thinkers of the
age expressed the same thing, in their elaborate intellectual theories, both of
life and of human history. It is inconceivable that popular enthusiasm for war
and aggression would have reached anything like the levels it did if it had not
been sanctioned and glorified by the leading philosophers of the age. The
intellectual food provided for all educated minds as they grew up at the end of
the 19th century was heavily larded with blood-red doctrines of war
and conflict. Popular jingoism excited by some remote colonial skirmish between
the great powers readily referred for support to the reigning philosophies of
force and struggle. These intellectual justifications for aggression are
crucial to everything that came after. The most important are the ideologies of
Darwinism and Marxism. It is to an examination of these two major systems of
thought, the chief intellectual underpinning of the cult of war and violence in
the hundred years that followed them, that we must now turn.
CHAPTER
FIVE : THE IDEOLOGICAL UNDERPINNINGS OF AGGRESSION
1) DARWIN, MARX & THE BRUTALISATION OF
SOCIAL THOUGHT
There can be no
greater contrast between the generally accepted view of man, life and nature at
the height of the eighteenth century and that prevalent at the end of the
nineteenth. Let us remind ourselves of the dominant eighteenth century view, in
Pope’s celebrated formulation in the Essay
on Man of 1734:
Above, how high, progressive
life may go!
Around how wide! How deep
extend below!
Vast chain of Being! which
from God began,
Natures ethereal, human,
angel, man,
Beast, bird, fish, insect,
what no eye can see
No glass can reach, from
Infinite to thee..…
All are but parts of one
stupendous whole,
Whose body nature is, and
God the soul.
Look round our world: behold
the chain of Love
Combining all below and all
above. 1
Within a hundred and thirty
years, these lines had come to sound naive and sentimental in the extreme. A
natural world of harmony, where each creature had its place, related to others
by attraction and interdependence, had been replaced by a world of perpetual
struggle, the savage war for existence of each against all. Nature as a wise,
benevolent and nurturing mother had been replaced by a savage process of
extermination of the unfit (“Nature red in tooth and claw”), a process
which some did not hesitate to recommend should be applied equally to human
beings. A stable, optimistic view of man’s history as a gradual
progression of knowledge and prosperity had been replaced by a vision of
ceaseless conflict, both of classes and of nations. The only encouraging
perspective was, for the conservative, the gradual extension by war and
conquest of the dominion of the most civilized races over all the others. For
the radical, the only source of hope was the imminence of a cataclysmic
revolution and the extermination of the ruling class. In this change of mood
the key ideas that became dominant in the thinking of the late nineteenth
century were those that would be acted out physically in the catastrophic
twentieth century: struggle, aggression, conflict, revolution, extermination,
total war.
Why these ideas
became so influential in the nineteenth century is at first sight puzzling. The
change in society was by no means all in the direction of more brutal values.
Over the same period, between the mid-eighteenth and late nineteenth centuries,
there was a humanitarian movement in England
and France
which put an end to slavery, torture and gruesomely cruel public executions,
three of the horrors that had been practised by almost every nation on earth
since time immemorial. Under the lead of these two European powers these
practices fell into disrepute as “uncivilized” and were soon
abolished in many other parts of the world where they had some influence. The
new Enlightenment rationalism, as well as the great movement of sensibility and
sentimentality, which began in the eighteenth century, continued to have its
effect in a reforming movement to improve (however gradually) the conditions of
the mentally ill, the sick, the war wounded, prisoners, the destitute, working
children, working women, and finally all workers. But this movement of
humanitarian concern was increasingly swimming against a new ideological tide
that carried a harsher and more brutal message. It was perhaps the great social
and political events themselves that led to a new climate of conflict and
violence, and a deepening conviction that these phenomena lay at the heart of
human history and of all life.
The industrial
revolution had uprooted populations from the countryside and crowded them into
insalubrious urban slums, and into “dark satanic mills” where they
worked in appalling conditions. On the continent the French revolution
unleashed a storm of violence and bloody excesses which finally disgusted many
of its early supporters. The mass executions and the atrocious civil war in the
Vendée were followed by the gargantuan violence of the Napoleonic wars, which
featured larger armies and bloodier battles than had ever been seen before – and which
conscripted whole populations for slaughter for the first time in history. The
peace, which was also the restoration of the old order, brought little but
social agitation by the wretched, cruelly exploited factory workers. Great mass
movements like Chartism, with huge demonstrations demanding democratic
political reforms, evoked the spectre of revolutionary anarchy all over again.
The development of railways and other technological changes appeared to be
driving humanity into an uncertain future at speeds never seen before. All of
these upheavals rendered the old, static view of the world obsolete. There was
a general sense of confusion amid undirected change, expressed on the continent
in a series of further attempts at revolution, culminating in that of 1848.
What exactly society was or should be moving towards became a subject of
violent and acrimonious debate. Social prophets like Carlyle, who claimed to be
able to see where things were going, attracted a devoted following as moral pilots
amid the tempest of the age, but he himself cultivated a polemical and
vituperative style that added to the climate of extremism. Thus the eruption of
conflict and turmoil in society itself was perhaps the main reason that
conflict and struggle became the central themes of nineteenth century thought.
The rise of the concepts of violence and conflict as a total vision of
existence reached its apogee in the works of Karl Marx and Charles Darwin. Both
of them formulated theories that placed violence at the very centre of life – theories that
were then used to justify the most horrific, insane orgies of killing of the
twentieth century.
2) DARWIN’S INFLUENCE
While Marx
influenced 20th century history more than any other human being, Darwin probably influenced
the 20th century’s view of the world more than anyone else. His
legacy is more fiercely defended by his disciples today than that of any
thinker since the first challenges to the authority of Aristotle. His influence
has not only pervaded the fields of biology, zoology and palaeontology, but has
also been felt in such domains as anthropology, sociology, history, politics,
economics and philosophy. His theory of evolution became the paramount
ideological influence of the end of the nineteenth century. The dominant
English philosopher of the age, Herbert Spencer, made it central to his whole
world view – though much of his work pre-dated Darwin’s opus, since Darwin was merely giving a scientific shape
and solidity to a vision of life common to the age. Captains of industry and
apostles of free market competition like Andrew Carnegie and Rockefeller saw
Spencer and Darwin as their ideological justification. Nietzsche, arguably the
greatest philosopher of the century, filled his work with Darwinian images of
struggle and elimination of the weak, and at a deeper level redefined morality
itself as merely a social survival mechanism. Novelists like Zola and Jack
London explored both biological determinism and the theme of the struggle for
survival. German nationalists enlisted Darwinism in the elaboration of a new
ideology of national struggle for a place in the sun. Hitler’s entire theory
of lebensraum and the right of the
stronger races to expand their territory by force was based on Darwinism, as
was his belief in man’s duty to imitate nature’s ruthless
elimination of inferior specimens. Marx was a fervent admirer of Darwin and sent him a
copy of Das Kapital. So widely was Darwin’s influence felt
that for more than half a century after he wrote, Darwinism may be said to have
been the ideology of the age.
Curiously, this
widespread intellectual embrace of Darwinism as an ideology was not accompanied
at first by general acceptance in Darwin’s own scientific
field of the mechanism of natural selection, which was his main contribution to
evolutionary theory. Many biologists remained sceptical of his theory because
it could not explain a certain number of difficulties, such as how new species
could actually be formed from the micro-variations within species. The degree
of variability and the extent of
modification possible through selective breeding always hit a natural barrier,
beyond which the species became sterile or reverted to type. But in the
twentieth century new theories of genetic mutation saved the day, and in the
thirties and forties a new updated version of Darwinism was produced in America:
the Synthetic Evolutionary Theory, usually referred to as neo-Darwinism. Since
then this theory has dominated the life
sciences and enjoyed all the status of established fact. In addition a new
biological determinism based on the natural instincts of aggression and
territoriality found in our ape ancestors, and the inherent egotism made
necessary by the struggle to survive, put the notion of natural selection back
at the centre of studies of human behaviour. Today such diverse debates as
those over gender roles, the origin of an ethical sense, the function of
selfishness, or the economic ideology of the globalized free market, are all
conducted in the shadow of Darwin.
Darwin’s influence on
human thought (beyond his influence on evolutionary theory as a specialist
domain) was twofold. The first was philosophical. In giving scientific weight
and respectability to the subversive hypothesis of man’s descent from
the ape, he broke down the frontier that had hitherto been thought to exist
between human and animal. This was a crippling blow to established religion, to
the notion of divine revelation, to Christianity as a world-view and the Church
as a dominant social institution. It precipitated not only the decline of
revealed religion, seen increasingly as unscientific, but also the decline of
belief in a humanity-centred universe, already under attack since Copernicus.
Man was not a separate creation made in God’s image. He did not have a
divine origin, nor did he have a divinely inspired (or revealed) spiritual
sense of what is right. But if religion was no longer to be the basis for human
morality and man’s sense of his purpose in life, then what was?
Darwinism therefore
very quickly developed a second influence: on ethics. Increasingly, animal behaviour came to be
seen as a template for what was natural and normal conduct in man. The Church
had of course feared precisely this result: belief in man’s essentially animal
nature would lead to a general bestialization of man and the collapse of all
morality – which was why the Church resisted the theory of
evolution for so long. Modern academics tend to ridicule these fears as
obscurantist, anti-scientific thinking. Evocation of the conflict of the
Victorian church with Darwinism tends towards the comic, as in the story of the
bishop’s wife who remarked, hearing of man’s descent from
the ape: “Let us pray it is not true, and if it is, let us
hope it does not become generally known.” But the collapse of
morality feared by the Church (and by Darwin’s old Cambridge Proctor,
Sedgwick) did in fact happen – in the adoption of Darwinian ethics by the Nazis.2
Everything that the Church had feared from the dethronement of a divinely
revealed moral law and the substitution of the jungle law of the strongest did
in fact come true in places like Auschwitz. We have not sufficiently recognized
(it is a subject of some embarrassment to academics) the extent to which Hitler
was essentially a Darwinist – minus the restraining scruples of a Victorian
gentleman of liberal background who had trained to be a vicar. The ethics of
Hitler are what Darwinism logically leads to, unless counteracted by a
humanistic moral code, which is essentially a hangover from the Christian
world-view that Darwin
did so much to destroy.
The ethical
influence of Darwinism lies of course in the glorification of struggle,
competition and violence as necessary principles of life. Darwin’s theory of natural
selection, the mechanism he proposed for evolution, requires a ferocious state
of war in nature for the selection of the “fittest” to operate. To
resume his theory briefly: nature acts like a stock-breeder, selecting those
minor variations among individuals which will give them an advantage in the
struggle for life, and eliminating those that don’t have these
superior characteristics, since they will either die or breed less. From the
changes accumulated by this constant selection of the fittest, species evolve.
But in order for the unfit to be eliminated, there must be an extremely brutal
struggle, with very high casualties, so that quite tiny differences among
individuals will decide between survival and death. Now if this state of
ferocious competition is the necessary condition for evolution, then it must be
considered something good rather than bad. His theory gave comfort first of all
to ruthless free-market capitalism, with its philosophy of “the weak to the
wall.” The link between the two is the so-called Social Darwinist philosophy
of Herbert Spencer, which saw an element of cruelty and heartlessness towards
the poor and weak as ordained by the stern laws of evolutionary necessity. The
children of the poor and shiftless, argued Spencer, should be left to die to rid
the species of a failed line.3 Capitalist free-marketeers, deploring
the state’s intervention to defend the weak and poor from the
exploitation and starvation they so richly deserved, rejoiced in this
vindication of heartlessness by science and philosophy. But it was a small step
from here to believing that not only ruthless economic competition but also war
is a beneficial and necessary process. War after all eliminates the weaker
individuals and strengthens the race, and also leads the stronger races to
prevail over and exterminate the weaker, thus strengthening the whole species.
This was the step the Nazis took, but it was wholly within the logic of
Darwinism. Darwin
looked with favour on the expansion of the British race throughout the world in
his time, displacing backward peoples, as part of the process by which “the stronger” were “always
extirpating the weaker.” At the end of his life he speculated on the
probable future extermination of many inferior and backward races as a
necessary part of human progress. 4 His thinking is in no way
contrary to the spirit of Nazism. It forms an important part of the upsurge of
aggression and martial spirit that was to lead to the imperialism of the last
decades of the nineteenth century as well as the European rivalries that were
to bring on the Great War.
It is in the four
decades following the publication of The
Origin of Species that Europe manifested
its most expansionist and aggressive drive. It is not unreasonable to see
Darwinian thinking as partly responsible for the change in attitude towards
colonial expansion that took place during these years. In 1840 Britain had acquired New Zealand with great reluctance,
and only to forestall the French. Colonies were thought to be largely a burden,
unless they were seen as rich in some tangible way, as India was with
its precious stones. Securing trading privileges by force (as in China) was one
thing. Ruling over more peoples was quite another. Whitehall deliberately hung back from any
African adventures. Africa, with its Arab-run
slave trade (now that the Europeans had given it up) and the desperate anarchy
of its tribal wars, was a can of worms the British government didn’t wish to open,
despite the humanitarian pleadings of the missionary lobby. By the 1880’s this had
changed, and the colonial grab for Africa was
on. In between came a wave of Malthusian enthusiasm for sending the paupers and
failures of England
out to the new colonies, where they would be transformed into more vigorous
specimens. Darwin
shared this enthusiasm. Although he had seen during his voyage on the Beagle the destructive effects of
colonialism on the natives, he believed colonial warfare was necessary to “make the
destroyers vary” and adapt to the new terrain. 5 But
there was also a new notion of the
responsibility of Europeans as a kind of vanguard of human progress to
take charge of the development of more backward peoples by ruling over them – what Kipling
called “the white man’s burden.” Darwinism, by
bolstering both the justifications for aggression and the notions of racial
evolution, seems to have played a large part in the change of attitudes to
imperialism, and the new consensus on the destiny of advanced peoples to rule
over less evolved ones.
Now Hitler (to
anticipate on our argument a little) simply adapted the notions of advanced and
backward races to the European scene of his youth. He grew up in the
melting-pot of the Austro-Hungarian empire, where ethnic Germans like himself
were being squeezed out of their rightful, dominant position by “inferior” Slavs and Jews.
The restoration of German supremacy over these peoples was to him the
restoration of the natural rule of the stronger and more advanced over the
weaker but more numerous. His notion of the racial competition for living-space
is pure Darwinism. The glorification of war as a purifying struggle which will
eliminate the unfit on all sides is also pure Darwinism. Hitler drew the crude
ethical conclusions from Darwin:
if the survival of the stronger is natural law, and there is no divine law,
then the strong have the right and even the duty to eliminate the weak. It is
part of man’s duty towards the human species to ensure that the
strongest and most intelligent races prevail. In order to optimize human
evolutionary progress, the struggle to survive must lead strong, intelligent
races to drive out or exterminate the backward, inferior races and propagate in
their place. Hitlerism is Darwinism applied literally and crudely, shorn of the
humane scruples of a Victorian liberal. As with the application of Marx’s theory by
Lenin, it is a good example of the violence of thought of the nineteenth
century being translated into the violence of action of the twentieth.
A related current
of ethical thinking that emerges from Darwinism and leads directly to Nazism is
eugenics, the attempt to breed a better race. Eugenicists (including Darwin’s son) saw
themselves as merely applying Darwinian theory in practice. Why not try to
breed a better race, and eliminate the unfit, as Darwin suggested in The Descent of Man, where he deplored the effects of modern
medicine and welfare provisions in saving the maladapted. 6 But
Darwin himself was always hesitant about the means to employ. He tended to
favour voluntary action. He felt that “both sexes ought to refrain
from marriage if they are in any marked degree inferior in body or mind,” though he
considered this hope Utopian. 7 Yet sometimes he seems more
impatient with voluntary means, as when he remarks tartly that “excepting in the
case of man himself, hardly anyone is so ignorant as to allow his worst animals
to breed.” 8 We often see Darwin struggling to
square the totalitarian implications of his theory with his own liberal
instincts. The Nazis were unencumbered with these problems of liberal conscience.
Himmler’s attempt to breed a super-race in the Lebensborn project is a direct
descendant of the neo-Darwinist eugenicists, and would probably have earned
their applause. Only his criteria of selection of ideal breeding couples might
have led to some debate.
Now modern
scientists, especially those apparently unfamiliar with all of Darwin’s writings, like
to claim that all this is merely a misapplication of Darwin’s scientific theories to
human societies by ignorant non-scientists. But this neat separation cannot be
made. The application of these ideas to man is central to Darwinism. It is the
very core of Darwin’s thought and is made very explicit in works like The Descent of Man. Darwin is an
ideologist as much as a scientific thinker. The academic categories that today
tend to separate the natural scientist from the social thinker did not exist in
the nineteenth century. It is essential to understand that for Darwin in particular the separation of human
society and the animal world was quite unthinkable. The theory that applied to
one must apply to the other, because both obey the same laws. It seems an
obvious point to labour, but it is one that Darwin’s modern disciples don’t appear to
grasp, or prefer to hide their eyes from. This is after all a thinker whose
central revolutionary idea (in the eyes of his age) was that man is only
another animal.
3)
DARWINISM AS AN IDEOLOGY
Darwin put together his
ideas during a period of intellectual, political and ideological strife of rare
intensity and passion. Never has a scientific theory been put forward in
circumstances which drew it more inevitably into the maelstrom of a fierce
ideological debate. For in the context of the times views of nature and the
universe were intimately linked with views both of God and of society. The
various currents of political and religious thought aligned themselves with
philosophies of nature as if the latter were merely extensions of competing
ideologies. The conventional, orthodox view of nature – the lineal
descendant of Alexander Pope’s Chain of Being or Chain of Love – was the
comfortable sentimental vision of the Reverend W. Paley. His great work, Natural Theology, was a sort of defence
of the present world order, not merely of nature, but of society also. Darwin’s biographers
describe this vision in lyrical terms:
Here was a
beautiful evocation of life abounding with goodness and joy: “it is a happy
world, teeming with delighted existence,” Paley enthused. “In a spring noon
or a summer evening whichever side I turn my eyes, myriads of happy beings
crowd upon my view.” Life was a summer’s teatime on the
vicarage lawn, with swarming bees and cheerful beetles testifying to God’s kindness. It was good, life was happy, because all beings were adapted to their surroundings.
Animals, including humans, are complex mechanisms from the divine workshop, and
exquisitely fitted to their places in the world. They are so obviously
designed, there has to be a Designer. 9
In other words
Paley’s complacent view of nature as a pretty scene of harmony and perfectly
adapted happiness was part of his argument for the design of the universe to
prove the existence of a bountiful God. This whole orthodox world-view was
already under attack in the early nineteenth century. The currents of social
reform and revolution coalescing around the Chartist movement of the 1830’s, which were
violently discontented with the present world order, saw Paley as the
ideological enemy. They were implicitly or explicitly atheistic because they
could not believe that a benevolent God could create so much human and animal
misery. George Holyoake, a political agitator whose two-year old daughter died
of malnutrition while he was in prison, wrote a bitter atheistic pamphlet
entitled Paley Refuted in His Own Words.
The working class printer William Chilton and his colleagues on the
revolutionary penny paper The Oracle of
Reason ridiculed Paley’s “happy nature” as a pernicious way of
justifying the status quo. Chilton’s own Nature had satanic
overtones: it was positive proof of God’s non-existence. If God had
existed he would have planned “less suffering and more enjoyment, less hypocrisy
and more sincerity, fewer rapes, frauds, pious and impious butcheries.” 10 The denial of God and of a benevolent nature was a means of denying
the goodness and rightness of the present social order – the two were inseparable.
And the authorities recognized the link when they tried and imprisoned a
succession of Oracle editors for
blasphemy, which was a useful substitute for a political charge of sedition.
More
worryingly for Darwin,
Chilton had put forward a sort of revolutionary version of Lamarck’s early theory of
evolution. Chilton posited a universal adaptive, progressive force that was
pushing nature and society toward a higher, brighter and more co-operative
future out of the present darkness and misery. The radical movements were thus
adopting not only materialistic atheism but also evolutionary thought as a new
ideological weapon against the old order. Darwin, who had already formulated
the essence of his theory by the 1840’s, hung back from publishing
it largely because he feared being lumped in with this new revolutionary
atheism. He was afraid that the socialist camp would exploit his work – linking man and the apes
and exposing nature’s brutal methods
– to their own advantage against the class and social
order to which Darwin
owed allegiance. Darwin
feared that he himself, a man who had trained for the Church, would be cast out
by the establishment as a traitor for providing grist to the revolutionary
mill. Darwin had already seen the vindictive
treatment meted out to his atheistic, evolutionist tutor at Edinburgh University,
Robert Grant – exclusion from the Royal Society and general
academic blackballing. The whiff of brimstone around these views is the main
reason that Darwin
agonized so long about publishing. He waited till the social agitation around
Chartism had died down, and these ideas had made more headway in respectable
scientific circles. Then he felt forced to publish his theory to avoid being
beaten to it by others, notably Wallace. It is in this light that we can
understand Karl Marx’s admiration for Darwin (though the story
of Marx’s offer to dedicate Capital to him is an error resulting from a confusion over authorship
of a letter.) Darwin’s portrayal of
the violence and murderous ruthlessness of nature was indeed seen by the
socialist camp as ammunition against the established social order and its
complacent view of the universe. But the revolutionaries’ support
embarrassed Darwin,
because he did not at all share their views.
In fact Darwin’s social views
were largely shaped by a more moderate current of reformist thought in which
his own family had for a long time been immersed. His grandfather, Erasmus Darwin,
was a freethinking poet and physician of the old Enlightenment school, an
atheist who worshipped at the shrine of reason and put forward his own version
of the evolution of all life forms:
Nursed by warm sun-beams in
primeval caves
Organic Life began beneath
the waves. 11
He was a philanthropist, a
supporter of the French revolution, opponent of slavery, and enthusiastic
womanizer, who sired several bastards and brought them all up together with the
children of his broad-minded second wife, the illegitimate daughter of an earl.
Darwin’s other
grandfather, the pottery magnate Josiah Wedgewood, was a Unitarian. These were
radical reforming Christians who had stripped Christianity of its
mysticism – the Trinity, the
divinity of Christ, the immortal soul – and saw it in material
terms as a moral code teaching the way to live and reach happiness in this
world. God’s benevolence was expressed through natural laws,
and science was the only true knowledge. Darwin’s father Robert
was another free-thinking doctor, even though the steady rise in the family
fortunes made him conceal his opinions and pay lip-service to the established
Church, source of all social privilege. Charles Darwin was destined for a
medical career himself, and spent two years studying medicine at Edinburgh University. Here he came under the
influence, as we have seen, of the Lamarckian evolutionist and atheistic
radical, Robert Grant. However, Darwin’s aversion to
blood and the horrors of surgery without anaesthetic led to a change of career
plan and his father sent him to Cambridge
to study theology. Despite his own religious scepticism, Robert Darwin viewed
the Church as a convenient outlet for idle sons. He saw an appointment to a
country vicarage as just the sort of sinecure that would allow Charles to do
all the botanizing and insect-collecting he felt inclined to. The offer to join
the Beagle on a voyage round the
world (to provide its depressive captain with intelligent conversation)
intervened at just the right moment and gave Darwin’s botanical obsessions an
unexpected boost. What he observed on the Galapagos islands in particular
provided concrete evidence, he thought, for the “transmutationist” (or
evolutionist) view, which had been wildly theorized about for years in hotbeds
of radical thought like Edinburgh
University. The variant
species of finches on each island seemed to him convincing proof of a common
ancestor, and an evolutionary divergence based on the differing needs imposed
by different environments.
In short, Darwin grew up in a class
and an intellectual milieu that was socially liberal, freethinking on religion,
and inclined towards evolutionary explanations of life, which reflected its own
upward mobility. His achievement was to give these evolutionary ideas a respectability
and a scientific weight that they had previously lacked. But it was also
important to cleanse these ideas of their socially subversive stigma, their
revolutionary associations, and anchor them firmly in middle-class thinking.
Only in this way could they replace the established orthodoxy and form a new
stable world-picture, instead of being suppressed as they had been until then
for political and moral reasons. Darwin’s originality lay
in providing a precise mechanism (natural selection) and copiously detailed
evidence (as it was thought to be) for an evolutionary idea that was not in
itself new. It was an idea central to the ideology of the rising middle
classes, which badly needed to have their world-view established as legitimate
and dominant.
The association of political liberalism with evolutionist
thinking about the universe was quite explicit in the various Unitarian writers
that the young divinity student became familiar with. One of the leading
Unitarian divines, Dr Southwood Smith, put forward a vision of Nature as
striving upwards towards ever-higher organisms, and drew the explicit inference
for society and class mobility: “All reasonable beings,
however inferior the condition in which they commence their existence, are
destined to rise higher and higher in endless progression, and to contribute to
their own advancement.” 12 This milieu of middle-class reformers was eager to see more
freedom, more individualism, the breaking down of class barriers and
intellectual and religious censorship, the ending of the Established Church,
freedom of science as well as economic freedom, and a mobile society in which
every man could fulfil his own individual potential. It is no surprise that the
vision of nature that prevailed in this milieu exactly mirrored the vision of
society they sought to bring about. But Darwin
added a new dimension: the mechanism he put forward for evolution was the
constant struggle for existence which had been posited by Malthus in his
theories on population. It is this savage struggle for existence which acted as
the selective force, eliminating the unfit and preserving the fit, thus
bringing about the constant small modifications in the species which was the
process of evolution. The somewhat idealistic and benign picture of evolution
painted by the liberal Unitarian divines was thus given a far more ruthless and
brutal aspect by Darwin, who took full account of the cruelty of the process.
It was the combination of hitherto benign evolutionary thinking and the cult of
ruthless struggle which gave Darwinism its peculiar character.
One of the ways in which Darwin’s view of nature differs
from Chilton’s atheistic,
revolutionary view is that it lacks the sense of horror and moral protest against the universe’s cruelty. For
the revolutionaries protested equally against society’s cruelty and
nature’s. They were atheists out of indignant revulsion
from the world God had supposedly made. A callous universe was seen as underpinning a wicked
social order. Now Darwin’s view is neither
Paley’s complacency nor Chilton’s revolt, but something in
between. What distinguishes Darwinism from Chiltonism is its calm acceptance of
nature’s most brutal processes, and its scientific
conviction that this all serves the higher purposes of the universe. And what
distinguishes it from Paley is that a theological and sentimental optimism
which hides its eyes from the cruelties of the universe is replaced by a stern
scientific optimism, which takes those cruelties in its stride – as though the
sufferings of sentient beings were of no great importance in the context of the
great evolutionary process.
It is clear then
that we have in the middle of the nineteenth century three views of nature,
corresponding to the three social classes and ideologies in conflict: a view of
nature as benevolent and good (Paley and the old establishment of church and
landed gentry); a view of nature as brutal and therefore evil (Chilton and the
revolutionary workers); and a view of nature as brutal but fundamentally good
(Darwin and the rising capitalist class.) This scheme might seem a little too
neat, but it explains the alignment of the old established order with
conventional Christianity, the revolutionary workers with pessimistic atheism,
and the Darwinian capitalists with a quasi-agnostic (one might almost say
radical Unitarian) view of the universe as good and progressive, but using
ruthless means to attain its evolutionary ends. One can see how the Darwinian
view, which was also that of Herbert Spencer, appealed so deeply to Andrew
Carnegie and other captains of industry in the United States. It was a way of
defending ruthlessness – of seeing ruthlessness as at the very heart of
nature, but seeing it as good. Hitherto nature’s ruthlessness
had either been denied, as it was by Paley, or it had been denounced as a moral
indictment of the whole universe and a proof there was no God – as it was by
Chilton. What was perhaps most shocking about Darwinism for many contemporaries
was this defence and even glorification of the ruthlessness of the universe. In
a sense, it was a novel way of solving the problem of evil: what looks evil isn’t evil, it is
good. But whereas Paley, like the
eighteenth century deists and like Alexander Pope, were led to downplay the
cruelty of the universe, to deny its intensity and extent, Darwin believed in
facing all the brutality and violence squarely, almost revelling in it, but
with a confident if harsh faith that it is all serving the basically benign
goals of nature.
As Darwin
reflected on the fate of his own ten children, of whom two had died very young
and his beloved Annie at the age of nine, he reassured himself by noting that
the survivors were the more “vigorous & healthy & can most enjoy life.” 13 One can see this as courageous or as callous, or as pathetically
self-deceiving, depending on one’s viewpoint. One might
almost see the moral perspective of Darwinism as a sort of stoic acceptance of
the harshness of existence without complaint but without complacency. He is at
pains to destroy any illusions any followers of Paley might still cling to. The
true visage of the parsonage garden, seen through Darwinian and Malthusian
eyes, was a battlefield. He conceded that “One may well doubt this” when viewing “the contented
face of a bright landscape or a tropical forest glowing with life,”
…& at such
periods most of the inhabitants are probably living with no great danger
hanging over them & often with a super-abundance of food. Nevertheless the
doctrine that all nature is at war is most true. The struggle very often falls
on the egg & seed, or on the seedling, larva and young; but fall it must
sometime in the life of each individual, or more commonly at intervals on
successive generations & then with extreme severity. 14
There is almost a determination
here to dash hopes and illusions. One senses here a mission to demonstrate that
the truth of the universe is cruel and harsh and is not for faint hearts or
sentimental softies. As Darwin’s Christian faith melts away
before such tragedies as Annie’s death, it is replaced by a sterner worship of a
far harsher God, not unlike the one Hitler repeatedly refers to as “the harsh goddess
Nature.” It has a
strong part of disillusionment that God is not the nice being one had been
brought up to think, but it contains also a masochistic determination neither
to dwell in a state of pointless denial of the facts nor to persist in an
attitude of pointless protest against what cannot be changed. This is the
perspective of a man who has been hurt and is determined that others shall not
be allowed to hide their faces from the cause of this hurt. It is what the
nineteenth century invented instead of a sense of tragedy: a rubbing of noses in unpleasant facts and a
scoffing at those who can’t take them. It is not far from the ethos of the
public school bully, gleefully thrashing a new boy to show him what the system
is really like.
There was a good
deal of determination in the circle around Darwin, notably in Thomas Huxley, to smash an
establishment world-view which they considered both obscurantist and hiding
from unpleasant facts. The year before The
Origin of Species was published, Huxley made an attack on the reigning
establishment anatomist, Richard Owen, for his argument that man constituted a
special sub-class, separate from the apes. The discovery of the gorilla in Africa had excited the British popular imagination. Owen
had been asked by worried divines to provide some refutation of dangerous
speculations (notably by Chilton) that man was descended from this newly
discovered primate. Owen obliged, and claimed that various organs of man’s brain made him
utterly unique, and further apart from the gorilla than the latter was from a
platypus. Huxley in a lecture in March 1858 savaged this view and argued on the
contrary that the baboon, gorilla and man stood in a steady evolutionary line,
equally far apart. The idea of man’s descent from the ape was
thus already a subject of open and violent debate before Darwin’s opus was published. It was
to Darwin that
the Young Turks looked to provide a thorough-going scientific defence of the
concept (and above all of the underlying notion of the “transmutation of
species”) which would convince the serious scientific
establishment. This was a scientific battle which formed part and parcel of a
wider ideological battle. The issue was not so much the presentation of an
original idea, as its presentation in such a methodical, scientific way that
its dismissal would no longer be possible. As often in science, the issue was
not the truth of an idea, but its acceptability.
But Darwin’s work was widely
seen not merely as giving crucial support to Huxley’s subversive,
anti-religious view of the descent of man from the ape. It was seen just as
importantly as giving support to the Malthusian vision of the struggle to
survive in a world of limited resources, the vision of ruthless competition as
the law of life – what is now
often referred to as Social Darwinism.
The social aspect of evolutionary theory – the “survival of the fittest” as applied to
human beings – had been developed shortly before Darwin published The Origin of Species, by
a thinker moving in the same ideological currents, Herbert Spencer. Spencer’s ideas had made
such a splash that Darwin
was at first seen as merely following in his wake with more scientific
evidence. It is worth looking at how their arguments intermesh.
4)
SPENCER AND THE SURVIVAL OF THE FITTEST
Spencer’s first book, Social
Statics, appeared in 1850, nine years before The Origin of Species. It
announced the principles that would later be known as Social Darwinism. “Pervading all nature we may
see at work a stern discipline, which is a little cruel that it may be very
kind.” Spencer declared that the “state of universal warfare
maintained throughout the lower creation, to the great perplexity of many
worthy people, is at bottom the most merciful provision which the circumstances
admit of.” What was at work was a “purifying process” which eliminated
“the sickly, the malformed, and the least fleet or powerful”, ending their
existence before it became a burden and making room for a younger generation.
This process operated among human beings as well. 15
He admitted that it was hard for us to see an incompetent
artisan starve, a sickly labourer sink into misery, widows and orphans
struggling to live. But he was adamant that this was necessary. “When regarded not
separately but in connection with the interests of universal humanity, these
harsh fatalities are seen to be full of beneficence – the same beneficence
which brings to early graves the children of diseased parents, and singles out
the intemperate and the debilitated as the victims of an epidemic.” People who
recoiled from these harsh facts were, in his phrase, “spurious
philanthropists”. 16
Spencer summed up his doctrine in the phrase he coined in
1862, “the survival of the fittest”. Darwin had by then
published The Origin of Species,
which was widely seen as confirming Spencer’s views scientifically. But
it was Spencer who was considered the major thinker of the age. Some
contemporaries did not hesitate to call him the greatest philosopher of all
time. Darwin
warmly admired him. Spencer went on to develop his arguments to justify all the
harshest aspects of laissez-faire economic doctrine. Any intervention by the
state to regulate foreign trade or banking, to improve public housing,
education or sanitary conditions would be self-defeating. Any attempt by the
state to help the poor would inevitably lead to more misery. In opposing state
education he argued that the poor should “get culture for their
children as best they may, just as they are left to get food and clothing for
them,” for in this way the “children of the superior will be advantaged: the
thrifty parents, the energetic, and those with a high sense of responsibility.” 17 It is easy to see why Spencer became the darling of the great
American capitalists like Andrew Carnegie, who promoted Spencer’s visit to the United States.
There were limits, however, even to Spencer’s stomach for cruelty. He
was so horrified by the conditions he saw in one of Carnegie’s factories that
he said they would justify suicide. Towards the end of his life he became
worried by the extremes of callousness and aggressiveness which he himself had
unleashed. In a late essay called “Re-Barbarization” he deplored the
re-emergence of militarism and the imperialistic impulse which he saw in the
Boer War and colonial conquests. Spencer’s qualms of conscience even
pushed him to plead for women’s rights and to attack mindless patriotism. But it
was too late. He had expressed a powerful current in the thinking of the age:
an opposition to humanitarian meddling in the great laws of nature, which were
seen as pitiless to the individual for the greater good of the species.
Whatever second thoughts he had at the end of his life, he was a major source
of the cult of ruthless struggle that came to dominate the world. 18
What Spencer’s social and
ethical system represents is a re-alignment of man’s moral behaviour
to make it conform with the ruthlessness now perceived to characterize the
universe. One cannot emphasize too much how radical this ethical shift is. To
this new way of thinking, pity for the weak, perhaps the most important moral
principle underlying both the Christian ethic and the Medieval aristocratic
ethic of chivalry, becomes a debilitating, cowardly vice, sabotaging Nature’s stern programme
of elimination of the unfit. Darwin himself in The Descent of Man specifically agrees with Spencer, and restates
his arguments even more emphatically. In this book Darwin attacks “civilized men” for
counteracting natural selection:
We civilized men …. do our utmost
to check the process of elimination; we build asylums for the imbecile, the
maimed and the sick; we institute poor laws; and our medical men exert their
utmost skill to save the life of everyone to the last moment….Thus the weak
members of civilized society propagate their kind. No one who has attended to
the breeding of domestic animals will doubt that this must be highly injurious
to the race of men…. Excepting in the case of man himself, hardly
anyone is so ignorant as to allow his worst animals to breed. 19
He concludes his book. “There should be
open competition for all men, and the most able should not be prevented by laws
and customs from succeeding best and rearing the largest number of offspring.” 20 Darwin,
in short, was himself an unapologetic Social Darwinist. He maintained these
views to the end of his life. Talking to William Graham in 1881, he predicted,
looking to the near future, that “an endless number of the
lower races will have been eliminated by the higher civilized races throughout
the world.” 21
These views are
remarkably similar to Hitler’s. Mein Kampf
is filled with passages that would not have been out of place in The Descent of Man. One quote will suffice here:
It is a half-measure to let
incurably sick people steadily contaminate the remaining healthy ones.…..The demand that
defective people be prevented from propagating equally defective offspring is a
demand of the clearest reason and if systematically executed represents the
most humane act of mankind. 22
The extermination of
invalids and the mentally defective was Hitler’ first act of
mass murder in October 1939, when the outbreak of war had finally allowed him
to take the gloves off.
There is a
tendency among modern day disciples of Darwin
to present these unsavoury views as totally irrelevant to his scientific
theories. They see them as a regrettable intellectual eccentricity, reflecting
the views of the age he lived in, rather like Sir Isaac Newton’s lifelong
experiments in communicating with spirits. In fact these views are central to Darwin’s entire theory,
because they formed the inspiration for it. It is Malthus and his views on human
population expansion and the inevitable starvation it would entail which gave Darwin his crucial
insight into nature’s method of selection. His own family circle were
intensely interested in the debate over the new Poor Law of 1834. Malthus was
the chief inspiration of the Whig Party activists who wanted to make it harder
for the poor to breed (notably by separating couples in the workhouse, a sort
of prison for the destitute.) Among these Whig militants was Darwin’s close friend (and his
brother’s fiancée), the literary lioness Harriet Martineau,
who constantly preached Malthus at every dinner table. Darwin dutifully sat down and read the sixth
edition of Malthus’ Essay on the
Principle of Population in 1838, two years after
returning from his Beagle voyage. He
at once saw how Malthus’ theory might solve his own problem of finding the
mechanism of evolution. Here is how he later looked back on it:
In October (1838)
that is fifteen months after I had begun my systematic enquiry, I happened to
read for amusement Malthus on Population,
and being well prepared to appreciate the struggle for existence which
everywhere goes on from long continued observation of the habits of animals and
plants, it struck me that under these circumstances favourable variations would
tend to be preserved and unfavourable ones to be destroyed. The result of this
would be the formation of new species. Here then I had at last got a theory by
which to work. 23
Malthus
calculated that, with the brakes off, humanity would double in numbers in a
mere twenty-five years, rapidly outstripping available food resources. What
prevented it from doing so was disease, wars, famine, and a savage struggle for
resources, and this struggle would intensify as the population rose, leading to
more and more violent and premature deaths. Darwin began to perceive that an identical
savage struggle must occur throughout nature. He had previously thought that
most species had only enough offspring to keep the population stable. Now he
was convinced that wild populations too bred beyond their means, just as man
did. Like the poor in London’s slums or the
armies of scavengers on London’s rubbish heaps,
they had to scrimp and fight and struggle. But what Darwin suddenly saw is that this reduction of
numbers by the state of catastrophe Malthus foresaw would not be random. Those
better adapted to survival would live while the others died out. This selection
by premature death could be the mechanism by which species changed over time,
adapted to new conditions, and eventually evolved into other species. In short,
it was in contemplating Malthus’ theories about mankind that Darwin arrived at his theory of natural
selection: death would play the role of the stock-breeder in selecting and
breeding with only the best individuals. The application of his theory to human
societies is not therefore an irrelevant and unjustified extension of
Darwinism; it is the very core and origin of the theory. Darwin saw no distinction between animal and
human society in this regard. Malthus, he thought, had depicted “the warring of
the species” throughout nature better than anyone else. To quote
Darwin’s biographers:
In society and
nature, paupers and brutes were both struggling, the best alone surviving….. The population
pressure became “a force like a hundred thousand wedges” rammed between
members of a species, “forcing gaps by thrusting out weaker ones.” The best adapted
varieties survive to breed, expanding at the expense of the rest, changing the
whole species slowly. The same “grand crush of population” that shook men
from their indolence kept life at its peak of perfection. 24
Here at last was
the mechanism for selection that Darwin
had sought. He had long had an intuition that evolution must proceed much like
the artificial breeding of dogs or horses or pigeons. Since all individuals,
even from the same litter, vary slightly, a breeder can select certain features which he wants to promote,
and by breeding only the individuals that have those features he gradually
reinforces them and transforms the breed. The problem was to decide what took
the place of the breeder in the state of nature: who or what did the
selecting? Now Darwin had his answer. Malthusian population
pressures, the ruthless struggle for survival with its high mortality rate, was
the selective force. This solved the tricky problem of how in nature the
non-selected were prevented from re-crossing themselves with the selected. The
answer was – they died out.
The competitive edge given by tiny variations was so decisive that only those
with this tiny variation survived (or, in the intense competition, they outbred
the others and left more offspring until they eventually took over the
species.) Here was a vision of nature which fitted in thoroughly with the whole
ethos of the age: it made the crucial link between evolution and ruthless
competition.
Darwin’s biological
initiative matched advanced Whig social thinking. At last he had a mechanism
that was compatible with the competitive free-trading ideals of the ultra-Whigs....
An open struggle with no hand-outs to the losers was the Whig way, and no poor
law commissioner could have bettered Darwin’s view. 25
Moreover, this was a view
which did not decry the cruel and ruthless processes of nature (as had the
radical worker movements of the Chiltons and Holyoakes), but celebrated and
even revelled in them.
He had broken
with the radical hooligans who loathed Malthus. Like the Whig grandees – safe, immune,
their own world characterized by noblesse
oblige – Darwin was living on a
family fortune and thrusting a bitter competition on a starving world for its
own good. From now on he could appeal to a better class of audience – to the rising
industrialists, free-traders, and Dissenting professionals. 26
The social and
human dimension of Darwin’s theory was
therefore the key to it from the beginning. This was a social theory applied to
nature, not a scientific theory applied afterwards (illegitimately or
irrelevantly, some modern followers would say) to society. Darwin
was a Malthusian Whig, a believer in ruthless and untrammelled competition as
the best way towards prosperity, who had the brilliant inspiration of applying
this idea to nature. And in so doing, he made his entire scientific theory part
and parcel of a general hardening of social attitudes towards the poor and the
weak, a cultivation of stern harshness and necessary cruelty, which was to
develop through the most ruthless brands of capitalism and colonialism to reach
its culmination in the ideologies of fascism and Nazism.
Nazism and
fascism are merely a practical application of Darwinism to politics and foreign
policy, to about the same degree that Leninism is a practical application of
Marxism. Nazism simply takes Darwin literally,
unrestrained by any lingering tradition of Christian or humanist morality of
the kind that made Darwin (grandson of a radical anti-slavery campaigner) an
opponent of slavery. Hitler saw life as a ruthless competition between races.
Following this logic, one’s own race, if it is to survive, must combat and
subjugate the others, and eliminate its own weaker specimens in order to
strengthen itself for the struggle. War becomes, in this perspective, the
ultimate fulfilment of our natural urge to survive at others’ expense. War is
the ultimate affirmation of the Darwinian vision of life, and Hitler took the
oft-repeated Darwinian image literally.
Now to see Nazism as a development of Darwinism is not to
suggest that Darwin, if he had been born a
little later and in Germany,
would have joined Hitler’s Nazi party. Ideas give birth to other ideas in a
chain that the original thinker cannot control and is not morally responsible
for. But it is necessary to see where Darwin
leads in order to understand his fundamental importance to twentieth century
thought. Historians have had a tendency to see Hitler’s ideology as an
inexplicable aberration, or to look for its origins in the specific
anti-Semitic and militarist traditions of Germany. But Nazism belongs to one
of the most powerful currents of Western thought that the last two centuries
have produced. Darwinism filtered down in popularized form to pervade the
world-view of an age, and Hitler, growing up in pre-First World War Austria-Hungary,
would have been thoroughly familiar with it. The German evolutionist Haeckel,
one of Darwin’s most enthusiastic admirers, who came to visit him
in England, had combined Darwinism with German nationalism and racism into a
highly popular ideology in the Germanic world. It was a heady mix for a young
man with no qualifications struggling for survival in a decadent empire where
the pure Germans like himself were losing out to the hybridised, inferior Slavs
and Jews, who now made up four-fifths of the population. Here was an ideology
which explained his own personal situation. And here was the direction which
his own survival struggle must take: a mission to awaken the German people to
the need to assert themselves if they were not to perish under the mass of
inferior racial types. Hitler is a disciple of Darwin: Darwinism underlies his entire
philosophy. There is scarcely a general reflection on the human condition in Mein Kampf which is not totally
Darwinian in its perspective. This is the world-view that drove Hitler to make
a cult of war and racial aggression. Hitler’s ideology may be called
Darwinism-Hitlerism, with the same precision that we use the term
Marxism-Leninism. But to convince the sceptical of this idea, it is necessary
to take a closer look at a book which is ritually denounced but seldom actually
read, Mein Kampf.
5) DARWIN AND HITLER
Consider this
passage from Mein Kampf. Hitler is
examining the German over-population problem, due to the reduced borders of the
Versailles
settlement and the lack of resources to feed itself, and is considering what to
do about it. He evokes the Malthusian spectre of mass starvation (Darwin’s own starting
point) and proposes four possible solutions to prevent it.
Following the French example, the
increase in births could be artificially restricted, thus meeting the problem
of overpopulation.
Nature herself in times of great poverty
or bad climatic conditions as well as poor harvest, intervenes to restrict the
increase of population of certain countries and races; this, to be sure, by a
method as wise as it is ruthless. She diminishes not the power of procreation
as such, but the conservation of the procreated, by exposing them to hard
trials and deprivations with the result that all those who are less strong and
less healthy are forced back into the womb of the eternal unknown. Those whom
she permits to survive the inclemency of existence are a thousandfold tested,
hardened, and well adapted to procreate in turn, in order that the process of
thoroughgoing selection may begin again from the beginning. By thus brutally
proceeding against the individual and immediately calling him back to herself
as soon as he shows himself unequal to the storm of life, she keeps the race
and species strong, raises them to the highest accomplishments.
At the same time the diminution of number
strengthens the individual and thus in the last analysis fortifies the species.
It is different however when man
undertakes the limitation of his number. He is not carved of the same wood, he
is “humane”. He knows better than the cruel queen of wisdom. He
limits not the conservation of the individual, but procreation itself. This
seems to him, who always sees himself and never the race, more human and more
justified than the opposite way. Unfortunately, however, the consequences are
the reverse.
While Nature, by making procreation free,
yet submitting survival to a hard trial, chooses from an excess number of
individuals the best as worthy of living, thus preserving them alone and in
them conserving their species, man limits procreation, but is hysterically
concerned that once a being is born it should be preserved at any price. The
correction of the divine will seems to him as wise as it is humane, and he
takes delight at once again having got the better of Nature, and even having
proved her inadequacy. The number, to be sure, has been limited, but at the
same time the quality of the individual has diminished; this, however, is
something the dear little ape of the Almighty does not want to see or hear
about.
For as soon as procreation as such is
limited and the number of births diminished, the natural struggle for existence
which leaves only the strongest and healthiest alive is obviously replaced by
the obvious desire to “save” even the weakest and most sickly at any price, and
this plants the seeds of a future generation which must inevitably grow more
and more deplorable the longer this mockery of Nature and her will
continues.
And the end will be that some day this
people will be deprived of its existence on this earth, for man can defy the
eternal laws of the will to preservation for a certain time, but sooner or
later vengeance comes. A stronger race will drive out the weak, for the vital
urge in its ultimate form will, time and again, burst all the absurd fetters of
the so-called humanity of individuals in order to replace it by the humanity of
Nature which destroys the weak to give his place to the strong. 27
I have used this very lengthy quote to show
Hitler’s perfect mastery of Darwin’s theory of the survival of
the fittest and the process of natural selection. It is, indeed,
absolutely central to the murderous
callousness of Hitler’s thinking. Given the frequency of Darwinian
arguments of this kind in Hitler it is not too much to see his entire political
theory as essentially Darwinism applied to ethics and international politics.
And as we have seen, Darwin
was in no way reluctant to see his theory so applied. He applied it both to
individuals, lamenting as Hitler did the sentimental tendency to keep alive the
unfit; and he applied it to races, foreseeing with approval the elimination of
inferior races. Hitler has the same double strand of thought. We have seen how
he deplored the preservation of weak individuals. In Mein Kampf he recommends the sterilisation of the mentally
retarded, something he was to carry out quite soon after taking power,
eventually going on to kill them. And of course he also applies this principle
to races. The Germans, says Hitler, are a strong and superior race; confined in
a reduced territory by their defeat, they need living space; so they must
expand into a weaker race’s territory and, like any other animal species,
drive out or wipe out the weaker inhabitants. In the process, the hardship and
violence of their great struggle will be a useful way of strengthening their
race by culling the weakest individuals among them. This is how he expounds
this Darwinist theme:
Nature
knows no political boundaries. First she puts living creatures on this globe
and watches the free play of forces. She then confers the master’s right on her
favourite child, the strongest in courage and industry……
When a people limits itself to internal
colonization (by which he means more
intensive production in a limited territory) because other races are
clinging to greater and greater surfaces of the earth, it will be forced to
have recourse to self-limitation at a time when the other peoples are still
continuing to increase….. Since in general, unfortunately, the best
nations, or even more correctly the only truly cultured races, the
standard-bearers of all human progress, all too frequently resolve in their
pacifistic blindness to renounce new acquisitions of soil and content
themselves with “internal” colonization, while the
inferior races know how to secure immense living areas in this world for
themselves – this would lead to the following result:
The culturally superior but less ruthless
races would in consequence of their limited soil have to limit their increase
at a time when the culturally inferior but more brutal-natured peoples, in
consequence of their greater living areas, would still be in a position to
increase without limit. In other words, some day the world will come into the
possession of the culturally inferior but more active men. 28
These brutal but inferior
peoples, he goes on, will govern the world either through democratic means and
weight of numbers, or by force, and the superior peoples will be outnumbered
and eliminated.
No one can doubt
that this world will one day be exposed to the severest struggles for the
existence of mankind. In the end, only the urge for self-preservation can
conquer. Beneath it so-called humanism, the expression of a mixture of
stupidity, cowardice and know-it-all conceit, will melt like snow in the March
sun. Mankind has grown great in eternal struggle, and only in eternal peace
does it perish. 29
Hitler’s expansionistic
policy to obtain lebensraum
(living-space) by force from inferior peoples is Darwinian in its entire
conception. Such a passage makes it perfectly clear that Darwin supplied the practical politician
Hitler with his theory, just as Marx supplied the practical politician Lenin
with his theory. Neither theoretician may have entirely approved the barbarous
methods used to put his theory into practice, or the extremes it led to. But
neither can claim he was against any of it on principle. Marx believed in a
dictatorship of the proletariat and the elimination of the bourgeois class,
which Lenin carried into action. Darwin
quite explicitly applied his theories of ruthless competition to the races of
humanity, and advocated the elimination of “lower races” and the
prevention of defective individuals from breeding. Hitler’s initial
programme of sterilisation, then extermination of invalids, the incurably ill
and the insane was simply putting Darwin’s recommendations into
practice, even if the methods were somewhat harsher than Darwin might have
wanted. Whether Darwin
would have approved the persecution and extermination of the Jews is an
entirely separate question. The young Darwin was
strongly opposed to slavery and scandalized by the treatment of black slaves he
witnessed in Brazil,
but he was also convinced of the inherent inferiority of “savage” races such as
the Indians of Tierra del Fuego. In old age Darwin
complacently accepted the dying out of “backward” races in Tasmania and elsewhere
and believed that hundreds of backward races would one day perish, as part of
the natural scheme of things. Once you have a belief in higher and lower races,
different opinions may obviously arise as to which races are the lower ones.
But on the principle of eliminating lower races, Darwin appears to have had few qualms.
Hitler’s plan to
exterminate the Jews was part of a wider programme to exterminate millions of
Russians and Ukrainians by starvation, and settle Germans in their place. “There’s only one duty,” he declared to
his ministers in the midst of the invasion of Russia, “to Germanize this
country by the immigration of Germans and to look upon the natives as Redskins.” He envisaged “a hundred and
thirty million people in the Reich, ninety in the Ukraine” and looked
forward to the day when, along with their allies, they would be “400 millions, as
compared to 130 million Americans.” 30 He imagined in detail the way of life of the master race of
colonists. “The German colonists ought to live on handsome
spacious farms. The German services will be lodged in marvellous buildings, the
governors in palaces…. Around the city to a depth of thirty to forty
kilometres, we shall have a belt of handsome villages connected by the best
roads. What exists beyond that will be another world, in which we mean to let
the Russians live as they like. It is merely necessary that we should rule
them.” The inferior race would be kept as ignorant serfs in a permanently
backward state. “Let them know just enough to understand our highway
signs, so they won’t get themselves run over by our vehicles. For them
the word ‘liberty’ means the right to wash on
feast days.” 31 He saw this
displacement of a backward race by a more advanced and intelligent one as
natural law, the survival of the fittest, making for the further progress and
strengthening of the human race. For him humane, compassionate values were the
suicidal, pacifist weakness which advanced peoples were prone to, and which
would allow other, less advanced races to ultimately dominate the earth. Hitler
is haunted by a powerful Darwinian sense that the Germans must conquer or be
conquered. There is no third possibility. Life is war. It is merely a question
of taking the initiative to impose one’s victory or
allowing the gradual victory of others, through the sheer weight of numbers and
the breeding power of inferior peoples. The massive bloodshed which his policy
of war involves, far from being an argument against it, is a positive advantage
in Darwinian terms, because it will eliminate the weaker individuals from all
the races engaged in the struggle, including his own. Seen in terms of
Christian or humanist morality (which believes in every individual’s absolute worth)
the carnage of war is bad. Seen in Darwinian-Hitlerian terms it is wholly good
since it intensifies selection of the best and speeds up evolution. War is like
an extreme Malthusian crisis, the ideal condition for rapid evolution. Hitler’s cult of war is
therefore a logical extension of
Darwinism.
Now this does not
mean, as we have already said, that Darwin
would have approved of Hitler’s programme. Darwin
remained forever divided in his mind as to how much inhumanity and callousness
was acceptable. His biographers ironize over the contradictions between his
harsh beliefs and his mild behaviour. “The sickly and degenerate
deserve to be scythed down, he believed, even as he sent subscriptions to the
Downe charities ….. and worried about his sons’ in-bred
ailments.” 32 Darwin did not have the
ruthless consistency of Hitler, it is clear. It is less clear whether or not
Marx had the ruthlessness of Lenin and Stalin. But the relationship of theory to
practice is there in both cases, in roughly equal degrees. Darwinism-Hitlerism,
along with Marxism-Leninism, illustrates how the nineteenth century’s violence of
thought, however rhetorically it may have been meant, was translated into the
twentieth century’s all-too-literal violence of action. Darwin’s theory becomes,
in Hitler’s hands, a Frankenstein’s monster.
Darwin’s modern
apologists would deny that he had any part of responsibility in this. Even in
his own time his disciples finally tried to defend him against association with
the worst excesses of the Social Darwinists, by denying that he intended “natural morality” to apply to
human beings. This is what Thomas Huxley argued after a lifetime of stoutly
defending Darwin’s evolutionary
theory and then becoming alarmed by the brutal extremes that Social Darwinism
was being carried to. Huxley argued just before he died that man’s morality was
opposed to nature’s, which was not a morality at all, since the
fittest were not necessarily the best. “Let us understand, once for
all, that the ethical progress of society depends not on imitating the cosmic
process, still less in running away from it, but in combating it.” 33 However, in this change of heart (which mirrors Spencer’s), he was
opposing Darwin himself, by then already dead ten years. On what grounds can we
argue that man is an exception to nature’s rules and must live by a
different morality? It is precisely Darwin who destroyed the firewall between
man and nature – who proved that
man is merely another animal, subject to the same laws. What then is to prevent
man applying the same Darwinian principles to his own behaviour, especially in
the lawless realm of relations between nations? What other source of morality
is there but nature? Divine revelation? But Huxley himself had spent his life
ridiculing the notion of revelation: his sworn enemy was the Church. So where
was the higher morality (which Huxley still emotionally believed in) to come
from?
Darwin in his notebooks
had himself toyed with the notion that all morality can be derived from the
rules of the troop, in pack species like wild dogs, which obey a certain social
discipline. 34 Hitler was to extend the same idea into a conviction
that it was the most disciplined peoples, where the individual was most
inclined to sacrifice himself for the good of the nation, that were the
strongest and fittest. Morality was therefore to Hitler merely behaviour which
strengthened the nation, where the individual subjected himself to the
collective will – obedience to the pack, or to its leader. 35 This
is a concept of morality as mere conformity to the group which breaks
completely with the humanist tradition, derived from the Christian gospel of
brotherly love, and also the notion of the individual’s moral conscience,
which is in touch with a higher law than society’s (a notion that
goes back to the Greeks as well as to the Hebrews.) While Darwin had some guilty hesitations about
putting forward his suggestion of a radically new non-Christian morality, based
on the survival of the fittest and the rules of the pack, Hitler was encumbered
with no such scruples about consigning the old morality to the dustbin.
The fact is that Darwin undermined
permanently and fatally the compassionate ethical code based on the Christian
gospels: love thy neighbour, and do good to those that harm you. He did this
not only by undermining belief in revealed Christianity through his demolition
of the biblical creation story. He also undermined the arguments of liberal
humanists for trying to preserve the Christian ethic of compassion and love of
one’s neighbour as a socially useful moral code, even after Christianity’s decline as a
faith. How could one any longer defend the Christian virtues as socially useful
if they were now exposed as nation-weakening vices, crippling us in the
struggle for survival? Did they not conflict with what science was now telling
us was the code needed for the fittest to prevail and the race to evolve? If
Christianity and all divinely-revealed ethical systems are to fall in an
atheistic age, then what is left but to apply Darwinism to human relations? If
religion is dead, what is left but science? And the science of survival and the
improvement of species is Darwinism. Why not then apply Darwinism to man, and
adapt our moral attitudes accordingly? Why not jettison the absurd compassion
and pity for the sufferings of the weak, the “hysterical desire
to save every living being”, when these no longer correspond to a scientific
viewpoint and their religious basis has disappeared? Why not shuck off the
ethical, humanist clothes of Christianity, now that it is discredited as a
religion? In short, if humanism, derived from the gospel of universal love, has
no scientific basis and no religious basis, then what does it rest on? How does
it continue to stand up? It is a mere superstition, waiting for a forceful mind
to demolish it.
By Hitler’s day that
forceful mind had already come along, hard on the heels of Darwin, and he became (some would argue by
misunderstanding and ignorance) one of Hitler’s heroes. His
name was Friedrich Nietzsche. He forms an essential link in the ideological
chain between Darwin and Hitler, through his devastating critique of
Christianity as a source of moral values that could outlast “the death of God”.
6)
NIETZSCHE’S ATTACK ON THE SPIRITUAL PLANE
Darwin
destroyed the notion that man is biologically different from the rest of
nature. Man is not a separate creation, placed on this earth by God for
inscrutable divine purposes. He is part and parcel of the natural, animal
world, a descendant of the apes, and obeying the same biological laws. But
there is still the question of man’s soul, his spiritual
dimension. The Church may have been discredited by Darwin because of the absurdly unscientific
creation myth of The Book of Genesis, but man’s belief in a
spiritual reality stretched well beyond the Christian religion. It lay at the
heart also of the classical civilization, which had again come to dominate
Western thought after its rediscovery in the Renaissance. One of the earliest
Greek poets, Hesiod, in the 8th century BC proclaimed the distinction between
man’s morality and that of animals by invoking the law of Zeus:
The son of Kronos made
this law for men:
That animals and fish
and winged birds
Should eat each other,
for they have no law,
But mankind has the
law of right from him,
Which is the better way. 36
The Greeks were thus from
the earliest age keen to distinguish man’s moral sense from the realm
of nature’s brutal struggles. They generally saw the human
moral faculty as of divine origin. Various Greek philosophers refined this
notion of the divine provenance of moral law. Plato believed in a realm of
spirit transcending the material world of nature. The material world, for Plato,
was a pale shadow of the spiritual one. Man’s body might be a purely
natural phenomenon, a product of this world, but his soul was of divine origin,
belonging to a higher plane. The morality that guided man’s actions must
also derive from this spiritual plane. This is the idea that Thomas Huxley was
hinting at when he tried to distance Darwinism from the Social Darwinists by
insisting that man’s morality consisted in combating nature’s, because
it came from a different source. It is
this belief in a spiritual plane, source of a higher morality, which still
stood in the way of applying Darwinian natural laws vigorously to human
relations. And it is this spiritual plane that Nietzsche set out to destroy.
Nietzsche
attacked front on the fundamental dualism of Platonic philosophy, according to
which man’s spiritual life has another origin from his
biological one. Nietzsche preached with all the rhetorical power of an old
testament prophet against Plato’s siren song whispering in man’s ear: “you are of another
origin, you are from another world, a spiritual plane, and you must conquer the
base urges of the body and try to attain that spiritual plane.” His own message
was the opposite: “I entreat you, my brothers, remain true to the earth, and do not believe those who speak to you
of super-terrestrial hopes.” 37 “Once the soul looked contemptuously upon the body” but “the enlightened
man says: I am body entirely, and nothing besides; and soul is only a word for
something in the body.” 38 And since man’s nature is purely physical,
his morality must necessarily be the product of his biological existence.
Nietzsche pulled the rug from under the feet of Huxley’s belated
traditionalist argument that man’s morality did not come from
nature but a higher plane. What higher plane? asked Nietzsche bluntly. While Darwin proved that man is
not physically separate from the animals, that he is not the product of some
divine spark, Nietzsche sought to prove something similar about man’s thinking and
his ethical sense. This is not the product of a divine spark either, but merely
of man’s physical survival needs. Nietzsche is responsible
for a major shift in the very conception of morality. It is no longer to be
seen as a revealed truth of divine origin as the Christians saw it, or as a
truth coming from a spiritual, intellectual plane that man’s mind has access
to, as Plato saw it, or as a sort of mathematical truth or logical law of the
mind as Kant tried to see it. No, says Nietzsche: man makes morality, it comes
from his own needs. Morality is merely a social construct, designed to suit the
purposes of a particular society. For Nietzsche, you do not ask whether an
ethical principle is true but whether it is necessary or useful, and what sort
of society it is useful for. “God is dead” is simply the announcement
that modern man no longer needs the concept of the divine to be the origin of
his ethical code. He has finally understood that God is also a construct, and
that man himself invents the ethical code that he needs and the God to go with
it. Having reduced human morality to the invention of a code corresponding to
the needs of a certain kind of society, Nietzsche has effectively demolished
the last intellectual defence against accepting Social Darwinism, and by
extension Hitlerism. If man is no longer an exception to nature, if there is no
longer a spiritual world that sets man apart, no planet heaven, then there is
no barrier to the crude application of Darwinian morality, the survival of the
fittest, to man himself – and the competition between individuals, nations,
and races. For why should man be exempt from universal natural laws and
processes?
But Nietzsche
went further than this. He not only destroyed the metaphysical basis of a
system of spiritual values opposed to the natural world, and insisted that man
simply invents morality. He also placed various moral codes in a kind of
hierarchy from best to worst, reflecting the societies that gave birth to them.
And he placed Christian morality – love and compassion – at the very bottom of the
scale as the contemptible code of a slave society. Now this was new in Western
history. There had been critics of Christianity before Nietzsche – those who had
argued that the Christian religion was based on myths or that the gospels were largely fictive accounts of a legendary
teacher. Some had ridiculed the gospel story, as in Voltaire’s parody about
the virgin made pregnant by the dove. But most agnostic thinkers, from Voltaire
to Matthew Arnold or John Stuart Mill, had still treasured the moral message of
those gospels: love thy neighbour, do good to those who harm you. Christian
morality survived Christianity in the form of humanism and the liberal, humane
ethical code. Now Nietzsche attacked head-on this last respected remnant of Christianity,
the humane moral code, by arguing that it was the product of a slave society.
Harsh, warrior-like ethical systems are, according to Nietzsche, the product of
aristocracies, and raise human beings to the highest level of nobility,
strength and talent by their rigorous discipline. Creeds of universal
compassion, on the other hand, are the invention of the downtrodden and
oppressed, who want to alleviate their own sufferings. They are inherently
despicable because they blunt that discriminatory urge by which the best are
selected, trained and perfected in harsher systems, and instead level everybody
downwards. They therefore lead to spiritual and artistic decline. Now no one had ever before attacked Christian
morality, the gospel of love, the vague belief that human beings should be kind
to one another, in such a direct and brutal fashion. That attack again was an
essential step towards the Nazi enthronement of the cruel goddess Nature, whose
ruthless ways are to be imitated by man.
Now it is unclear
whether Nietzsche understood that his thinking had opened the way to the crude
application of Darwinism to human behaviour – that is to say, Hitlerism.
His sister, who hijacked his legacy
after his madness and death, saw Hitler as the embodiment of Nietzsche’s ideal. His
modern admirers, of course, hotly deny any Nazi tendencies in their idol. They
have struggled for decades to get Nietzsche out from under the Nazi embrace,
and have striven to prove that he would have found Hitler’s regime
intolerable. They like to point to his cult of liberty, his admiration for the
Jews, his love of the South, his cult of the solitary artist as the superman,
his hatred of the mob and of mob rule, his refined sensibility, his final
rejection of Wagner’s anti-Semitism and Teutonic nationalism. None of
this is to be denied. There is a great deal that separates a complex and subtle
thinker like Nietzsche from Nazism, and would probably have made him abhor it.
But his supporters miss the point. The problem is not what Nietzsche believed
but what he made possible. Nietzsche’s denial of a spiritual
realm of moral absolutes, of a transcendental plane from which values contrary
to nature’s may be acquired, his belief in the purely
pragmatic, survival value of moral codes, and his systematic attack on the
Christian-humanist code of love and compassion as the creed of slaves, all
opened the ideological door to the Social Darwinists and ultimately to Hitler.
The Nazis may have been wrong in claiming Nietszche as one of theirs. They were
not wrong in seeing his thought as an essential step on the road that enabled
them to apply cruel Darwinian laws to human beings. For that road leads to the
temple of “the harsh goddess Nature”, worshipped as
the only deity, and it is Nietzsche who did more than anyone else to destroy
all other divinities but her.
Nietzsche remains
one of the greatest and most stimulating thinkers of recent centuries. But it
is pointless and dishonest to deny his role in the march towards Nazi
ethics. Just as Marx might (and it is a
big might) have been horrified to see the Stalinist gulags that came out of his
work, Nietzsche and Darwin would certainly have been horrified by Auschwitz.
But paternity cannot be denied merely because the child becomes a monster. And
Nazism is the child of Darwin and Nieztsche, as certainly as Stalinism is of
Marx.
Now the morality
of Nazism, that might makes right, that the weak should be eliminated, which is
deeply repugnant to most of us, is extremely difficult to refute without refuting
either Darwin or Nietzsche. If both Darwin and Nietzsche are right, then Hitler
is right. To refute Hitler, we have to take one of two approaches: either prove
that Darwin is
wrong in positing a ruthless struggle to survive as the basic “morality” of nature. Or
else prove that Nietzsche is wrong in denying a spiritual plane from which man
can derive a morality very different from nature’s cruel laws. In
other words we must refute Darwin’s vision of
nature, or refute Nietzsche’s contention that there is no escape from it, no
alternative morality. Now many people, particularly in America, would
dispute Nietzsche’s claims outright: they believe that God is very
much alive and from the perspective of religious faith they have no problem
devising a higher morality for man. However, relatively few scientists and
intellectuals in the West share this religious faith, and most would go along
with Nietzsche’s claim that morality is a social construct. With Darwin, there is even
less room for manoeuvre. His position is virtually unassailed among
establishment scientists and thinkers in Britain
and America,
and above all in the school curriculum to which every child is subjected – the only
nineteenth century system-builder to have survived the scepticism of the
twentieth. The most vocal critics of Darwin
are “Creationists”, many of them Fundamentalist Christians who deny
evolution as such and cling to a literal reading of the bible. Such people are
not taken seriously by most scientists. We are left therefore wondering how
scientific Darwinists live with a world-view which basically justifies Hitler’s policies of
war, the military expansion of the strongest races, and the killing of the
handicapped. On what grounds do they criticize Hitler’s Darwinian
morality? Do they deny Nietzsche’s demolition of the
spiritual plane from which we can derive different values? Or do they accept
there is only this material, biological life and the values derived from it – which are
Darwinian values? Or are they simply not thinking things through, blithely
living with an inherited morality derived from Christianity, while not
believing its basis, and not seeing its inconsistency with their scientific
world-view?
The acceptance of
Darwin’s theory of
evolution through natural selection poses far more problems to the basis of our
morality than we have so far realized. The very lack of understanding of where
Darwin and Nietzsche lead us on the ethical front suggests that our morality is
in fact a matter of cultural habit and not at all related to the scientific
world-view we hold. The only evidence to the contrary, some might suggest, is
that those who hold to Darwinism as a militant faith are inclined to a
ruthlessness and aggressiveness in their intellectual struggle to destroy or
silence their adversaries, which testifies to their practical application of
Darwinian morality in their lives.
Darwin’s theory provoked
criticism from the very beginning on ethical grounds as much as scientific
ones. Darwin’s friend and
co-originator of the theory of natural selection, Alfred Russell Wallace,
gradually drifted apart from him because he came to see “the survival of
the fittest” as both a false picture of what happens in nature
and a morally pernicious concept. Wallace was a socialist, opposed to the
justifications which natural selection provided for brutal competition to
eliminate the weak. He was also a believer in man’s spiritual
nature and its importance in his evolution. He spent much time living with the
Dyak tribes of Borneo and formed a profound respect for the intelligence of
so-called primitive man (unlike Darwin’s contempt for
the Tierra del Fuego natives.) Wallace
believed such peoples were intelligent far beyond the level necessary for their
physical survival, and he posited an excess of intelligence and a spiritual and
moral dimension as the key to man’s evolution. He opposed the
racism implicit in Darwinism, the concepts of superior and inferior, whether of
races, classes or individuals. For him, the belief that “some have a
better right to existence than others” was immoral. 39
The fact that unlike the prosperous Darwin,
Wallace was chronically penniless and unemployed may have influenced his views.
He was, in many ways, one of life’s brilliant failures, a
noble loser, the sort of individual in fact destined to be eliminated by
natural selection – and sensitive to the injustice of this brutal
process. Just as he himself personally failed in his career, so also his more
humane and egalitarian version of evolution failed to prevail and was
eliminated. It was steam-rolled over by the Darwinian cult of ruthless violence
which led on inexorably to Hitlerism.
Many prominent
scientists, over the years, have challenged Darwinism on scientific grounds
rather than ethical ones. Fred Hoyle, the British astronomer, confessed that he
never believed in Darwinism. Pierre Grassé, the President of the French academy
of sciences and the reigning expert in his field of biology, claimed thirty
yeas ago that Darwinism was a mere pseudo-science which does not explain the
mechanics of evolution. “Today our duty is to destroy the myth of evolution
considered as a simple, understood and explained phenomenon which keeps rapidly
unfolding before us. Biologists must be encouraged to think about the
weaknesses and extrapolations that theoreticians put forward and lay down as
established truths.” 40 He accepts the general hypothesis of evolution but considers its
principles and workings to be so far unexplained. The problem for him is not
only the precise adaptations of organisms which seem beyond the blunt
instrument of natural selection to arrive at, but also the fundamental one of
the origin of life, which nobody can account for. “Any living thing
possesses an enormous amount of ‘intelligence’ …. Today this
intelligence is called ‘information’, but it is still the same
thing. This intelligence is the sine qua non of life. If absent, no living
being is imaginable. Where does it come from? This is a problem which concerns
both biologists and philosophers, and at present science seems incapable of
solving it.” 41
Now to the modern
Darwinists this sort of scepticism, which a normal person might consider to be
in the purest scientific tradition of agnosticism (an admission of ignorance),
is a dangerous mysticism which opens the door to irrational world-views. They
believe that they have solved the problem of life (or laid down the definitive
lines that such a solution must follow.) Any doubt that they have done so they
regard as a form of treason against science, an open invitation to
Creationists, bible-thumpers, New Age gurus and sundry peddlers of the
irrational to rush in and occupy the space that science has cautiously
withdrawn from. The Darwinist professors who hold the major biology chairs in Britain and America are quite militantly
defensive, apparently convinced that the flying saucers are on their way and
will land the moment they display an ounce of healthy self-doubt. They respond
to every criticism of natural selection with a charge of “Creationism!”, do everything
to prevent their scientific opponents gaining a hearing, and have contributed
to an atmosphere of intellectual hatred, intolerance, abuse, dishonesty and bad
faith which is worse today than at any time since Darwin put forward his
theory. Instead of taking a normal scientific interest in experiments such as
those of biologist Ted Steele in Australia, which suggest that there are
elements of Lamarckism in the behaviour of retrogenes and immune systems, their
only concern is to fanatically attack such experiments as treasonous breaches
in the defensive wall of a theory that must be preserved as an absolute, a
whole, a total explanation of life. 42 No modification can be
allowed. Lamarck is the devil, the defeated, he must not be allowed back in. It
is the fanatical behaviour of these scientists that leads one to treat their
beliefs not as science but as ideology, and as therefore falling within the
scope of a history of ideas.
Our main concern
in this book is with Darwinism as a popular world-view which has had an
enormous influence on our society – through the Social
Darwinism of cut-throat capitalism, colonialism and Nazism. The notion of
natural selection and the survival of the fittest as the single universal
principle by which all life evolved is a poisonous world-view which has done
immeasurable harm. I believe that even today this world-view remains at the
back of every person’s mind at the moment of doing something thoroughly
vicious, selfish and ruthless – the fleeting reflection that after all life is a
struggle in which the weak go to the wall and I am only obeying jungle law in
putting number one first. In short, we live in a world of kill or be killed.
Every aggressive act is only an act of self-defence. Every murder, every
treachery, every cruelty is an act of self-preservation. This philosophy is an
in-built justification for every form of evil, whether in business, politics or
personal relationships. It is the popular Darwinian image of the world which
shapes the criminal mind, the fascist mind, and the ruthless capitalist mind.
The survival of the fittest is a doctrine of evil, indistinguish-able from the
right of the strongest – the essence of fascist ideology. Many of the worst
horrors of the twentieth century can be ascribed to this doctrine directly, and
most others indirectly. And it survives as our dominant world-view simply
because the scientists who occupy the chairs at leading Anglo-Saxon
universities are terrified that if this vicious doctrine is not taught in
schools then religion and other irrational explanations of life may gain
ground. In fact this theory has itself become a breeding ground for a fantastic
upsurge in superstition and pseudo-science – notably the field of
so-called evolutionary psychology, which pretends that every human trait from
dishonesty to freckles to bad breath has been selected for its survival value.
Its adepts construct game theory structures which demonstrate the evolutionary
advantages of infidelity or lying and pretend to explain these traits
biologically without reference to any human systems of thought, morality or
custom, or any knowledge of history or other cultures except the grossest comic
strip versions of them. Darwinism is not only the greatest source of evil and
viciousness in human behaviour, but also the greatest source of irrationality,
ignorance and superstition in academic thinking today.
Of course there
would be no point in denouncing as evil the popular Darwinian picture of the
world, if the scientists had produced convincing evidence that it is,
unfortunately, true. But in fact they have done nothing of the kind. This is
what leads me to examine the theory of Darwinism as such: not just as a
pernicious popular ideology but as a scientific explanation of the way nature
works. It is the relation between the two that is of interest. To what extent
is the popular Darwinian world-view actually borne out by the scientific
version of Darwinism that prevails today in the universities? We will see in
fact that even Darwin’s most prominent
disciples have so modified and diluted his theories that the popular image of
the “survival of the fittest” is an obsolete world-view which, when pushed, no
evolutionist today dares to defend. What is unacceptable is that the academics
have fudged and refined their interpretations of Darwinism until they have
denuded the theory of all its original meaning – but they still
pretend to believe in it, thus perpetuating the popular ideology which has had
such a corrupting effect on human morality. And what is most disturbing is that
the scientists who have diluted Darwinism beyond recognition as an explanation
of the mechanics of evolution, appear to be fiercely attached themselves to the
popular emotional world-picture of ruthlessness and savage struggle that it
gave rise to – even though they have given up any belief in the
technical details of that world-picture. In short, the defence of Darwinism
today is essentially the defence of an ideological and moral belief about the
universe. Underneath that ideology, the biological theory that sustains it has
already been refined out of existence.
Now it may be
objected that a non-scientist has no right to launch himself recklessly into
arcane arguments in a field in which he is not qualified. If the rules of
specialization had been respected by the other side, this might be a valid
point. But the Darwinian evolutionists
for the last fifty years have been throwing so much rubbish over the
fence into the field of philosophy and ideas about the meaning of life, that a
historian of ideas is perfectly entitled to look over the scientific fence to
see where all this rubbish is coming from. And what he sees there is not a
pretty sight. The Darwinist camp is extremely messy, in disarray, and full of
the muddiest thinking imaginable.
7) AFTER ALL, WAS DARWIN RIGHT?
The theory of evolution itself, that all forms of life on
earth evolved from one form, or at the least, that complex forms evolved from
simple forms, is generally agreed to be the most probable scientific hypothesis
until proved wrong, given the structural similarities of many different life
forms. The idea of the evolution of species had been around for half a century
before Darwin,
ever since the Frenchman Jean Baptiste Lamarck published his Zoological Philosophy in 1809. While
Lamarck’s theory was also implicitly subversive of the
biblical creation story, it did not break radically with traditional ideas
about the harmony of nature, or about the moral principles that should guide
human behaviour. His theory of evolution was based on a mechanism of direct
adaptation to the environment. Confronted with a new situation, animals adapt
their behaviour, and if this adaptation is radical enough to develop muscles or
organs in a new way, or to lead to reduction through disuse of other muscles or
organs, then over generations these physical adaptations will be inherited and
hence progressively developed. Prime examples are the atrophying of wings in
birds that no longer need to fly away from predators in island habitats. The
accumulation of inherited small changes leads to radical long-term change or
macro-evolution, the transformation of one species into another.
This was the
standard version of evolution in Darwin’s day – a view
anathemized by the church and the establishment, but held by radical thinkers
like his old tutor at Edinburgh
University, Robert Grant.
Lamarckism was never entirely abandoned by Darwin himself, even when he put
forward his alternative theory of natural selection. Lamarckism seems even to
have remained the view preferred by many evolutionists after Darwin (perhaps even including his great
ally, Thomas Huxley, who remained sceptical of natural selection to the end.)
It was only in the 1940’s when the new Synthetic Evolutionary Theory
combined Darwin’s idea of natural
selection with a new theory of mutations that Darwinism was finally enthroned
as the orthodox version of evolution, and Lamarck was banished to the outer
darkness of exploded fallacy. Now it is important to see that when Darwin published The Origin of Species it was the idea of
evolution as such, not his theory of natural selection, which aroused the most
heated controversy and the fiercest church opposition, because of its challenge
to the bible and to the idea of mankind’s uniqueness. His new
forceful restatement of a fifty-year old idea, complete with detailed examples
and a new mechanism for how it operated, meant that this challenge to the
separate creation of mankind could no longer be dismissed as mere speculation.
If evolution was demonstrably right, and all scientists were compelled to
accept it, then the bible was wrong. His own specific contribution, natural
selection, aroused a different sort of controversy. There was the concern of
many (such as his old Cambridge Proctor Sedgewick from his divinity student
days) that it encouraged an immoral ruthlessness of behaviour; and there were
the objections of other evolutionists that it had too many problems as a theory. Darwin had to contend with both sorts of
opposition: church and conservative opposition to evolution as such; and both
moral and scientific opposition to the mechanism of natural selection.
One of the
paradoxes is that most of the people who eagerly espoused evolution after Darwin’s book came out,
and saw him as a hero for having demolished biblical creationism, were still
sceptical of his theory of natural selection. As one Darwinist puts it :
After
his death many biologists found it easy to accept evolution and impossible to
accept Darwin’s chief
explanation for it. Evolution yes, selection no. William Bateson, the founder
of modern genetics, wrote an elegy for Darwinism in 1913, calling it “So inapplicable
to the facts that we can only marvel … at the want of penetration
displayed by the advocates of such a proposition.” In 1924, another leading biologist recounts
that “Darwin’s theory of the
origin of species was long ago abandoned.” 43
In fact most people still
leaned towards Lamarck’s picture of evolution. Darwin, it is not too much to say, probably
converted more people to Lamarckism than to his own theory. Virtually all the
well-known thinkers who enthusiastically welcomed Darwin, men like Herbert
Spencer, Samuel Butler, and later Bernard Shaw, were more or less Lamarckians – and some of them
directly attacked natural selection. Darwin himself published a book developing
Lamarck’s theory of the inheritance of acquired
characteristics, because he saw it as a major cause of the variation which
natural selection must act upon. In short, true Darwinism was a hybrid of
Lamarck and natural selection. But once the new narrow version of his thinking,
the Synthetic Evolutionary Theory, or neo-Darwinism, was developed in the 1940’s, the Lamarckian
element in Darwinism was excluded and expurgated. The book where Darwin elaborates his
Lamarckian ideas (The Variation of
Animals and Plants Under Domestication, published in 1868) is now treated
as a regrettable error and is seldom talked about by neo-Darwinists. A thinker
who was relatively open-minded and willing to consider a number of alternatives
to his own ideas has, many might argue, been hijacked by a narrow, dogmatic,
ideologically-driven sect that has colonized the academic world.
Darwin’s key idea of
natural selection – the selection by the rigours of life of those random variations among individuals that give
some advantage – introduced a new, brutal vision of nature because
of the high number of casualties required to make it work. The old view of
harmonious and balanced nature was replaced by a vision of unending ruthless
warfare. For the differential death rates to play their selective role there
had to be ferocious amounts of premature death. Darwin’s theory of natural
selection, we have just seen, was deeply influenced by Malthus, the prophet of
the population explosion. It was Malthus’s predictions of future
catastrophe, as the human population outran its food supply and was plunged
into a brutal competition for dwindling resources, which gave Darwin his idea. He began speculating as to
which individuals would survive in this catastrophic state of savage
competition. How would nature choose the survivors? He came to the conclusion
that such a catastrophe would probably be good for the human species: it would
lead to the elimination of the weak and the selection of the stronger
individuals. His idea of natural selection was born. But what constitutes the
weak and what constitutes the strong? Clearly the degree of adaptation to the
new environmental conditions. Under the new conditions, those individuals who
possess some feature which gives them a marginal advantage in the struggle for
survival will be selected by nature. That is, they will survive and outbreed
those who don’t have this quality, till their descendants
gradually take over the species. Darwin
realized that he had here in this catastrophe scenario a general explanation as
to how species evolve, how they change over many thousands of generations, and
how they diverge under differing conditions and form new species. 44
One of the huge disadvantages of Darwin’s theory comes from its
genesis. It was a theory of survival in catastrophic conditions of generalized
vicious warfare for scarce resources. In order to make this into a general
theory of how nature always operates, he had to convince us that nature is
always in this state of generalized vicious warfare. He also had to prove that
this vicious state of warfare would in some way be selective – that it would
not be the blind destruction of mass bombing but the careful targeting of the
weak and maladapted. Those are the only
conditions under which natural selection will in fact operate – if life or
death, or reproduction or childlessness, depends on having a certain
characteristic. At the very least he has to prove a very significant
differential in numbers of surviving offspring between the fit and the unfit,
the adapted and the maladapted. Now the great problem is that all that research
has ever shown is that the death rate varies enormously from one species to
another, and that sometimes it is very high. But it is much more problematic to
prove that the individuals culled and those that survive are in any way
selected on genetic merit. The sea-slug lays six hundred thousand eggs, most of
which are fortunately destroyed or they would soon overrun the world. Is it
reasonable to believe this mass destruction is a qualitative selection rather
than something purely quantitative? Given the scale of extermination required,
you might as well believe that Hiroshima
was a qualitative selection, and that the fittest survived. What
characteristics in the sea-slug eggs are being selected? Similarly, the vast
majority of birds that die before breeding (like humans in the past) die in
infancy. The highest death rates among altricial birds (those that stay in the
nest after being hatched) are suffered while in the egg, in the nest, and just
after they leave the nest. It is quite hard to see where the qualities of the
individual bird would come into play here to make a difference to their fate.
Falling through a wobbly wall in the nest or being found by a large weasel are
not things that Johnny nestling can do much about with his own individual
brilliance. If we conclude that premature death is just a massive lottery, a
purely quantitative reduction in species numbers, and that not much genetic
variation is being selected here, then the whole principle of natural selection
as the motor of evolution falls to the ground.
It is this
problem which makes variation so important. How much variation is there between
individuals? We need large amounts of it to make natural selection work. This
pushed Darwin
to explore the ways in which genetic variation can develop, and one of the ways
he accepted was Lamarck’s theory of the inheritance of acquired
characteristics. Different behaviour and habits create physical variations, and
these can then be selected. But this might tempt unkindly sceptical souls today
to ask the mischievous question: if you accept the variations caused by
behaviour (and transmitted to offspring), then why do you need natural
selection at all? Lamarck’s variation is quite likely to apply to an entire
group when subject to different conditions (a new island, for example, where
birds have new food and must develop a different beak.) This will not be
individual variation so much as collective variation. In short, not the
material of natural selection, but the beginnings of a collective evolution, as
Lamarck envisaged, where all the individuals on the island tend to develop the
new, better-adapted beak. Darwin himself accepted this possibility in the case
of horses on the Falklands. 45 But
of course, as we have noted, Darwin’s disciples no
longer accept Lamarck, having fallen in love with a theory of mutations
instead. These provide the potential for much more sensational variations, even
though mutations tend unfortunately to be overwhelmingly degenerative.
Darwin
begins his book The Origin of Species
by inviting us to look at how stock-breeders create new strains and races of
animal. All animals of the same species vary slightly from one another.
Breeders choose those with a shade more of the specific characteristic they
want, breed those individuals, then select those among their offspring which
show more of the desired feature, and in this way keep developing it over
generations. Like this they can come up with a dog with tiny legs and a huge
body, or one with a pug face, or long ears, or furry tail, or whatever takes
the perverse fancy of idle dog-lovers. Of course the breeder stops the other
animals from cross-breeding with the chosen ones, and thus preserves the
desired traits from being drowned in the melting-pot. Now for nature to evolve
new species, it must, Darwin
guessed, do something similar. But what plays the role of selection in nature?
How are the individuals with particular characteristics chosen (and on what
principle?) And how does nature stop the mass of ordinary individuals from
breeding again with the variant few and drowning out the modifications (which Darwin, writing in the
days before genetics, assumed would happen very quickly)? Darwin came up with the answer: death is the
selector. Death plays the role of the breeder. The chosen individuals are those
that survive the rigours of life thanks to their special new features, and the
others die out – if not at once, then by having fewer and fewer
offspring, because they compete less well than the variant individuals in the
fierce struggle to survive. Here is where we see the importance of Darwin’s Malthusian
vision of nature as constantly breeding far too many individuals, who must
compete in a ferocious struggle for limited resources. Without this Malthusian
vision, the selector death will not carve deeply enough into the mass to shape
the species. Death plays the role of removing all those who do not have the
desired features so that the favoured few become the bearers of genetic
modifications into the future. Death is therefore the shaping force of
evolution. Death sculpts the species over time as a sculptor sculpts a form by
removing and discarding the material to be rejected. Death is the artist of
life. Death is the creator of species.
This is the
curiously necrophiliac cult which reigns supreme in our scientific world. The
trouble with death is that nobody seems to have bothered to study how it operates.
And death has a particular problem as a selective force. The problem briefly is
that the bigger the scale on which death operates, the less likely it is to be
genetically selective. If death is a maniac on a balcony with a Kalashnikov, he
may well be selecting passers-by according to whether he likes the look of
them. If he is a bomber-pilot carpet-bombing a city, he is very unlikely to be
selective at all. When hounds are chasing down a fox, the fox’s individual
cunning may have an effect on his survival. When a fish is gorging on six
hundred thousand sea-slug eggs, or sea-birds are attacking scores of turtle
hatchlings as they race down a beach to the water, death becomes a lottery, and
only the predator’s full stomach will save any of the prey, not their
own individual merits. In short, where death appears selective, it is
insufficiently large-scale to have much genetic impact on a species; and where
it is large-scale, it is insufficiently selective to be subtracting any
particular characteristics from a gene pool. Would you like to hazard a guess
as to which genetic characteristics were eliminated from the population by the
atom bomb on Hiroshima?
Or which qualities of the local fauna were eliminated by the eruption of Mount
Saint Helen?
This problem of proving his assumption that death
eliminates unfit individuals appeared very soon after Darwin put forward his theory. His colleague,
Wallace, co-originator of the notion of natural selection, had doubts about it
very quickly. He told Darwin
bluntly that his theory of the survival of the fittest was wrong. Among humans,
said Wallace, war does not kill the weakest but the bravest, those who lead the
attack and take the most risks. 46 A few decades later Wilfred Owen
and other First World War poets would repeat what he said with the authority of
bitter experience. What Wallace said of war among humans he meant more
generally of the vicious war among and within species. What allows us to say
that those who survive are the “fittest”? Who says it is the
inferior that are killed?
Most people are content to see the survival of
the fittest as a sort of truism. But it is either a meaningless tautology in
which the fit are defined as the survivors (we will come to that later) or it
is a meaningful statement about which individuals survive, in which case it
must be proved. Does premature death act in the genetically selective way that
will alter the genetic destiny of a species by making it fitter and more
adapted to its environment, or does it act at random? It is important to be clear about what is
being debated here. Darwin
did not see natural selection as simply eliminating the small percentage of
deformed, sickly or handicapped individuals. It was not merely the killing off
of the runts of the litter. He saw it as eliminating large numbers of “normal”, “healthy” or “average” individuals
which are inferior in certain qualities that would make them better-adapted – leaving alive
those that have more of those qualities. That is the only way natural selection
can function as an instrument of the evolution of a species, not merely as a
means of maintaining a species in good health. The two things are utterly
different and should not be confused. Darwin
does not say “the unhealthy die young.” That is a
truism. He says that among the healthy those which have certain specific
inheritable characteristics will survive the rigours of life and those without
those qualities will be eliminated. Is this true? Is premature death
genetically selective?
One would have
thought that a principle so crucial to Darwinism would have been tested by
extensive research – into rates of predation, techniques of hunting,
survival rates of each species, numbers of birds actually leaving the nest as a
percentage of number of eggs laid, how and in what numbers they are killed,
whether or not the individual qualities of the prey can lead to different
outcomes, what qualities seem to matter, to what extent predators select their
prey and on what criteria, etc. This would appear to be the crucial
evidence-gathering necessary to establish whether or not premature death is
genetically selective, whether what looks like the random lottery of predation
can be correlated to any characteristics of the prey. Little of this research
seems to have been done, because the thing is just assumed. Evolution has
clearly happened; this is the mechanism; therefore this is what has caused it.
And because this crude version of Darwinism (we will come to the more subtle
version in a moment) has imprinted itself on every mind as the way things
operate in nature, it is difficult to awaken enough scepticism as to whether
this really is how the world works. I will therefore spend the next few pages
rather laboriously attempting to outline (to the best of my amateur abilities)
how premature death in fact functions among birds and mammals, in order to
raise in the reader’s mind the simple question: is it genetically
selective?
8) IS DEATH GENETICALLY
SELECTIVE?
Apart from old
age, we can list six different causes of death of an individual animal in
nature: killing by rivals, accident, starvation, cold (or other inclement
weather), predation, and disease. We can dismiss old age because if an animal
lives till old age, it has clearly already fulfilled whatever reproductive role
it was going to have, and its demise will make no difference to the future of
the species. We are concerned here with causes of premature death, which will
stop an individual from transmitting its genes to the future and thereby
influence the evolution of the species. We will treat separately the notion of
different rates of reproduction, when we come to look at sexual selection as a
subsidiary selective method, which Darwin
turned to in a later book. Looking at our six causes of premature death, the
question is: do any of them act in the way Darwin supposed, in selecting the most
adapted for survival? Are these causes of death random or are they so biased
towards eliminating or favouring certain characteristics that they will have a
marked effect on the gene pool of the species? And if so, what effect?
Let us look first
at killing by rivals. This apparently promising Darwinian concept – the combat to
the death among competing males – is in fact rather rare in
most species. Most fights between males competing for females are not fatal, as
the loser simply runs away (and often
finds another female.) But to look at male rivalry in more detail, we have to
distinguish the four different patterns of mating among higher animals and
birds. Briefly, there are harem species, monogamous species, promiscuous
species, and lek or arena species. In harem species, such as lions or many
species of deer, where the male possesses a herd of females, the possessor of
the harem generally sees off the challenger very quickly. Robert Ardrey and
Konrad Lorenz have shown how the male in possession of a territory and a herd
of females (the two go together) has a huge advantage in aggressive drive over
the challenger, and usually succeeds in putting him to flight. 47
The challenger, of course, has rather less at stake and does not usually go on
fighting till he is killed or seriously injured. He abandons the combat as soon
as he gets the feel of who is stronger. Only when the lord of the herd becomes
old and tired is he likely to be beaten, and given his persistence in fighting
for his herd he may well sustain injuries that will lead to his death. But the
death of a deposed leader of a herd will not eliminate his genes from the gene
pool. He has already done a vast amount of breeding if he has lasted even two
seasons, and all the younger members of the herd will be his offspring. His
young daughters will be tupped by his successor, not killed. The individual
most likely to be killed by rivals therefore, the weakened old king, will die
leaving his genetic heritage intact. No elimination of his genes will occur
through killing him. (The change of harem lord is periodically necessary, one
might imagine, to stop him mating endlessly with his daughters, grand-daughters
and great granddaughters, which would lead to the degeneration of the
herd.)
But even
supposing that a challenger is occasionally killed, or dies of infected wounds
after the fight, what genetic effect would this be likely to have on the
species in that locality? At first sight it might seem that death would occur
to the weaker males and that this would lead to a gradual increase in strength
or fighting ability in the species, or the further development of the armaments
of the males – antlers, tusks, horns, etc. But this may not be the
case. The challenger most likely to die in combat with the lord of a harem is a
strong male whose pugnacity prevents him from realizing that his opponent has
the edge, and that it is time to run away. Thus it is not the male at the
bottom of the fighting ladder that is most likely to be killed (he runs away
very quickly), but one near the top. It is one that is endowed with more
aggressiveness than sense, who has perhaps challenged a harem lord prematurely
before being quite strong enough to win but is determined to fight to the
bitter end. So the individual most likely to be killed will be a relatively
strong and aggressive male. It is by no means clear what genetic effect his
loss would have on the gene pool. The idea that the deaths of losers must lead
to an increase in fighting ability, size, armaments and aggressiveness, does
not follow at all if the losers killed are among the biggest and most
aggressive. If you eliminate the genes of the number two or number three male
in size and aggressiveness, are you increasing those characteristics in the
gene pool, or decreasing them? Very probably the genetic effect will be zero.
The heroic loser is survived by at least one stronger and many weaker males.
Even this rare event of the death of a challenger will thus not have any effect
on a gene pool whatsoever.
Now if in species
where a male monopolizes a whole herd of females there are seldom mortal
combats between rivals, it is even rarer in monogamous species. All animals and
birds have an instinct to flee when beaten; man is almost the only animal that
makes a virtue of standing his ground against a stronger rival and being killed
(and even then only in certain cultures.) Once pairing has taken place, the
happy husband is generally defending not only a female but a territory, and the
superior aggressive drive of the householder defending wife and hearth and
animated by righteous indignation will always see off the intruder. As we saw
already, the latter is not sufficiently motivated to press the attack, because
he has too little at stake to risk his life. He simply moves off to find
another territory and female. In monogamous species there are generally enough
females to go round, since there are roughly equal numbers of both sexes, so
there is little point in getting killed for a date. It has been found that at
least eighty per cent of male robins (a very aggressive bird) successfully find
a territory and a mate. 48 This suggests a very low level of
elimination at mating time. We don’t know what happens
to the twenty per cent of solitaries of both sexes. They may act as a pool of
replacements, like football reserves, since one of the striking things noted by
Darwin about
bird couples is how rapidly mates that are killed by hunters get replaced. The
widow or widower often remarries the next day, suggesting that even the small
percentage of unmarried individuals are only so temporarily. In short among
monogamous species very few killings by rivals occur, certainly not enough to
have any significant genetic effect on the evolution of the species.
As for species
where the males gather in leks (arenas) or stamping-grounds and joust for the
prize of servicing all the females of the tribe, these combats are largely
ritualized and seldom lead to fatal injuries. They are more like arm-wrestling
tournaments than gladiatorial combats. Often, as with the sage-grouse, they
resemble dances to display the species-specific features which will lead rivals
to acknowledge the superiority of the top guns and allow them to take
possession of the more central territories in the arena. The winners of
lek-tournaments, whether among the sage-grouse or the African kob, are not
usually exhausted champions scarred and maimed from multiple fierce battles. If
they were they would hardly have the energy to service the scores of females
who then arrive on their doorstep and put out to them as the reward of victory.
We will come to the sexual selection involved here later – our concern at
the moment is death by combat with rivals. It very rarely happens. What
surprises many observers of the Ugandan kob (a species of antelope) during
their arena contest is the degree of civility and harmony among the competing
males, and the passivity of the losers as the females flock to the winning few.
Once they have had their joust and established their respective places on the
stamping-ground, the males tend to ignore one another, rather like Olympic
athletes who sit peacefully side by side between races. Females which cross
their territory are not even molested unless they stop and put out to the
owner. In short the whole tournament is conducted in a far more gentlemanly and
civilized way than one might expect from a description of the principle behind
it. There are seldom any corpses left on the jousting field. And the winning
places seem to rotate from year to year as new individuals reach their peak of
strength and beauty and take over as that season’s stud, rather
like Wimbledon tennis champions who reign for
a year or two and then go off form. Again, the temporary nature of the champion’s reign is
essential to avoid too much inbreeding with his own daughters and
grand-daughters in subsequent years.
In the fourth
type of species found among mammals, promiscuous species, such as chimpanzees,
where several males mate with several females in a tribe, the killing of rivals
is virtually unknown. The males exist in a social hierarchy or pecking order of
strength, and disputes are quickly resolved by the submission of the weaker
animal, whose gestures of placation are magnanimously accepted by his superior.
In fact in all tribal animals (and promiscuous animals are usually tribal),
there is a strong inhibition against using their killing skills on members of
their own tribe. Why would this inhibition exist if killing rivals were an
important means of genetic selection and hence of evolution? In species where
males stay within the tribe, instead of being driven out at maturity by the top
dog (as in harem species), there must be reasons for not driving them out (they
contribute to collective defence or hunting.) These reasons for their
usefulness also inhibit the top male from killing them.
In short, we may
seriously doubt whether killing by rivals has any effect whatever on the gene
pool in any species. It occurs too rarely, and, where it does, it mainly
happens to ageing harem lords who have done all their breeding. More rarely, a
very tough and persistent challenger may be killed, but in this case it is
quite difficult to see how any genetic inferiority is being eliminated.
Turning to the
second cause of premature death, accidents
– such as birds falling out of nests or animals
putting their foot in a rabbit hole and going lame, thereby making themselves
vulnerable to predators – these appear to be purely chance occurrences and
therefore utterly devoid of any genetic significance. Would anyone seriously
maintain that car or train accidents happen only to genetically inferior
humans? Or that horse-riding or climbing accidents are genetically selective? How
can these be differentiated from the accident that happens to an antelope
putting its foot in a well-concealed rabbit hole? Or the bird falling out of a
nest? Does anyone seriously believe that a baby dropped on its head by a
careless au pair is being eliminated for its genetic unfitness? So why believe
this of a baby bird falling out of a nest? Accidents, especially to the very
young, are random, and to moralize them is mere superstition.
Yet the belief
that accidental death is genetically selective – that it is based
on the inherent qualities (hyperactivity, poor balance, inattention) of the
individual – is one of the
reflexes of the neo-Darwinist mindset. Every single characteristic that exists
is the result of natural selection, according to this scheme of things, and
accidents are part of that selective process.
But let us see how this world-view works in practice. One of my two pet
kittens once fell off a balcony. The one that fell was the adventurous one. So,
the neo-Darwinist would argue, too much adventurousness is not good – nature punished
this temerity as genetically ill-adapted. As a matter of fact the kitten
escaped with a bleeding nose. He only fell two floors. So clearly he was not an
unfit kitten: he survived. But wait – does this mean that if the
flat had been on the tenth floor and he had fallen ten floors and died, his
death would have proved he was genetically unfit? So whether my kitten was fit
or unfit to survive depended entirely on whether his acrobatic exploring was
carried out on a second floor balcony or a tenth floor balcony. So the actual
distance fallen would have in some way transformed the genes of the kitten from
superior to inferior genes. As he passed the fifth floor on his way down his
genes instantly deteriorated, as his survival chances diminished. If on the
other hand I had yelled out to someone to catch him on the way down, or if a
neighbour below had put up his sun umbrella to break the kitten’s fall, the
kitten’s genes would have been instantly transformed back
to superior genes, as a bright and promiscuous future stretched before
him.
Does this absurd
scenario demonstrate that the inherent characteristics of a living being cannot
depend on some event which happens to it later in time? The inheritable genetic
traits of an individual, and whether or not they are favourable ones, cannot be
dependent on whether or not it is struck down by accidental death.
And yet this is
the absurd idea that underlies any belief that accidents have some genetically
selective function, that accidents cull the unfit, and that their occurrence is
proof the animal had inferior genes. If a hyena attacks and devours a lame
antelope, the neo-Darwinist sagely points to the genetic cleansing effect, the
elimination of inferior genes. And if you point out that lameness is the result
of an accident, not a genetic condition, he will at once begin arguing that
accidents themselves are the result of a genetic condition. This idea is
essentially a belief in the occult. The further you go into Darwinism, the more
you realize it is a mode of thought that is closely akin to a magical,
superstitious, religious world-view. It is a modern form of belief in
pre-destination: that things were meant to happen that way by some hidden
divine plan. Natural selection is the modern equivalent of Calvin’s divine
election. Premature death by accident is God’s judgement on the
non-elect, the very proof that this individual was not chosen. It is the habit
of primitive minds to believe that nothing occurs by chance, that everything
was caused by God or demon. Everything happens for a purpose. If a boy on a
bike is killed by a drunk driver, the primitive religious mind will see this as
a divine sign that the boy would have come to no good. Such people would probably claim that those
killed at Hiroshima or Auschwitz or in the Twin Towers
must have had something wrong with them – or in Darwinian terms, must
have been genetically inferior. Only the unfit could be culled in this
spectacular way: their elimination is proof of their unfitness. Now however
repugnant this world-view may be, it is in fact the logical extension of Darwinism. Nothing happens by accident.
Everything is genetically pre-ordained. Every quality is the result of selection
over time, because the survival of each individual is the result of natural
selection. There is no room for accidents in this world. The fatal accident is
a selection, and is therefore genetically significant. It is astonishing that
this primitive religious outlook has made a come-back under the guise of
scientific Darwinism. It is a means by which impoverished minds cheer
themselves up in the face of life’s tragedies – in the way that
Darwin himself found consolation, after his beloved daughter Annie’s death from
illness, by reflecting that it had made the other children physically stronger
and more apt to survive. This belief is pure superstition.
Let us turn to
starvation. Superficially, this is more promising for the Darwinists, as hunger
taxes the physical resistance of the individual, and therefore might logically
lead to the survival of the stronger. In fact this is one of the few areas
where some research has actually been done into survival rates, which has given
what at first look like positive results for the notion of natural selection. Darwin’s famous finches on the Galapagos
islands have been studied by Rosemary and Peter Grant for over
twenty years and their mortality rates from starvation in severe drought years
have been recorded. These islands are useful for Darwinists because climatic
variations are so extreme that large numbers of birds die prematurely every few
years and the shores are littered with their corpses. It is therefore possible
to compare corpses and survivors and see if death shows any selective pattern.
In 1977 when 85 per cent of the finch species fortis on the island Daphne were
killed by drought, the Grant team found that the survivors were six per cent
bigger than the average of this species on the island before the drought. Now
this evidence was presented (by Jonathan Weiner in his study of their research)
as though the chief factor was the bigger beaks of the survivors: half a
millimetre increase in beak size was touted as meaning the difference between
life and death, because of the need for a strong beak to crack the big tough
seeds which were the only available food in drought conditions. This might look
at first sight as if a selection for a specific structural variation had been
observed here – bigger beaks relative to body size. But it turns
out that overall weight and wingspan were also bigger in the survivors, so this
was not a selection of a structural variation but of a mere size variation. The
bigger birds survived. 49 But it was also mainly the males that
survived: 150 out of 600 males but only “a pitiful remnant” of the females,
which are smaller (apparently about 25 birds, since the sex ratio was
afterwards one to six.) And it was the older birds which survived – the younger
birds born in the previous two seasons all died. So most of the survivors were
the oldest, most mature male birds – which would also,
coincidentally, be bigger than the average bird, and have bigger beaks. Now
this would tend to blur the results somewhat. Is this a selection of a
structural variation (beak size or shape – he claimed the survivors
had deeper beaks) or merely of a size variation, or a selection of the oldest
males, with perhaps more experience in finding seeds in tough times, and better
able to defend their food patch – since they are also the
biggest? This fudging of the characters selected is important: any selection
which is for age or sex rather than for size or structural variation is not
selecting inheritable genetic characteristics. You cannot have a species which
goes on having an overwhelming majority of mature males for several
generations. Moreover, since the mature survivors are likely to be the parents
of the immature losers, the elimination of the young is not a modification of
the gene pool – they will simply be replaced by more of the same by
their own parents who have survived. But the massacre of females operated by
the drought meant that the tiny handful of females left (only one sixth of the
number of the males, so presumably only 25) mated with only the very biggest
males. This made their offspring also bigger with slightly deeper beaks, “4 or
5 per cent deeper than the beak of their ancestors before the drought.” 50
It is largely through this extreme sex-ratio distortion, making the surviving
handful of females choose the biggest one sixth among surviving males, that the
growth in size among offspring was achieved. This does seem to be a faithful
reproduction in nature of the selective breeding process that a dog-breeder or
sheep-breeder might use to enlarge his animals – and it required a massacre of
96 per cent of the females and three quarters of the males to achieve it. This
would seem a somewhat exceptional circumstance in nature, and it poses a bit of
a problem. In order to get a 4 per cent change in beak size, we need to kill 96
per cent of the females (and condemn 96 per cent of the males to either death
or celibacy.) But how often does nature imitate to this drastic degree the
actions of a stock-breeder?
But there is a
twist to the tale. In early 1983, five and a half years after the drought which
apparently selected for big, mature male birds, there were torrential rains on
the island which led to luxuriant vegetation and a huge upsurge in breeding
among all the species of finches. They bred so profusely that when the rains
and vegetation diminished the next year, the “finches had
overshot the carrying capacity of their desert islands” and began to die
like flies of a new famine. But this time the selection was curiously for
smaller birds and for females. 51 This time, Weiner claimed, there
were fewer large seeds and more smaller seeds and the larger birds could not
get enough to feed their bigger appetites. So the survivors and their offspring
shrank in body size again to where they had been before the drought. Now this
is triumphantly proclaimed by Weiner to be an example of “oscillation” natural
selection – a species is modified in one direction by natural
selection and then is modified back again. This is trumpeted as an irrefutable
proof that Darwin
was right, and natural selection of specific characteristics with a survival
advantage has been proven to occur. But let us look at this argument more
closely.
Imagine a Caribbean village of a hundred people which is wiped out
by a tornado so that only fifteen people survive (the proportion of survivors
of the finch fortis in the 1977 drought.) It would be very unlikely that the
fifteen survivors would have exactly the same average profile for age, height,
weight and sex as the original one hundred. The elimination of 85 per cent
would certainly have modified the survivors in some direction, just by the laws
of chance. Perhaps they would be on average slightly older, taller, heavier,
and include a higher proportion of males than the original one hundred. Then
imagine after long years the village has just recovered to a hundred
inhabitants again and it is suddenly hit by another tornado. Again only fifteen
people survive. But this time what are their characteristics? If once again it
is the older, taller, heavier males that survive, one might start to think that
tornadoes select for these characteristics. In short we might be witnessing
some real evolution by natural selection here (though of course it won’t be able to be
sustained since we cannot have a permanent bias in the population towards older
males – age and sex-ratio distortions, which are typically caused by disasters
among humans, are not sustainable.) But if after the second tornado the fifteen
survivors prove to be younger, shorter, lighter and have more females among
them, then surely we will conclude that the alleged selection is merely the
result of chance. Chance cannot be expected to make a perfectly representative
selection that will mirror exactly the profile of the original population. Any
drastic selection always shows a bias in favour of some characteristics – but this bias
will be counteracted by a different bias the next time. By analogy, when you
make a random selection of eight cards from a pack, you will almost never get
two cards of each suit, reflecting the real composition of the pack. You may
get five red cards and no spades at all. And when you reshuffle the pack and
try again you may get six black cards and no hearts. Each time there will be
bias towards one suit, which will be counteracted next time by a different
bias. Every random selection shows random bias. The more drastic the selection
the greater the random bias. But the randomness is only apparent when you add
all the successive selections together.
Now one could
argue that this is what has been observed on the Galapagos
islands by the Grants and their team. The first famine of 1977
selected for older, bigger, mostly male birds. The second famine of 1984
selected for smaller birds, and mostly females. Over the longer time period no
evolution occurred. Weiner, bizarrely, regarded the first event as marking the “progress” of the species
(as if big must be beautiful) and the second as a “regression” back to the
starting point. One could argue, on the contrary, that the selection was random
each time. An accidental bias in the characteristics of survivors one time was
countered by the opposite bias the next time. But even if we can co-relate the
selection of big males one time and small females the next time to particular
causes – the size or type of seeds available in the famine conditions – this
does not subtract from the overall randomness of the events. In any famine some
foods will remain more available than others and will favour the specialists in
those foods. But if this availability itself is a random or chance event, and
switches from one food to another with successive famines, then the entire
event and the selection made will be, from a longer perspective, random. It
will not lead to any evolution by natural selection unless the availability of
only one particular food, which selects for a particular kind of bird, becomes
repeated and constant. All we can say is that varying environmental
catastrophes will select temporarily for big or small birds, males or females,
young or old, specialists in big seeds or in small. But so long as these
circumstances vary unpredictably with each disaster, there can be no sustained
natural selection leading to a directional evolution.
Survival in
conditions of famine may well be more a question of luck in stumbling on a food
source at the right time, rather than physical characteristics. It may also
depend on changing behaviour patterns, and learning to find new sources of
food. Animals do this all the time. Grisly bears learn to raid camping grounds
in national parks and go through rubbish bins, sparrows to haunt restaurants or
balconies, crows in some places to drop shellfish in the path of trucks at
traffic lights and wait for them to be split open. The kea, a New Zealand
mountain parrot which was once vegetarian, learned first to eat meat off drying
sheepskins on farms, and then to attack live sheep by burrowing into their
liver. Dolphins have learned to hunt fish in quite different ways in different
regions of the world. Altered behaviour is probably the best single defence
against famine, and often it is the result of a chance discovery, which is
quickly imitated by others of the species. Some British blue tits by chance
learned recently to peck through milk bottle tops to drink the milk, and the
behaviour spread like wildfire through all the blue tits in the country. 52
The fact that altered behaviour is the most immediate reaction to changed
circumstances is what led Lamarck to give primacy to behaviour in evolution:
changed behaviour, if it places different stresses on the organism, will then
lead over time to changed physical structure. But we will come back to that
later.
The attempt to
correlate survival to individual genetic characteristics on the Galapagos islands has in fact failed, despite the many
interesting observations made. The failure is demonstrated by the details of
the evidence gathered. The Grants point to one male bird which has fathered
several families, but none of his dozen offspring have managed to raise young
in their turn. He is a father of a dozen but not a grandfather. They refer to
him (jokingly, but in a manner typical of Darwinists) as a loser. 54
But the very fact that this bird has been very successful in transmitting his
genes, but that the inheritors of those “successful genes” have not been
successful in their turn, surely shows there is no such thing as successful
genes. It is not that this bird is a loser with a loser’s genes, but that
survival is a lottery and there are no genes of success. The genetic
characteristics which allegedly allowed this bird to survive have not allowed
his progeny to survive. There can be no more damning demonstration of the
fallacy of this entire ideology.
What we have said
of starvation, and of the large element of chance in surviving this danger,
also applies in varying degrees to other causes of death – cold, heat,
storms, floods and bush fires. But with cold there is perhaps some selection
for body size and shape, for thicker fur, better feathers or whatever. Certain
species of bird in North America, imported from Europe, have grown larger in
northern latitudes than southern, presumably as a defence against cold – since in larger,
rounder bodies, surface area (and therefore exposure to air) is less in
relation to body mass. Whether this greater body size has developed
collectively, through different behaviour in colder climates (more vigorous
movement, more compulsive eating, longer summer days for hunting), as Lamarck
might suggest, or through natural selection (the higher death rate of the
smaller) is another matter – but we should give selection the benefit of the
doubt. Once again, in exceptionally cold conditions for which the species is
not prepared, mortality will be so high that migration, modified behaviour and
luck in finding warmer places will probably make more of a difference to
survival than the tiny physical variations between individuals of the same
breed. But we shall give half a point to cold, as there does appear to be some
natural selection for body size.
Let us turn now to predation. This is the cause of death
that Darwinian evolutionists point to most often as a clear demonstration of
genetic selection and the survival of the fittest. There is an almost universal
and unquestioned belief that predators pick on the weakest specimens of a herd,
and it is automatically assumed this weakness is genetic weakness.
Here is Toronto University’s McGowan in the Raptor and the Lamb, describing a
lioness charging into a herd of zebra.
The big cat
selects her quarry..…. It was not the closest one but it failed to follow
the choreography of the herd quite as closely as the others. 55
After a luridly gory
description of the kill, he comes back to this point, and drives home the
moral.
The zebra that was killed by
the lioness was the one that failed to keep together with the rest of the herd.
The zebra’s behaviour may have been attributed to a number of
factors, ranging from its running ability to its spatial awareness. If the
behaviour had genetic components, the zebra’s unfavourable genes would
have been removed, by natural selection, from the gene pool, which is the sum total of genes in that breeding
population. 56
Here we have a clear
expression that this lioness is selecting a slightly bizarre and awkwardly
running zebra, with suspect genes, for the sake of biological cleansing, and
rendering the gene pool of this herd a lot healthier and better adapted.
The first point to make is: why would a lioness do this?
Why pick a genetically inferior specimen? Does the meat taste better? Are they
easier to kill? There must be some advantage in this for the lioness: otherwise
we are led to suppose some kind of cross species altruism, combined with
far-sighted ecological concerns for the future of the prey species. Why would a
lioness want to contribute to the general increase in speed and strength of the
zebras? Surely her interest would be the opposite: stop the strongest specimens
reproducing so that the future zebras don’t grow too fast and strong
for her and her cubs. If we are to lend the lioness some preternatural
selective ability, surely it would be a selective ability in her interest, not
the zebra’s?
Logically, what
would a lioness’s choice, as she charges into a herd of zebras, be
based on? Clearly, one thing only: ease of conquest. The individual that
predators choose will be based on their own convenience, not the evolutionary
health of the prey species. In the case described, the lioness may have
regarded this zebra, which she had panicked into separating slightly from the
others, as easier to bring down without danger from the hooves of the rest of
the herd. Why see anything more occult in her choice than that? It is a
standard hunting practice to rush at a herd and try to separate one animal from
the rest, and go for that one. And panic dispersal is purely random: no
individual can know which way the others will run, away from it or with it. To
read genetic qualities into this is superstition. It is like reading
significance into the fall of pick-up sticks. If the observer were able to
predict beforehand which zebra the lioness would go for, he might be on to
something. To rationalize it after the event is too easy. But let us look at
hunting more closely, to see whether its mechanism can have any genetically
selective effect. How does hunting work?
Large mammal predators are divided into cursor and ambush
predators. Their techniques of hunting differ. Lions are ambush predators
because they have good acceleration but they tire quickly and cannot run as
fast as most of their prey over any distance. Cursors such as wild dogs or
hyenas or wolves, on the other hand, are tireless runners. They stalk a herd,
separate off an individual target animal and may have to chase it over a long
distance to tire it out, or surround it in numbers and bring it down. Cursor
predators are often much smaller than their prey and being mostly canids
(members of the dog family) lack the opposable paws and sharp retractable claws
of felids (cats) to spring on a victim’s back and wrestle it down.
(Cheetahs, felids with canid-like claws, behave like something between a cursor
and an ambush predator – they are short-distance cursors.) These differences
lead felids and canids, or ambush and cursor predators, to make different
choices of individual prey, even when they are both hunting the same
species.
Such studies of patterns of predation that have been done
provide no evidence for the notion of genetic selection, and considerable
evidence against it. Research by George Schaller in The Serengeti Lion (which McGowan himself quotes) reveals
interesting patterns among African predators.
“Lions kill zebras and wildebeests of all ages,
whereas cheetahs and leopards …. and wild dogs concentrate on young individuals…..And while lions
and cheetahs primarily kill healthy animals, hyenas tend to focus on sick ones.” It is instructive to correlate this with
success rates in hunting. “The hunting
successes of the lion, averaged for all hunts both day and night, varied from
14 per cent for reedbuck to 32 per cent for wildebeest .…. Hunting dogs
and cheetahs did considerably better, with average successes of all prey hunted
of 70 per cent.” 57
What can we deduce from all this? Firstly, it
is significant that the cursor predators,
which also tended to concentrate on the young, had a much higher success
rate. This would be logical in that cursor predators, such as Cape
hunting dogs, stalk a herd, choose their individual prey, separate it off, and
keep on chasing till they tire it out. Since they have as much stamina as their
prey, there is little chance of the prey escaping. Lions, on the other hand,
must succeed in bringing a prey down with their first charge, and if they fail
they give up, because they can’t keep up with their prey over a long distance.
Their rate of success is therefore lower, but they probably make many more
tries. It is interesting also that lions kill healthy animals of all ages. Of
course, unlike dogs and cheetahs which are much smaller than zebra and
wildebeest and will therefore prefer calves, lions are able to kill even the
largest individuals (not just because they are strong, but because they can
jump on their backs and hold on with their felid claws.) But there is perhaps
another reason for the lion’s eclecticism in the matter of age.
Lions are most
successful when they rely on collective ambush, in which two or three “killer” lionesses
conceal themselves in long grass or behind bushes or hillocks, while other
members of the pride encircle the herd of prey and drive it in panic towards
the ambush. Now the killer lionesses in this kind of ambush can exercise very
little selection. As soon as the herd arrives in stampede upon their
hiding-place, they leap frantically on the nearest. They must naturally try to
get one of the leading animals by surprise, because the others following behind
will see the danger and veer away. Thus the killer lionesses are often tackling
the fastest animals at the front of the herd. This explains why their prey are
generally healthy individuals: the sick ones would be too slow to be at the
front. And it explains their hit and miss record of success, since they are
often trying to stop very fit animals going at speed. Moreover, the wide range
of ages of their prey suggests a total lack of selection being exercised: they go
blindly for the nearest individual, young or old. Death is a lottery. No
genetic selection can reasonably be expected to result from this kind of
random, opportunistic predation.
Now let us look at cursor predators, which are mainly
canids. Wild dogs (such as Cape hunting dogs)
focus almost entirely on calves, which are easier for them to bring down.
Firstly the calf is a less vigorous runner and can be more easily caught.
Secondly it is not as heavy or steady on its feet and can be dragged down by
seizing one of its legs, which is important since canids cannot spring onto its
back and bite its neck as felids can. Thirdly, it is less able to defend itself
with hooves or horns than an adult wildebeest or zebra, which could do damage
to a small hunting dog. For all these reasons, canids tend to pick calves,
which they try to separate by panicking and dispersing the herd.
It is different
for hyenas, which pick on sick or lame adults. This is perhaps because hyenas,
though they lack the sharp retractable claws of a felid and the springing power
to jump on a healthy adult zebra, are extremely aggressive and very strong.
They have jaws with exceptional gripping power, strong enough to crush bones,
so that once they manage to fasten them around the leg of a slow-moving animal,
they can probably drag it down however big it is. The problem with a
fast-moving healthy animal is getting their jaws round the leg, or being able
to get their teeth into its belly or udders which they like to rip as a way of
disabling their victim. Their crude hunting methods require a slow-moving prey.
On the other hand, a calf might not provide enough meat for a band of hungry
hyenas, which are voracious feeders and travel in big packs. The killing of a
small prey might lead to considerable civil strife as they all tried to get a
piece. All of this would dictate old, sick adults as their favourite prey.
Now in none of these cases – the random selection of the
nearest stampeding beast by an ambushing lioness, the killing of wildebeest calves
by wild dogs or cheetahs, or the killing of old sick adults by hyenas – is there the
slightest evidence of any genetic selection that will improve the gene pool of
the herd. Not one of these techniques of predation leads in any way to the “survival of the
fittest”. In the lion’s case it is random and the
ambushing lioness may well be killing the fittest specimen, the one leading the
stampede. And once a lioness gets its claws and teeth into the neck of a
wildebeest or antelope, the qualities of the individual animal count for little
in that unequal contest. How close the lioness has got to it, the lottery of
proximity, is all that determines outcome. In the wild dog’s case, the
selection of a calf is not the selection of a genetically weaker or inferior
specimen but merely of a circumstantially weaker one. Being young is not a sign
of genetic inferiority. The calf might have the best genes in the herd and
still be singled out for attack because of its youth. As for the hyena, killing
old and sick animals is not going to affect the gene pool since these animals
are not going to breed any more anyhow. They are genetic deadwood, whether they
have already reproduced or not, and their elimination will make no genetic
difference to the herd. In none of the typical cases of predation by major
predators whose killing habits have been carefully observed can we detect the
slightest pattern that resembles Darwinian natural selection – the elimination
of healthy but inferior specimens, which would otherwise breed and pass on
inferior genes.
The popular myth
that predators kill the weak and thereby strengthen the species is based on a
confusion between genetic weakness and circumstantial weakness. A three-day-old
calf is weak, but this is not a genetic weakness or inferiority. It may have
the best genes in the herd and still be chosen for the predator’s dinner because
it can be pulled down more easily by a wild dog. The same applies to an old
sick animal. It may have the finest genes in the herd, and may once have been the
fittest and most prolific female. It may have numerous offspring in this herd.
Old age has now made it weak, slow and vulnerable to disease, but its killing
will again have no effect on the genes of the herd, since it has already done
all its breeding. The notion that in killing the “weak” – the very young
or the very old and sick – a predator
is improving the genes of the herd by removing inferior animals that would
otherwise breed, is a popular superstition, raised to the level of scientific
theory. Even in the tiny percentage of cases of animals born deformed,
defective or sickly, the predator is not removing genes from the pool, since
these sickly runts would not breed anyway. Natural selection is not the removal
of runts or congenital defectives. By definition it must be the elimination of
healthy animals capable of breeding, but whose inferior genes would not
contribute to the adaptive improvement of the species. That is the only way it
can work as a mechanism for evolution. And that is a kind of natural selection
that no pattern of predation that has ever been observed can possibly lead to.
When one considers the effect of predation upon birds,
there is a similar lack of any evidence that any genetic selection is taking
place. A good number of baby birds are killed in the nest, when a weasel or
hawk manages to get to it. No individual qualities in the prey are going to
give them the slightest chance against that sort of visitor. Among most bird
species, the greatest losses are in the egg stage, or among the very young
nestlings, whose helplessness makes them vulnerable. This weakness and
vulnerability scarcely varies between individuals of the same age (any more
than when they were eggs.) One would hardly argue that a weasel that ate three
eggs and left one was eliminating the inferior eggs. If it eats three baby
birds and leaves one, this is the same randomness. It stops when it has had
enough – not because it has come upon a nestling with a
formidable right hook. Even among adult birds preyed on by other birds, death
is generally a lottery. McGowan describes the way a colony of Eleanora’s falcons on an
island off the coast of Crete ambush at dawn the autumn migration of birds from
Europe to Africa. “They spread out
on a broad front, keeping about 100-200 yards apart … The broad net
strung across the sky is a formidable barrier to migrants that have to overfly
the island.” 58 The falcons
attack as soon as the swarms of migrant birds come into view. Though only 11% of individual strikes are
successful, some falcons kill as many as a dozen birds and take each one back
to their nests before returning to the fray. McGowan compares the scene to the
Battle of Britain. Since the prey don’t fight back, it is perhaps
more apt to compare it to a row of machine-guns firing into wave after wave of
charging troops. One would hardly dare suggest that the machine-gun culls the
genetically inferior soldiers – those who are less good at running or dodging
bullets. The testimony of most war veterans is that in this kind of attack it
is pure chance who the bullets kill. What evidence is there that any more than
chance is involved in the culling carried out by these falcons?
But the more fanatical proponents of the Darwinian theory
of natural selection may actually be mad enough to believe that soldiers killed
by machine guns, or by a shell landing in a trench, are being culled on genetic
grounds. If they believe it of migrant birds or zebra, why not believe it of
men? Darwin
apparently believed it – Wallace took issue with him on it. And Darwin’s disciple Hitler
certainly believed it. He was convinced that war killed off the weakest – those “unequal to the
storm of life.” His own wounding in the First World War by gas did
not seem to shake this belief. If army medical care had been less good, Hitler
might have died. Does this mean that he would have had inferior genes? Did the
quality of his genes then depend on the quality of Wehrmacht medical care? The
patent irrationality of this belief did not faze him. The idea that war kills
off the weak and selects the strong for survival was such a fundamental part of
Hitler’s worldview that doubting it was not an option. This
is not too dissimilar to the faith of many modern Darwinists. Natural selection
is the basis of their world view. Predation must be genetically selective,
killing off the inferior genes. To doubt it is like doubting the earth is
round. No amount of evidence from individual cases will convince them of the
contrary. This is a universal principle and no demonstration of its limitations
can cast doubt on it.
Of course there
may be some neo-Darwinists who accept that predation by lions or birds of prey
is genetically selective, but refuse to believe that the machine gun or the
bomb are genetically selective. It would be interesting to hear them justify
the distinction. Hitler and Darwin in applying the same theory to animals and
people are at least consistent. Once this superstitious principle is accepted
it must surely be universal. If predators somehow seek out inferior genes, why
not human predators? Why would nature grant this preternatural selective
capacity to a falcon or a lion and not to a machine-gunner or a bomber pilot?
Darwinian natural selection logically implies Hitler’s conclusions:
the guns and bombs of war kill off the weaker individuals and strengthen the
species, and war is therefore good for mankind.
I do not wish to imply by these parallels that all
Darwinists have a fascist cast of mind. On the contrary, the problem is that
many Darwinists want to believe in genetic selection of prey precisely because
it is the only way the ferocious ways of nature can be made to seem vaguely
benign. If you believe that the prey being torn to pieces are inferior
individuals, and that this gruesome process is improving the gene pool and
furthering evolution, then you have a sort of justification of the harsh ways
of nature. If you believe that the baby turtles racing down the beach after
hatching are being culled by sea-birds in function of their individual genetic
qualities, rather like an 11+ exam, then you have a sense that the universe,
even if severe, is fair. If, on the other hand, you believe that predation is a
purely random, purely quantitative decimation of the prey species without any
genetic selection whatever, and without any evolutionary purpose being served
by it, then nature looks extremely cruel and wasteful. The desire to moralize
the universe is the fundamental impulse behind Darwinism. And in moralizing the
universe, Darwinism falsifies it. We have not the slightest scrap of evidence
for asserting that the universe is moral, or that its overall plan is for
adaptive improvement, or that species are in fact improving, or that there is
any general progress towards anything whatsoever. One of the more amusing
ironies of the hilarious debate between Darwinists and Christian Creationists
is that both sides are descendants of different currents of Protestant
fundamentalism. Both are devoted to proving that the power controlling the
universe is harsh but just. They simply see that power slightly differently.
Predation, we must conclude, is not sufficiently
selective to have any genetic effect on a species, any more than the Blitz
improved the breed of Londoners by killing off those too slow or stupid to make
it to the shelters. But are there any characteristics of prey that might
possibly be selected by predation? What about camouflage? Surely those animals
less well camouflaged will be caught more easily than those better camouflaged?
The huge problem here of course is that camouflage usually varies little within
a species, or at least within a variety of a species. Where we see big
differences in camouflage we are probably already looking at different
varieties, if not different species. This still begs the question of how they
became different varieties or species, and whether the minute variations of
individuals were in any way selected in this process. The classic example of
alleged Darwinian evolution taught in every British school is the peppered moth,
which spends a good part of its time clinging to trees. In Manchester in the nineteenth century the
darkening of trees by pollution led to a decline in the numbers of light-winged
moths and a rise in the numbers of dark-winged moths. As the trees darkened,
the dark-winged moths were better camouflaged, were seen less by birds and
survived in larger numbers, while the light-winged moths were eaten. This is
clearly the effect of predation and effective camouflage on the relative
survival rates of different moths. But is this an example of Darwinian
evolution by natural selection, as it is triumphantly proclaimed to be? The
crux of the matter is whether the dark-winged moth can be shown to have been a
more recent mutation from the light-winged one or not. Was it a new variety
that developed in response to the darkening of the trees? Or was it simply a
different pre-existent variety, which was favoured by the change in
environment? This latter case would not be one of evolution. 59 It
is simply a case of one variety doing better than another in changed
conditions. To say one evolved into the other is a very different assertion. If
mosquitoes are favoured by a hot climate and fleas by a cold one, then a drop
in temperature may lead mosquitoes to die out in that region and fleas to
proliferate. But we can hardly say that the mosquitoes have evolved into fleas.
All the evidence suggests the darker peppered moths were a pre-existing variety
predating the industrial revolution. Weiner, recounting the story of the moths
as another irrefutable proof of natural selection, makes this damning admission
without realizing its significance:
Before the
industrial revolution the black form was under strong negative selection
pressures and the mutation stayed rare, except in forests with mostly black
barked trees. Factories reversed the selection pressure because the rare moths
looked like soot themselves. The case of the peppered moth gave evolutionists
their first inkling of the speed of Darwin’s process. 60
Translated from the jargon,
this means the black moths, which could only flourish where there were black
trees, suddenly expanded in numbers when the number of black trees grew. The
white moths that needed white trees to hide grew fewer when white trees became
rare. That this should have astonished anyone is in itself astonishing. To have
this described as “Darwin’s process” is even more
astonishing. Where is the evolution? Where is the modification of a species?
Where is the natural selection of particular individuals? Since this black
mutation predated industrial soot, the question still remains: how did it
arise? If the Darwinists had proved that natural selection caused this variant
form to arise – that individuals were culled in a selective manner that
favoured particular gradations of colour within the same variety so that the
colour gradually shifted, causing a genetic change – they would have scored a
point. But they have not shown that. This is not a species with a range of
colours, of which darker and darker shades were gradually selected during
industrialization. It is two distinct pre-existing varieties, one black, one
white, of which one was favoured and the other disadvantaged by a particular
change in their habitat (a process now being reversed as the trees lighten
again and the white variety makes a comeback.) This is not evolution. It is
simply a population shift, such as occurs all the time in nature as conditions
change. The human population of Tasmania
was once black. Whites arrived, wiped out the blacks by massacre and infectious
diseases, and replaced them. Could we say that the blacks of Tasmania have evolved into whites? It is
doubtful if even the Darwinists would claim this. Neither of these varieties of
human has evolved in any way over this period. Their relative numbers have
simply changed. And the same applies to the two varieties of peppered
moth.
When we get to the last cause of premature death among
animals – disease – we are finally on to
something that is probably genetically selective. It is the only one we will
give a full point to, in addition to the half point given to cold. Disease
kills those individuals with less resistance to it, and leaves alive those with
more resistance. Catching the disease and surviving it may also increase immunity.
Death by disease is therefore clearly a field for the operation of natural selection, which will
make a population (or its survivors) more resistant to that disease. This seems
to be how Europeans built up resistance to the influenza, measles and other
viruses, which then killed off Amerindians and Polynesians in droves when
Europeans went near them. So let us grant the Darwinists one point here. The
only drawback to the idea of selection by disease is that a disease cannot
select for any quality except resistance to that disease. It cannot select for
narrow beaks or wide antlers or long necks or trunks or retractable claws. This
is a fatal limitation if one wishes to find here the mechanism for all
evolution. Only if you could prove some association between resistance to a
disease and some structural modification would you be able to make the case for
disease-selection being a factor in the evolution of the elephant’s trunk.
All together we have come up with a poor score for
natural selection: one point for disease and half a point for cold out of the
six causes of premature death. But the problem is that even this poor score – the fact that
disease selects for resistance to disease, and cold may select for a larger
body size – is probably enough to reinforce the Darwinists in
their basic world view. “You see, natural selection does occur!” they will cry
triumphantly, pointing to kinds of selection that cannot possibly be
responsible for any structural evolution in animals whatsoever. But to its followers,
natural selection is not a scientific theory, to be proved or disproved: it is
an ideology, even a faith. It is the basis of an entire world-view. Evidence
may be found for it, but never against it. Once a single crude example of it
has been shown to occur, its proponents imagine they have demonstrated its
universal operation and its myriad detailed effects. They think that once they
have shown that a parrot can repeat “pretty Polly” then they have proved it is
only a matter of time before it learns to recite “The Rime of the Ancient
Mariner” or the Gettysburg Address. The chief problem with natural selection is
not that no example of it can be found, but that its proven effects are by
their nature so limited and crude that it cannot be the main motor of a process
as precise and sophisticated as evolution. So far in all the causes of
premature death we have found selection for disease-resistance and size. Is
that really enough to explain how the elephant got its trunk, or the cat its
retractable claws?
9) DARWIN’S
SECOND STRING: SEXUAL SELECTION
Now these drawbacks to the functioning of natural
selection by means of premature death are probably what led Darwin to focus in his later work on another
method of selection: sexual selection. Animals leave different numbers of
offspring. Surely this difference will lead to the selection of certain
characteristics over time. This forms the theme of his later book The Descent of Man.
Now the idea of
invoking sexual selection was on the surface a promising one. For it had the
potential to get around one of the most damaging objections to the theory of
natural selection. Evolution, Darwin
believed, is a slow accumulation of tiny modifications over many generations,
and such small variations are not going to be enough in just one generation to
make the difference between life and death. If we take a giraffe, a difference
in neck-length of a centimetre in one individual, if repeated for a hundred and
fifty generations will add a metre and a half to the neck, and give the giraffe
vital access to the high leaves no other animal can reach. But this first
centimetre will hardly be enough to give this individual a decisive advantage
in one lifetime, so that others die out and he survives. So how does the process
of evolution towards long necks get launched, how does this individual get “selected” for his
advantage, when the first centimetre will make no difference to survival
chances? One might have expected Darwin
to argue that these tiny structural differences might make a difference in
rates of reproduction. The females might possess a preternatural flair for
guessing which male is going to be better adapted a couple of hundred
generations down the line, and make sure he leaves a numerous progeny. Just as
a centimetre difference in a man’s nose might make him look
more handsome to a woman, so a centimetre extra on a giraffe’s neck might make
it more desirable to a female giraffe. In actual fact Darwin doesn’t go down this
path. He doesn’t invoke the selective prescience of the female as a
way of solving one of the basic problems of his theory. He merely contents
himself with laboriously detailing the ways in which females of various species
seem to choose males, and how this choice itself must have affected their evolution.
While this is at times fascinating it leads nowhere. This is because all he can
show is that sexual selection operates in the evolution of armaments and
useless ornaments – long tails, bright colours, ruffs, whistles, etc.
It is not capable of selecting for anything else, or setting in motion any
major structural change. It explains, in short, why the male elephant has long
tusks, or is bigger than the female, but it takes us no further in
understanding how the elephant got its trunk. Sexual selection of the good
fighters among males can develop nothing but size and armaments. Sexual
selection of those males who win display contests can lead to nothing but an
evolution of beautiful and spectacular ornaments. Where does the rest of
evolution – all the functional parts of animals, which are
essential in food-gathering, and which have undergone the most extraordinary
variation – come from?
The basic principle of sexual selection seems simple:
females choose mates they fancy. Darwin
argues that the elaborate ornamental displays of the males of certain species,
especially birds – their colourful ruffs, crests and tails, their
courting rituals, songs and dances – all constitute
an attempt to influence female choice in mates. This choice must therefore be
real, and must have influenced the evolution of these same display features in
the male. He argues convincingly that in
species where the sexes differ most, and where the male has gone to the
greatest trouble to evolve attractive or impressive features, there is acute
competition between the males for mates because the species is not monogamous,
but a harem or arena species. A harem species, one will recall, is one where a
single male has a herd of females, which he must fight other males to keep, and
an arena species is one where all the males gather in the breeding season and
joust for top dog positions at the centre of the stamping ground, the winners
being rewarded by being able to service all the females. In most monogamous
species, there is little development of ornaments in the male, and the sexes
resemble each other much more. It is
clearly therefore because of the differential breeding rates in harem and arena
species – the fact that one lucky male mates with a multitude
of females and other males miss out – that these remarkable
ornamental features of the male have developed in these species. The male with
the longest tail or the brightest crest is the one that gets to mate with all
the females, and this extreme characteristic therefore keeps getting developed
in the species. And these ornaments have not developed in monogamous species
because in the latter there are no such differential breeding rates. It is a
convincing argument, and few people can put down The Descent of Man without being convinced that sexual selection
has operated in the development of these striking male ornaments in the species
concerned. The only problem is Darwin
has not demonstrated it operates in any other species, or for any other
features. The failure to develop such striking display features in the vast
majority of species (which are not harem or arena species) suggests that huge
differences in breeding rates do not occur in most species and that sexual
selection therefore has very little effect on their evolution.
Moreover, in the
course of this argument, Darwin
demonstrates convincingly that the sole features that interest the choosy
female are purely ornamental. These features are not related to food gathering,
predator evasion, protection or feeding of the young, or any other useful skill
or characteristic. They are simply attention-getting devices serving to win
mates. The utter uselessness of the features is the main point Darwin
emphasizes – as against his colleague Wallace, who thought that
these ornaments must be merely the outward signs of health, vigour or some
other useful quality. Darwin
argues on the contrary that the very uselessness of the ornamental features
proves how important attracting a mate is in these species. Breeding is the
goal of life, and the creature evolves in a competitive effort to fulfil this
goal. The very arbitrariness of the female’s taste is proof of its
absolute value. Once this taste exists it becomes self-justifying and
self-perpetuating. The female will be attracted to those features that she
knows other, future females will be attracted to – thus favouring
her own genetic survival, by ensuring that her male offspring will do well in
future breeding contests. So the qualities she selects have no advantage
whatsoever except that she is attracted to them. They include such useless
things as crests, ruffs, bright colours, long tails, silly dances and whistles,
which can have no practical purpose, and may even make the male more
conspicuous and an easier target for predators. It has even been found that
species such as the Irish elk, developing larger and larger antlers in order to
win herds of females from rivals, actually died out because of this, since
their huge antlers made them incapable of running away from predators in
forests. It is clear that the very long tails of peacocks and other male birds
in arena species are similarly a huge disadvantage for predator evasion. So
much for fitness. So much for “adaptive improvement”. Darwin’s entire
demonstration of the operation of sexual selection only serves to prove that it
operates at full force mainly in a number of harem or arena species which have
become in fact beautiful freaks, evolutionary eccentricities or genetic dead
ends, which may well be expected to become extinct the moment anything happens
to upset the balance of their habitat. Apart from these cases of useless
ornament, he fails to show how sexual selection can have any effect on the
species, except for the simple, crude result (in the case of actual fighting
between them) of making the males bigger and better armed.
His problem, in short, is that this kind of sexual
selection for ornaments operates at its most intense in arena species, but
these do not make up even one per cent of the mammal and bird species. What about
monogamous species and promiscuous species? With these two kinds, both of which
often show no great difference between the male and the female in size or
ornaments, there seems little evidence that sexual selection has operated on
their evolution, and little scope for it to do so. Among promiscuous species
there can be no effective sexual monopoly. Chimpanzees live in tribes which
have a certain pecking order, and the pecking order of the males seems in
theory to determine who gets first shot at whichever female is in heat. But
lower-level chimpanzees often gang up on the top male to trick him out of the
female and enjoy her behind his back, so to speak. Moreover, the females in
heat may accept several males one after another, and it is something of a lottery
whose sperm is going to come out on top. It has been argued that this inability
to monopolize females leads the males of promiscuous species to develop bigger
testicles and shoot more sperm in a desperate attempt to get their seed in the
pole position inside the uterus. This would be unnecessary unless there was a
strong probability that several lots of sperm would be in there together,
jostling at the starting blocks. Because of the usefulness of the other males
in hunting and defence, the alpha male in fact tolerates their sexual
competition, in what appears to be an instinct to promote the group’s genetic
survival, rather than his own. The same has been observed among multi-male lion
groups, which co-operate in their ownership of the females of a territory,
rather than bitterly competing for them. Among such promiscuous tribal species
there is, in effect, collective fatherhood, and anything less selective it is
hard to imagine. 61
In the case of
monogamous species, who dominate the bird kingdom (around 99 per cent of
species are seasonally monogamous, and some mate for life), and are well
represented among animals, it is even harder to prove sexual selection. This is
because, while choice is undoubtedly exercised in pairing, it is not usually “selection” in the Darwinian
sense: that is, it is not a selection as to who will breed; it is a choice of
who will breed with whom. A rejected suitor of one becomes the successful
suitor of the next, as among humans. Since the sexes are of roughly equal
number, the vast majority of individuals end up pairing, whether they are at
the top of the ladder of attractiveness or near the bottom – just as they do
among people. If sexual selection were to have an effect on the evolution of
monogamous species, one would have to prove either of two things: that there is
a huge difference in the numbers of offspring of different couples (not merely
at the extremes but in the bulk of cases), or that a large number of
individuals fail to mate at all. Now neither of these has been proven. It is
only in environmental catastrophes that a huge proportion of a monogamous
species fails to mate, because of the wiping out of most of one sex, as
happened during the drought on Daphne in the Galapagos in 1977 described
already. But catastrophes of this sort are rare. Under normal circumstances,
the vast majority of individuals reaching adulthood in monogamous bird species
(around 80% in the case of robins) generally find a territory and a mate.
Though there is lots of squabbling among them until pairs are formed, almost
everyone eventually finds a shoe to fit his foot – whether big,
small, fat, thin, pretty or ugly, just as among humans. What happens to the
twenty per cent of solitaries is not clear; they may even simply act as a pool
of reserves, replacing the casualties that fall to predators. It was noted by Darwin, as we have mentioned,
that widows and widowers in bird couples remarry very quickly and often the
next day: a hunter no sooner shoots one of a couple, than the survivor finds a new
mate. This would suggest that the solitary twenty per cent are like reserve
players, or like wallflowers at a dance. Unimpressed by the remaining singles
available, they wait for a widow or widower, who are perhaps hotter numbers. Or
they may simply be victims of a dearth of decent territories; like the
homeless, they wait for an apartment to fall half vacant, and rush in to share
it. Until figures are collected for the percentage of adult birds of monogamous
species which never mate, we are justified in assuming it is very small.
Now there is, of
course, some difference in breeding success among bird couples. But differences
may be circumstantial, and successive seasons might see very different results
for the same individuals. It is also by no means certain that the breeding
success of one bird or couple will be repeated by its offspring. As we saw
above, in one of the few long-term research projects where biologists have got
to know individual birds in a breeding population, that of the Grants on the Galapagos islands, they mention birds which have had
several successful families, but have no grandchildren. Their own success was
not repeated by the next generation. This would bear out the notion that
breeding is something of a lottery with no discernible patterns of the
long-term success of particular genes. It is also significant that most bird
species tend to have an optimum clutch size, or number of eggs laid, which the
majority of them keep to. Going above it to lay a lot more eggs and raise a lot
more offspring leads to a negative trade-off in the quality of feeding provided
and the size of the offspring when they leave the nest. It has been found that
a higher clutch size than the optimum will lead to more of the young birds
dying both before and just after they leave the nest – being smaller,
they may have less vigour in finding food. 62 This suggests that
real competition among birds to raise lots more offspring than their neighbour
is rather limited. Most of them raise a
similar number. And chance, in the form of a cat or a hawk taking an interest
in their tree, will probably have more of an effect on outcome than any
variations in vigour among different couples. Darwin himself was well aware of
these difficulties with his theory of sexual selection. He tells us with rather
disarming honesty:
I have not
attempted to conceal that, excepting when the males are more numerous than the
females, or when polygamy prevails, it is doubtful how the more attractive
males succeed in leaving a larger number of offspring to inherit their
superiority in ornaments or other charms than the less attractive males; but I
have shown that this would probably follow from the females – especially the
more vigorous females which would be the first to breed, preferring not only
the more attractive but at the same time the more vigorous and victorious
males. 63
Let us study this sentence
closely. Having admitted that it is by no means clear how the allegedly more
vigorous or attractive males could manage to leave more offspring than the rest
in monogamous species, he then relapses into what the unkind might call popular
superstition, folklore and anthropomorphism. He claims that he has “shown” that “this would
probably follow” from what he considers the natural preference of
females for the “more vigorous and victorious males”. Apart from this
anthropomorphic analogy, he doesn’t offer us much to go on
here. It is in fact a disarming appeal to us to accept what he has not proved.
It is an example of what one critic of Darwin
has described as a technique of admitting a weakness of his theory only to turn
this very candour into a convincing argument for it – as though his
very honesty were the proof of his irreproachable scientific method. It is a
mere trick of rhetoric. And that is really what the whole theory of sexual
selection rests on, once one leaves aside the small number of arena and harem
species where differential breeding obviously occurs – and where its
effect seems confined to ornaments and armaments. There is no more evidence
that superior specimens have more offspring among monogamous birds than among
monogamous humans. But even in saying that we have suddenly touched a subject
where the neo-Darwinists, one might say, have had a field day.
10)
A DIGRESSION ON SEXUAL SELECTION AMONG HUMANS
The difficulty in
showing that sexual selection operates in any but the very few species (harem
and arena species) where sexual monopoly of many females by one male is
obvious, has not stopped the Darwinists. They assume as an axiom a principle
that they have not proved, by a simple appeal to common sense – as if it couldn’t be otherwise.
In fact, underneath the discussion of sexual selection among animals and birds
lies an unquestioned assumption that it happens among humans. Again there is
systematic confusion between the notions of sexual choice and sexual selection.
Because human beings (or their parents) choose their marriage partners and some
partners are clearly seen as more desirable than others, it is taken for granted
that the more desirable partners have more offspring (which is what sexual
selection means.) But is it true that Miss Universe and Mr Universe have more
children than the rest of us? Do the most attractive Hollywood
film stars have more children than their gardeners and plumbers, just because
more people desire them? Are rich men or powerful rulers always more prolific
than the poor and downtrodden? Are Bill Gates and George Bush fathers of a
dozen children apiece? That is what sexual selection means. But have the
Darwinists produced the slightest scrap of evidence for it?
Darwin, to his credit,
does try to examine how the sexual and marital habits of various societies of
the remote past may have given rise to sexual selection (which is more than his
modern followers have done.) He cites the anthropological research of his own
age, notably that of Morgan, on the “communal marriage” believed to have
been practised in early tribal societies. But this communal marriage did not
allow sexual monopoly at all, as women were common property. Then when monogamy
developed, it is hard to see how differential breeding occurred, given the
strength of human jealousy and the almost universal prohibition of adultery.
Anecdotal evidence is cited of a certain number of “savage” societies where
the stronger men simpler took the pretty wives of weaker ones by force. No
attempt is made to show how widespread this kind of lawlessness and tyranny may
have been, and Darwin
accepts that this sort of behaviour may have characterized “savage” societies only
in their present degenerate state. In fact, whenever Darwin examines the question closely he finds
objections to the notion of sexual selection, and lists what he calls the
“checks to its operation”, including widespread infanticide and child
betrothals. But his analytical, sceptical
intelligence is forever being overridden by an ideological conviction
that he keeps coming back to and repeating as a kind of mantra to convince
himself:
The strongest and most vigorous men …. would succeed
in rearing a greater average number of offspring than the weaker and poorer
members of the same tribes. There can also be no doubt that such men would
generally be able to select the more attractive women. 65
And he goes on to say that
“after the lapse of many generations” this would “modify the character of the
tribe.” He believes the sexual selection operates in both directions:
For
the women would generally choose not merely the handsomest men … but those who
were at the same time best able to defend and support them. Such well-endowed
pairs would commonly rear a larger number of offspring than the less favoured.
The same result would obviously follow in a still more marked manner if there
were selection on both sides; that is, if the more attractive, and at the same
time more powerful men were to prefer, and were preferred by, the more
attractive women. 66
But it is still not clear
how this choice of more attractive females by the stronger males would lead to
these females being more prolific than others. Why would the prettiest females
have more children than the plainer ones in a monogamous society? He has
already admitted that in primitive societies it is the women who tend to do the
work in the fields and hence put food on the table, so family size is not
proportionate to the male’s ability as provider. But why then should it be
proportionate to the female’s attractiveness? Are attractive women more fertile
than their plainer sisters? There is an element of sexual fantasy here. But
above all the belief is driven by his ideological convictions, which are
powerfully restated at the end of the book:
Man,
like every other animal, has no doubt advanced to his present high condition
through a struggle for existence consequent on his rapid multiplication; and if
he is to advance still higher, it is to be feared that he must remain subject
to a severe struggle. 67
This sounds eerily
reminiscent of Hitler’s statement quoted above: “Mankind has grown
great in eternal struggle, and only in eternal peace does he perish.” However, Darwin draws only a
eugenicist not a militarist conclusion:
....There
should be open competition for all men; and the most able should not be
prevented by laws or customs from succeeding best and rearing the largest number
of offspring. 68
“Should not be prevented by
laws or customs” – as the mollycoddling, bleeding heart welfare state was
already beginning to do, or so he feared. This is the world-view which
underlies all Darwin’s attempts to discover sexual selection in the
remote past – the need to reverse the present calamitous tendency
of the poor to breed more than the rich, by asserting that it goes against
nature. Sexual selection of the best and strongest must have taken place
throughout the past: this is the axiomatic view that justifies restoring it by
a robustly competitive system in the present. And this is the conviction his
modern followers share. It has driven them to invent an extraordinary fantasy
world as they explore the manifold workings of a process of sexual selection
whose historical reality they have not made the slightest attempt to
demonstrate. An entire discipline, evolutionary psychology, has been built up
upon these fantasies.
With a blithe
disregard for the known marital habits and sexual behaviour of previous ages,
the evolutionary psychologists have constructed a fantasy picture of the past
where an extreme Darwinian sexual jungle allowed the strongest and most
attractive to vastly outbreed all the others and hence confer upon future generations
the qualities most desired by all. They are convinced that such characteristics
as courage, lying, pacifism, sensitivity, brutality, tidiness, untidiness,
musical tastes, promiscuity, fidelity, infidelity, a fondness for gardening, a
willingness to perform cunnilingus or to help with the dishes, are all to be
ascribed to sexual selection. No other explanation is possible. Since every
characteristic must be genetic, then whatever characteristics exist must have
been sexually selected – it is axiomatic, no evidence is needed for it. One
is tempted to ask these people: if all good qualities have emerged as a result
of sexual selection of particular genes, then what about bad qualities? Have
smelly feet, bad breath, snoring, potato noses, bad complexions, crooked teeth,
obesity, stupidity, round shoulders, a tendency to steal, to beat the wife, to
belch, to pick one’s nose – have all these
characteristics also been sexually selected? Did people really select these
qualities in their mates because they were attracted by them – thus filling the
gene pool with them? And if not, if these ugly characteristics were not
sexually selected, then on what grounds can we make this claim for the
attractive ones? If the gene for ears
that stick out was not sexually selected, but blundered through as part of the
aimless lottery of genetic recombination, then why should it be any different
for curly hair or white teeth?
The evolutionary
psychologists create an absurd game theory on the basis of what the rational
choices in a mate would be at any time and what features this would have
selected for. They then argue how the selection of these features would then
lead to the selection of other features, or how women’s choices would
affect men’s behaviour and then this behaviour affect women’s choices, and so
on in an endless game. But their ignorance of the historical conditions of
marriage in past ages reduces the whole procedure to nonsense. The fact is that
human pairing and reproduction is one of the least rational, least consistent
and least predictable phenomena that have ever existed. In most sexual
selection scenarios, female choice of male partners is taken for granted. Yet
from the beginning of history until the modern age, few girls were ever allowed
to choose their mate themselves: their parents chose for them. And the basis of
parents’ choice was usually economic position, not
personally pleasing qualities. Given these criteria of partner choice, if
sexual selection had had the enormous influence ascribed to it, then we would
have evolved into a species consisting entirely of rich male landowners and
beautiful women, since these have been the most sought after mates in all ages.
That we are in fact a species with many more ugly, stupid, and poor individuals
than beautiful, intelligent and rich ones suggests that sexual selection has
done a singularly mediocre job. The fact is that sexual desirability has seldom
decided who would reproduce or how much; it has only decided who would
reproduce with whom. The ugliest man might well have been turned down by all
the pretty girls (or their parents) and may have seen himself as a sexual
failure. This has never stopped him finally marrying a girl as ugly as himself
and fathering ten children. There is among the evolutionary biologists a
systematic confusion between the notion of sexual attractiveness – who is the most
desirable partner – and sexual selection – who leaves the most
offspring.
The whole
perspective of the neo-Darwinists, the evolutionary psychologists, game
theorists, and sundry other pop-science cranks is not much more than a popular
superstition. Its starting point seems self-evident: all the men want to screw
the prettiest girl at the dance. But the real question is: do they all screw
her? And does she have more children than anyone else? The simple answer is no.
The prettiest girl at the dance (if she lives in a society that allows her any
freedom in the matter) will make her choice among the men and have her children
with him, and that will be that. She has no tendency whatever to reproduce more
than anyone else. (If anything, her beauty may give her higher status and more
power in the relationship, which may lead her to limit her pregnancies more
than another.) Nor, contrary to popular myth, does the handsomest or strongest
man at the dance have a tendency to father more offspring. He might well be
able to choose the prettiest girl – but he does have to make a
choice, and one choice only. This is because we have not generally lived in a
state of anarchy where the strongest took whatever and however many he wanted.
In the overwhelming majority of societies that have ever been, the invention of
weapons and the power of clans very soon placed a limit on the tyranny of
individual strength to take what it wanted. In most societies we have records
of, the father and brothers of the first girl a man got pregnant would have
been round to see him the next day with
the local equivalent of the proverbial shotgun – and his
philandering days would have been strictly limited from then on. Most
philandering in history has in any case been confined to a class of
prostitutes, who did everything to avoid pregnancy. A man who goes through
thousands of prostitutes is quite likely to breed less than a respectable
father of six who has never looked sideways at another woman. Lord Byron, for
all his female conquests, probably left behind fewer children than his
coachman.
But the
neo-Darwinists are still ludicrously under the spell of that old romantic myth
of Rousseau’s (and before him Hobbes), the state of nature. They
seem seriously to believe that we spent long periods living in a state of
anarchy, without rules, where the strongest men took as many women as they
wanted and filled the world with their offspring. Yet nobody has ever discovered
any society living like this, or any evidence that any primitive tribe lived
like it in the past. In general the more primitive the society, the stricter
the rules governing breeding. The evolutionary psychologists point to a few
tyrants of Africa or Arabia who had hundreds
of wives and conclude that this was the universal practice of past ages. Their
comic-strip view of history is an indictment of modern university education,
which has left them crassly ignorant of every domain except their own. Here is
a highly popular evolutionary psychologist, Matt Ridley, on the subject: “In medieval
Europe, or ancient Rome,
powerful men took all the beauties into their harems, leaving a general
shortage of women for other men, so an ugly woman stood a better chance of
finding some man desperate enough to marry her.” 70 This is the comic book view of history which scientists from Oxford now hang their
scientific theories upon. It is the level of knowledge found on toilet walls.
Ridley’s picture of Rome
is that of a semi-literate maker of porn movies. There were no “harems” in
ancient Rome.
In fact the laws of Augustus fined citizens who did not marry, and no Roman was
allowed to have both a wife and a concubine. The only “beauties” who might have
been accumulated by powerful men were foreign slaves, and the purchase of these
would not have limited the choice in partners of anybody else, since Rome’s wars gave an
inexhaustible supply of them. Where did these Roman “harems” monopolizing all
the beautiful women come from except from Ridley’s overactive
imagination? The entire worldview of this pop-science is schoolboy fantasy.
The reality is
that the vast majority of human beings that lived before the industrial age
were born into a highly possessive and protective family, living near related
families in a closely-knit clan system, and were married according to the
wishes of their parents. Sexual repression and strict monogamy have been
overwhelmingly the norm of human history. As a general rule, the more primitive
the society, the more rigid its rules in the domain of breeding tended to be – the famous rules
of the much reviled patriarchy, where females were protected from predatory
seducers by father, brother or husband. And when they were not patriarchal,
societies were matrilineal and matrilocal – the husband came to live
with his wife’s family, under their thumb. There is simply no
evidence there has ever been a widespread “state of nature” or anarchy in human
breeding for any sustained period. Apart from a small minority of prostitutes
(who did everything to avoid pregnancy), women have been cloistered, veiled and
chaperoned, and forbidden to look sideways at another man, for most of human
history. Rapes, seductions, adulteries, and other acts dishonouring families have
been avenged by entire clans and even nations, in murderous fashion. It is hard
to see in these circumstances how a great deal of rampant sexual anarchy could
have gone on, or how the genes of the most powerful and attractive few could
have flooded the world.
Of course there
have been some promiscuous individuals, and in societies where tyrannical rule
existed, a few such men were able to give free rein to their impulses. Absolute
monarchs sometimes chose freely among their women subjects and had a string of
mistresses. However, in Europe these women
were seldom kept exclusively for the king’s use (being frequently
married or promiscuous themselves.) The fondness of monarchs for a succession
of other men’s wives or ladies of easy virtue hardly constitutes
the sort of sexual monopoly which would have influenced the gene pool or
limited other men’s range of choice. Perhaps in some African or Asian
countries where rulers kept harems of several thousand women, they may have had
enough children to have a local influence on the gene pool – though it would
have been diluted by the millions of ordinary peasants who have lived dull
monogamous lives since the dawn of history. In fact the prolific tendencies of
tyrants were often neutralized by their own more sanguinary practices. The
Ottoman Turkish Sultans had large harems, but the custom was for all the heir’s
brothers and half-brothers to be murdered the day he acceded to the throne. Nor
would large harems have caused gender imbalance as Ridley imagines: the abduction
of the prettiest girl in each village for the Sultan’s harem would
only have balanced the abduction of every fifth son for his army.
In the case of
European kings, the number of children of those who commanded the favours of a
cohort of mistresses is, where we have the evidence, surprisingly small. Since
royal bastards usually had a claim to wealth and advancement, they had every
reason to declare themselves, or be declared by their mothers. Yet the number
of such declared bastards, even of prodigious womanizers like Louis XIV or
Charles II of England,
is rather modest. Louis XIV acknowledged thirteen illegitimate children (in
addition to his six legitimate ones), Louis XV (called the Well-Loved) fathered
fifteen, Charles II of England acknowledged fourteen, Maximilian I of Austria
nine, William IV of England eleven. The all-category champion in England was
Henry I, who had twenty-three illegitimate children, and two legitimate. Now
these numbers might seem large, but (with the possible exception of Henry’s score) many
peasant families in the Middle Ages would have equalled them. Families of ten
were commonplace in the countryside well into the twentieth century all over
Europe, just as they are among the poor of Africa
and the Arab world today. Nor were the chances of survival of royal offspring
all that much better than anyone else’s – of Louis XIV’s six legitimate
children, entitled to every care and attention, only one made it to adulthood.
Someone has gone to the trouble of calculating that in all some one hundred and
fifty royal bastards were born to English kings over the past thousand years.
This tiny number would have had a negligible effect on the genes of the nation.
Considering their limitless opportunities, the breeding of Europe’s monarchs has
been remarkably restrained. It is clear that their interest was in sex, not
reproduction, and smart mistresses apparently found ways of avoiding pregnancy
in order to keep their figure and the royal favour.
Excessive royal
breeding has not therefore been a major factor in history; it has rather been
the opposite. Henry I, that champion breeder, lost his only legitimate son when
the White Ship went down in 1120. Charles II, for all his womanizing, left no
heir either. In fact one of the major problems of kings in history has been
their inability to breed at all. Henry VIII went through six wives and changed
his country’s religion in a futile attempt to produce a son. We
can certainly not conclude on this evidence that the randiness of royalty had
any significant genetic effect upon the species. Nor was this sort of thing
widespread further down the scale. It has recently been demonstrated that the
famous ius primae noctis or sexual
rights of the lord over his peasants’ daughters at marriage was a
popular myth. There is no evidence it was ever exercised; it lived chiefly in
folktales about tyrants. It appears to have been a fictitious “ancient right” invented to
justify a marriage tax in lieu of it.71 Among the aristocratic class
a certain libertinism was often the rule, but it had as its object sex, not
breeding, and the class of courtesans and ladies of fashion became expert at
preventing or terminating pregnancies. Yet if among kings and aristocrats we
cannot find any substantial evidence of the proliferation of the genes of an
attractive or powerful few because they left far more offspring than others,
then where else can we find evidence that such sexual selection took place at
all?
The truth is that
this so-called scientific theory rests on the flimsy basis of popular
superstition and gross ignorance. Darwin’s reflections on
this subject are on the same level of Victorian pseudo-science as phrenology or
racism. They are based on a Victorian fear of the rising numbers of the
proletariat, who were breeding at twice the rate of the upper class. The
British working class in the late nineteenth century had on average nearly
twice as many children as the professional and upper classes – 5.11 as opposed
to 2.8 children per female. 72 This was a great worry throughout the
nineteenth century to the Malthusian Whigs – the milieu of Darwin’s family – and was one of
the reasons for the Poor Law, separating couples in the workhouse so that they
couldn’t breed more paupers. It was an article of faith
among the Social Darwinists and eugenicists that this trend was a reversal of
the universal pattern of the past – that in the good old days
the superior people had bred far more (and we should recreate the conditions
where this would happen again.) The more prolific breeding of superior
individuals was a creed, an ideology, which Darwin sought to promote by proclaiming it a
principle of nature. In fact there is no evidence that it was true at any stage
in human history. The class of aristocrats in most ages had fewer children than
the peasants, largely because their women had more access to whatever means of
contraception were available at the time, and had more power (relatively) to
stand up for the right not to be permanently pregnant. Under the Roman empire it was a source of constant worry to rulers
like Augustus that the aristocrats bred so much less than the common people. It
has been estimated that by the third century AD the vast majority of Romans
were descended from foreign slaves. 73 This pattern seems to have
been common in other ages too. As one great historian put it, “it remains a good
rough working rule that fecundity varies inversely with income.” 74 The proliferation of the poorest appears to be one of the constants
of history, as we can see from the relative birth-rates of Africa and Europe today. In Europe,
too, oppressed and impoverished minorities, such as (till recently) the
Kosovars and the Romanian gypsies, seem to have been remarkably prolific.
Darwinists such
as Dawkins and Ridley, who make sweeping statements about the most powerful men
in all ages having more offspring than the average, are retailing an urban myth
refuted by all the facts of history. The four most powerful conquerors Europe
has ever seen, Alexander, Caesar, Napoleon and Hitler, produced a total of
seven (mostly illegitimate) children among the lot of them (and only two of the
seven had children in their turn who survived to adulthood.) Breeding appears
to have been rather low on their list of priorities, even though they all
married and had mistresses. Nor were great artists, poets, writers, scientists
or other outstanding individuals usually blessed with numerous offspring.
Leonardo da Vinci, Michelangelo, Durer, Bacon, Newton, Washington,
Beethoven, Chopin, Stendhal, Nietzsche, and Shaw are just a few we could cite
from an interminable list of childless great men (most of them not
homosexuals.) The phenomenon was commented on in various ages. Francis Bacon
proclaimed: “the best works, and of greatest merit for the
public, have proceeded from the unmarried or childless men.” 75 Darwin himself admitted this embarrassing fact and tried to explain
it by suggesting that these geniuses are in some sense monsters, and have a
monster’s tendency to sterility, but that superior “normal” men are
prolific. 76 But neither Darwin nor any of his followers ever cited
a single statistic to prove it. American presidents are probably good examples
of powerful, popular and highly successful men, unlikely to be tainted by the
abnormality of genius. Yet the first eight American presidents had an average
of 2.75 children, well below the average of the time. Three of them were
childless. There were then two presidents (both utterly forgotten for their
total mediocrity) who produced twenty-five children between them, followed by
another 8 presidents who again had an average of 3 children each. What pattern
can be discerned here except a total absence of pattern? All the evidence indicates that there has
been no general tendency in recorded history for attractive individuals by any
standards whatever (power, wealth, talent or beauty) to breed more than the
average. And we have no grounds for assuming that in pre-historic societies
which we know nothing of things were any different.
To say that
sexual selection has operated significantly on human evolution is, on the level
on which it is asserted – that the powerful, talented or attractive few have
always had more children than the average – demonstrably false. The
only thing we can assert about human breeding is that it varies in quantity
from one individual to another, and that those who breed more breed more.
Anything further would require research into large families in all cultures to
see if any characteristics correlate to prolific breeding, and are furthered by
it. This has never been done. But this does not stop the neo-Darwinists. They
will without hesitation redefine their statement as a tautology. They will say:
the superior and the fittest breed more, and then redefine the fittest and the
superior as those who breed more. An illiterate peasant with ten mentally
retarded children will be defined as “fitter” (more prolific and therefore, by
implication, superior) than a millionaire genius with two genius children. The
peasant’s wretched genes will be defined as the genes of
success. And the neo-Darwinists will imbue this success with the same emotional
overtones as the success of an extraordinary specimen. As a method, the
neo-Darwinists like to reduce their formulations to tautologies that are
logically irrefutable, while maintaining the emotive implications of statements
of fact that can easily be refuted. Thus the notion “We have all been
selected!” imbues the mere existence of an individual with a
kind of cosmic approbation, a label of superiority, irrespective of his real
qualities. Mere existence confers the status of a thoroughbred racehorse, the
end product of long and careful breeding. That we are here is proof of a superb
genetic achievement. We are the winners of an enormous competition that has been
going on for aeons. Our genes must be the best because they have been selected – and the poor
losers (Leonardo, Michelangelo, Newton,
Washington, Beethoven, Stendhal,
Nietzsche, Chopin, etc.) proved their worthless-ness by dying out and leaving
no offspring.
When Alexander
Pope in his Essay On Man wrote his
famous line “Whatever is, is right!” he was not
making any verifiable assertion about the universe. He was merely expressing an
emotional attitude towards it, an attitude of acceptance and somewhat complacent
approval. And when the Darwinist foot-soldiers today chatter excitedly that
every human quality, from laziness to obesity to freckles, is the result of
sexual selection, that in fact “Everything that exists has been selected”, again they are
not saying anything verifiable about the world. They are merely expressing an
emotional attitude towards it, an attitude of even more nauseating
self-satisfaction than that of Pope. All they are doing is patting themselves
on the back for being alive, and expressing admiration for their own wonderful
genetic make-up, which the whole of nature has been straining to produce for
untold millennia. Professor Richard Dawkins spends pages of his book River out of Eden in dithyrambic ecstasy
over the wonderful reproductive success that our presence on earth
demonstrates. We can all, he says, “make the following proud
claim: Not a single one of our ancestors
died in infancy….. Not a single one of our ancestors was felled by
an enemy, or by a virus, or by a misjudged footstep on a cliff edge, before
bringing at least one child into the world.” We are, in short, the
products of reproductive champions. He concludes in raptures of
self-satisfaction that
since all
organisms inherit all their genes from their ancestors, rather than from their
ancestors’ unsuccessful contemporaries, all organisms tend to
possess successful genes….We all, without a single exception, inherit our
genes from an unbroken line of successful ancestors. The world becomes full of
organisms that have what it takes to become ancestors. That, in a sentence, is
Darwinism. 77
Leaving aside the odd
paradox that one quarter of these reproductive champions in Britain will
die childless, what he understands by Darwinism appears to be nothing but smug,
preening self-satisfaction at the fact that he is alive, as if this alone were
proof of his superlative qualities. “After a thousand
successive generations, the genes that have made it through are likely to be
the good ones.” 78 In short, our
mere existence is proof of the superiority of our genes. It is curious to find
a leading Oxford
scientist priding himself so fulsomely on his mere existence, a quality he
shares with every dung fly, maggot and pubic louse on the planet.
One might as well
imagine a cockroach exhorting its offspring: “Remember,
children, we are the product of natural and sexual selection, we are the end
result of an immense genetic process, a tremendous struggle for survival over
millions of years, which has selected every hair on our legs, every wart on our
bodies, choosing only the finest genes and the most adapted characteristics.
And we embody them! Not one of our ancestors failed to reproduce. We are
descended from life’s winners, from champion breeders! We carry the
genes of success! Be proud to be a cockroach!” This is increasingly what the belief in
natural selection has become: an attitude of self-satisfaction and
self-approval, a smug faith that however ugly, stupid or mediocre one may be,
one is nonetheless the embodiment of the finest and most exclusively selected
genetic traits. “We have all been selected!” the Darwinists
cry, like a bunch of Calvinists at a church meeting to celebrate their own
predestined salvation. Apart from an attitude of smug self-congratulation at
being alive while others are dead, the belief says nothing at all about the
real world.
11
) HOW NEO CAN NEO-DARWINISM GET?
As we have
already noted, the neo-Darwinists have now retreated from their forward
positions into the fortress of tautology. It is a fake retreat, like that of
the Greeks at Troy.
Tautology is a bastion from which they periodically sally forth to try to
strike a blow for real (“old”) Darwinist attitudes by stealth. But let us look at
how they arrived at this odd retreat. It makes a fascinating study in
intellectual dishonesty and bad faith.
The severe
difficulties of Darwin’s theory led over
the years to a whole series of ad hoc
modifications by his followers. One should point out in advance that anyone
familiar with the works of Karl Popper on the philosophy of science will
recognize the ad hoc modification as
a warning sign. Popper argued that proponents of genuine scientific theories
actively seek their refutation: they try to create what he called crucial
experiments which will make or break the theory. A crucial experiment usually
consists of a prediction that in a given situation, if the theory is true, a
certain result will follow. If the result does not follow we must abandon the
theory. If the result follows, we can consider the theory corroborated for now,
but never definitively proved. On the other hand, the advocates of
pseudo-scientific theories, said Popper, never seek crucial experiments and
they never seek to refute their theory. They seize on all positive results as
proof and reject all negative ones as errors of measurement. When forced to
face devastating criticisms, they react by adjusting the theory, tacking on ad hoc modifications, redefining the
basic terms, shifting the goal posts, and so on. He saw this process at work in
Marxism, positivism, historicism, and concluded that these theories were being
held as faiths, not science. 79 This is precisely what we see at
work in the history of the Darwinists, and their fantastic displays of bad
faith and cheating have been exhaustively catalogued by Richard Milton in his
book Shattering the Myths of Darwinism. 80
One of the most
damaging criticisms of Darwinism had been voiced in Darwin’s own lifetime by his ally
and great defender, Thomas Huxley. Huxley put his finger on the gap between the
micro-evolution within species (breeding a dog with shorter legs or longer
ears), and the macro-evolution of one species into another. It is the latter
which natural selection has to explain and demonstrate if it is to be a theory
of how all life forms evolved. Huxley doubted that any process of selection of
small random variations could arrive at a new species. 81 He told Darwin that his theory
would only be proven when breeders managed to produce varieties that crossed
the species barrier and became new species (that is, able to breed fertile
young with each other, and unable to cross-breed fertile young with other
species, according to the definition usually accepted by neo-Darwinists.) Now
it was well-known that breeders had never managed to do this. Neither Dutch
tulip-growers in the seventeenth century, nor pigeon-breeders nor dog-breeders
had ever got there, and in the twentieth century it became clear why they could
not. A wall exists beyond which a species cannot be transformed by selective
breeding, because the offspring cease to be fertile, or if fertile revert to
previous types. This wall is encountered well short of a species difference.
Even Darwin’s own classification of the thirteen species of
finches on the Galapagos islands, all derived from a parent species, has been
called into question by the awkward fact that these “species” sometimes
cross-breed fertile young with each other, and ten per cent of those on Daphne
Major are now fertile and prolific hybrids. 82 Some biologists have
thus argued that they are only varieties, like different races of dog, which
breed true, but which are all one species. 83 This controversy only
highlights the central problem: how does a variety get to be different enough
to be defined as a separate species? How does the process of divergence by
natural selection get over the species barrier? This remained the chief
difficulty of Darwin’s theory, and
caused it to fall out of favour among evolutionists for half a century.
Help for the
Darwinists arrived with progress in genetics, the rediscovery of the work of
Mendel on genes, and above all the development of the notion of mutations.
Mendel’s theory of dominant genes helped to explain how a
new characteristic would remain in the gene pool and not be drowned out at once
by cross-breeding. Inheritance does not blend the characteristics of both
parents, reducing variation, but keeps them as distinct genes. The work on
mutations by De Vries and others showed how the species barrier might just
feasibly be jumped by sudden leaps, more radical than the gradual accumulation
of minute changes that Darwin
had envisaged. The Darwinists at a meeting of the Geological Society of America
in 1941 decided to incorporate these modifications into a new version of Darwin’s theory, which
would rescue it from the slough of despond into which it had fallen. Now Darwin had posited the
natural selection of both random and adaptive variations, as he had never
broken completely with Lamarck. The new version confined the theory to the
selection of purely random variations, and above all random mutations. It
rejected the elements of Lamarckism that Darwin
had accepted in some cases, such as the atrophying of wings in flightless
birds, or the effect of the use or disuse of limbs. Darwin had demonstrated the Lamarckian
hypothesis by showing that domestic ducks had developed heavier leg bones and
lighter wing bones than their wild duck ancestors, because of more walking and
less flying. He thus accepted the notion that acquired characteristics, caused
by a change in habits, could be transmitted to offspring. But by now the
established theory in genetics was that the genes governing heredity were
totally separate from the cells of the body itself: the body cells might be
modifiable by the organism’s own actions or by the environment, but the genes
were not. This was the principle enunciated at the turn of the century by the
German August Weismann – the notion of a firewall between the somatic (body)
cells and the germ cells. This was thought to spell the death of Lamarck’s theory of
direct environmental modification of organisms and the inheritance of acquired
characteristics. In fact Weismann “proved” this firewall by
some of the most ludicrously naive experiments ever carried out: by cutting the
tails off rats and then showing that the mutilations were not inherited. 84
This was hardly a revolutionary discovery ; the practice of circumcision had
demonstrated it for thousands of years. A mutilation is not an acquired
characteristic, the way heavier leg-bones in the domestic duck (through more
walking) is an acquired characteristic. The animal must make an effort to “acquire” a
characteristic, and it is the effort (particularly during growth in
adolescence) that might possibly switch on dormant genes so that the offspring
develop this characteristic more readily. Darwin’s study of
domestic ducks demonstrated that Lamarck was right. His modern followers, in an
astonishing assertion of dogmatism over empirical evidence, ignored his
research and purged his theory of these elements.
The so-called
Modern Synthetic Theory of Evolution was thus a narrowing down of Darwinism to
exclude all Lamarckian elements, to emphasize even more the randomness of
variations, and to lean heavily on the theory of mutations to jump the famous
species barrier. What it still required of course was a process of natural or
sexual selection of these variations by the fierce competition to survive.
But this
neo-Darwinian theory also ran into trouble over the nature of mutations. Watson
and Crick, after plotting the structure of DNA, soon identified mutations with
the random errors in DNA replication. The problem was that researchers found
that these errors result in the deletion of information, not the addition of
it. They are, in short, degenerative. Grassé compared mutations to typing
mistakes; it is unlikely that one will by chance produce a brilliant new
sentence. Furthermore, mutations are extremely rare – estimates by
neo-Darwinists vary from one in ten thousand (Monod) to one in one million
births (Julian Huxley). 85 Relying on random mutations (most of them
degenerative and only a tiny handful useful) as the mechanism of evolution
stretches out the time-scale required to even more unimaginable aeons. George Gaylord
Simpson, one of the church fathers of the theory, estimated the time needed for
the evolution of the horse as 65 million years. 86 This would put
its origins back to the time of the dinosaurs. This enormous time-span has not
deterred most neo-Darwinists, though it appears to exclude rapid evolution
completely. This makes it hard to see how evolution can ever be an adaptation
to a new environment in any sense; the process is simply too slow. It is like
reacting to a sudden cold spell by beginning to knit a sweater that will be
ready for your descendant in a thousand generations. If the sweater is really
necessary, then how will the next nine hundred and ninety-nine generations
survive without it? And how will a series of mutations (selected by natural
selection) have any linear, adaptive direction, since conditions will keep
changing in contrary and extreme ways over such very long periods?
Some
neo-Darwinists, worried by this, have opted for a theory of clusters of
mutations occurring together, so that a number of features of an animal mutate
simultaneously, thus speeding up the process by making major jumps. These
sudden big mutations (or “saltations”) help answer another
perennial criticism of the theory: the absence of intermediate forms in the fossil
record. 87 If species developed gradually from other species, surely
we would see evidence of some in-between forms, if not today, then at least
among the tens of thousands of fossil remains. Unfortunately we don’t. Arguing that
the major changes took place over a very short period, by sudden big jumps,
would answer this objection. The intermediate forms were around for too short a
time to have left traces. One of the most prominent neo-Darwinists, Harvard’s Stephen Jay
Gould, advanced this theory under the name of “punctuated
equilibrium”: long periods of unchanging stability in species,
punctuated by short periods of rapid and radical mutation, which have
unfortunately left no evidence behind. 88 (One wag unkindly quipped:
“Evolution is either so slow it’s invisible or so fast it’s invisible.”) But why these
periods of rapid change should occur if they were not in response to
environmental influences is not made clear. Even these major mutations have to
be random, with nature afterwards making its selection through the
time-honoured means of the survival of the fittest. If major clusters of
mutations are random and not adaptive, then presumably they are quite aimless
and erratic. Logically, then, the fossil record ought to be full of monsters,
aimless and fanciful mutations that were not selected (two-headed horses, cats
with hoofs, mice with tusks, and so on.) But it isn’t. We don’t find heaps of
rejected rough drafts in Nature’s rubbish bin. Nature almost always gets it right
the first time. That is what makes the idea of lots of random, radical
mutations as the raw material for natural selection such a difficult theory to
swallow.
But the final modification to the theory made by the
so-called neo-Darwinists was the most significant. The many problems with the
notion of the “survival of the fittest” – the difficulty
of demonstrating that it is the fittest which survive, and on what grounds they
can be considered the fittest – led the
neo-Darwinists to redefine “the survival of the fittest” as a tautology:
the fittest are those that survive, fitness is the quality of genetic survival.
This was the modification introduced by George Gaylord Simpson in the 1950’s and since
generally adopted as a solution to the central problem of the theory. Here is
how one prominent neo-Darwinist professor of biology, C.H. Waddington, states
the case:
Natural
selection, which was at first considered as though it were a hypothesis that
was in need of experimental or observational confirmation, turns out on closer
inspection to be a tautology, a statement of an inevitable although previously
unrecognized relation. It states that the fittest individuals in a population
(defined as those which leave the most offspring) will leave the most
offspring. Once the statement is made its truth is apparent. 89
One’s first reaction
is to see this as a hoax. As science, this is about on the same level as
Duchamp’s urinal or Manzoni’s cans of shit in
the world of art. It should be borne in mind
that Waddington is not a critic of neo-Darwinism who is being funny
here. This is one of its leading spokesmen, biology professor at a major
university (that of Robert Grant), being deadly serious. He goes on with the
inimitable pious platitudes of the academic apparatchik:
This fact in no
way reduces the magnitude of Darwin’s achievement;
only after it was clearly formulated could biologists realize the enormous
power of the principle as a weapon of explanation. 90
The critic of Darwinism
Richard Milton comments on this passage with what seems like admirable
restraint:
Many will be
surprised to find a professor of biology describing a tautology as an
achievement of any sort. Waddington failed to recognize the damaging nature of
his admission….
Milton goes on to
ironize over how indeed this tautology has been used as a “weapon of
explanation” – to explain everything and its opposite. He
concludes that natural selection makes no predictions, but is used to explain
every outcome. It “is not a mechanism:
it is a rationalization after the fact.” 91
But Waddington is no eccentric; he is being perfectly
orthodox, and is repeating the party line word for word as handed down by the
ruling commissars of neo-Darwinism. Here is Gaylord Simpson, one of the church
fathers of the theory, saying the same thing:
Natural selection
favours fitness only if you define fitness as leaving more descendants. In fact
geneticists do define it that way, which may be confusing to others. To a
geneticist, fitness has nothing to do with health, strength, good looks or
anything but effectiveness in breeding. 92
But the revisionism of the
neo-Darwinists goes further. Darwin’s central vision
of the violent Malthusian struggle involved in natural selection goes out the
window too. There is now a politically correct, “kinder, gentler” struggle for
survival. Here is Gaylord Simpson again:
Struggle is
sometimes involved, but it usually is not, and when it is, it may even work
against rather than toward natural selection. Advantage in differential
reproduction is usually a peaceful process in which the concept of struggle is
really irrelevant. It more often involves such things as better integration
into the ecological situation, maintenance of a balance of nature, more
efficient utilization of available food, better care of the young…. 93
This could be an election
manifesto aimed at the middle-class, Green, female vote. This is Darwin expurgated for the
sensitive reader. Peaceful competition has replaced war. There are probably
weekly community meetings between prey and predator species to discuss quotas,
and weekend outings together to clean up the environment. Admittedly this was
published in 1967, but did Simpson need the hippie vote that badly?
Richard Milton comments on
the whole thing:
To summarize, the
modern position of the synthetic theory is: the struggle for existence plays no
part in evolution. The direction of evolution is determined solely by the
characteristics of those animals and plants that are successful breeders. We
are unable to say anything about why a particular characteristic might favour,
or prejudice, the survival of any particular animal or plant.
Thus “the survival of the fittest” or “natural selection” or “differential
reproduction” sheds no light on the mechanics of evolution and is
only another way of saying that some animals survive and prosper while others
die out – an observation of limited value. 94
Now this is in no way an
exaggeration or a caricature. This is a fair summary of what is now the
official view of the neo-Darwinist establishment, imposed on every single
biology student, and dutifully parroted by every evolutionist. Here is another
example from our old friend, the observer of predators, Professor of Zoology at
Toronto University, Christopher McGowan. He is
also singing from the same hymn-sheet about “fitness”:
An animal’s capacity to
produce offspring is described as fitness.
This evolutionary term should not be confused with the usual meaning of the
term. In evolutionary terms an animal that produces the most offspring is the
fittest, regardless of its physical condition. 95
Now it is curious that
having reduced “the survival of the fittest” to a tautology (“the survival of
those that survive”) the neo-Darwinists still insist on using the word “fitness”. Since they have
redefined fitness to mean “capacity to produce offspring”, and admitted
that this is a gross distortion of “the usual meaning of the
term” (that is to say, Darwin’s meaning:
strength, health, speed, agility), why don’t they drop the term and call
it prolificness? Reproductive success? Breeding ability? In part, as we shall
see below, it is because they refuse to let go of the emotional associations of
the old term, and they want to pretend they still believe in Darwin’s theory when in reality they
have refined it out of existence. They want to disguise the fact that they have
dropped Darwinism, rather like the British Labour Party trying to disguise for
so long that it had dropped Marxism. They want to pretend they still have an
explanatory mechanism for evolution when they no longer do.
But even if we look closely
at the term “capacity to produce offspring”, its meaning is not entirely clear.
Is it the theoretical ability to have offspring (potency, fertility), or the
actual having of offspring? Imagine a magnificent stag, which has just won
possession of a herd of females by an epic fight, about to mount his first doe,
when he is fatally attacked by a hungry mountain lion. This supremely fit
specimen has suddenly died without producing offspring. In short, he has become
unfit—according to the new definition of fitness as “capacity to produce
offspring”. The question is: was he always unfit? Or did he suddenly become
unfit at the moment of being killed? Was he fit one moment and unfit the next?
Or can we never say an animal was fit before it produced offspring? Is fitness
a quality you gain retroactively, after you’ve done some sterling breeding (a
bit like an OBE?) If it is the latter, is it dependent on the offspring
surviving, and breeding in their turn? (Apparently it is: the Grants in their
Galapagos research project mock a finch that has had several families but no
grandchildren as a “loser”.) But this means that fitness is a quality that
comes and goes with the vicissitudes of one’s descendants. If a man has six
children and they are all killed in a plane crash after he is too old to have
more, he apparently becomes “unfit” at the moment of their death. But what if
one son had got in a quickie with a ground hostess before boarding the plane
and made her pregnant, does his father
become fit again? But if the baby boy she gives birth to turns out to be gay,
does the old man go back to being unfit? (What if the grandson has a change of
heart in later life and fathers triplets? Does the old man, now on his deathbed
and feeling rather confused about his status, become fit once again?) Is a man
who donates sperm to a sperm bank to be defined as fit according to the number
of female customers who use his sperm? Does he therefore get “fitter” as time
goes by and more women get pregnant thanks to him—and unfit if someone throws
his sperm out by mistake? And what about future generations? If you produce
four children, and they have twenty children, and forty grandchildren, but all
of them die in an earthquake except one who enters a convent, do you go back to
being unfit again? And what if she’s raped by a mad priest and has a playboy
son who fathers a whole football team? Does it make you fit again? How many
generations down the line do you have to follow the progress of your offspring
and check out their sexual orientation before you can be really sure you’re
fit? Can any animal ever be defined as fit, since we don’t know the ultimate
fate of its descendants ten generations on? According to this view, not a
single animal that ever lived on the island
of Krakatoa before the
late 19th century can be described as fit, because all their descendants
perished in the volcanic eruption of 1883. In fact all species that have died
out thereby proved they were unfit. All sabre-tooth tigers were unfit. So were
all mammoths, all dodos, all moas, and all other extinct animals and birds. The
dying out of all their descendants made all of them unfit. If the Siberian
tiger or the giant panda die out tomorrow, this will prove these species were
unfit too. So why should we try to save them? Since the planet is not eternal
and all species will one day perish, they are all unfit. In short, this notion
of fitness as reproductive success leads to a series of absurdities. It is
trying to turn an event—the having of descendants—into an inherent genetic
quality: fitness. Yet this event by its nature can never be complete or
definitive. After how many generations of descendants do we grant fitness? Two?
Ten? A hundred? A million? When is reproductive success an acquired fact? Darwin
would turn in his grave. He makes absolutely clear that he does not regard
fitness as being synonymous with reproductive success, because he laments,
along with all the Malthusian Whigs, that the poor, feckless, unfit humans are
having too many offspring, thanks to mollycoddling welfare laws, and should be
stopped from doing so. The whole Darwinian-Spencerian obsession with creating
the conditions of society where the unfit and inferior will actually die off
and the fit will actually leave more children becomes meaningless if this
copout tautology is accepted. In this new definition, all that is being said is
that those who leave more offspring leave more offspring. There is no
correlation of this reproductive success with any other characteristic. So no
characteristics are being selected by this reproductive success. There is thus
no natural selection, and no mechanism of evolution.
But McGowan himself does not in fact believe his own
tautological definition of fitness. Let us read once again his description of
an attack on a herd of zebra by a lioness:
The big cat selects her
quarry..…. It was not the closest one but it failed to follow
the choreography of the herd quite as closely as the others. 96
And once again, the conventional Darwinist moral just afterwards:
The zebra that
was killed by the lioness was the one that failed to keep together with the
rest of the herd. The zebra’s behaviour may have been attributed to a number of
factors, ranging from its running ability to its spatial awareness. If the
behaviour had genetic components, the zebra’s unfavourable genes would
have been removed, by natural selection, from the gene pool, which is the sum total of genes in that breeding
population. 97
Here we are back with the
familiar Darwinist notion of fitness or unfitness. We have the removal of “unfavourable
genes”, apparently related to running ability. We are not merely discussing “capacity to
produce offspring”. The zebra targeted was an awkward runner,
revealing some arcane genetic weakness, which the lioness, blessed not only
with preternatural perspicacity but also with a deep altruistic concern for the
future welfare of the zebra species, decided to cull, in order to rid the world
of this inferior, pigeon-toed rubbish. Whatever happened to McGowan’s definition of
fitness as merely the “capacity to produce offspring”? How do we know
this zebra had an inferior “capacity to produce offspring”? Obviously now
he is dead he is somewhat limited in that domain, but before his death what
allowed us to predict this dire reproductive deficiency? Above all how did the
lioness know?
The question is:
has McGowan abandoned the new Party-line tautological definition of fitness as
the animal that produces the most offspring, or hasn’t he? Has he gone
back to the original one (Darwin’s one) implying
strength, speed, beauty, vigour, and anything else that might make it a
superior specimen? McGowan seems to want “unfitness” to mean “genetic
inferiority”, allowing him to morally justify the predator’s culling of an
unfit zebra as a healthy purging of the species, a removal of “unfavourable
genes”. But when pushed to define his terms, he realizes this is no longer
the Party line so he falls back on the newly agreed definition of fitness – the “capacity to
produce offspring”. But this only multiplies the problems. Is this “capacity to
produce offspring” an inherent characteristic or the result of
external events? Is the zebra’s unfitness, i.e. its “incapacity to produce
offspring”, a characteristic inherent in it, which the lioness
detected beforehand by some occult means? (How? If lionesses have some
preternatural flair for detecting erectile disfunction in zebras, then this is
surely a marketable skill.) Or is the zebra’s unfitness simply the result of
the lioness killing him (the dead don’t breed)? Since the first is
unlikely, it appears the zebra has been defined as unfit because he was killed.
A dead (and childless) zebra is an unfit zebra. This is a bit like a Mafia
gangster killing someone and then saying: “He was no good. Look, there’s the proof, he’s dead!” The fact that he
was killed becomes the justification for it. The lioness was removing an unfit
specimen – but it was her act of doing so that made him unfit.
Everyone that gets killed deserves it. We confer the quality of unfitness on an
animal by killing it. If it hadn’t been unfit, it wouldn’t have been killed.
Now this is a
somewhat peculiar line of logic, yet it follows irresistibly from the neo-Darwinist
definition of fitness as genetic survival (leaving descendants) and unfitness
as genetic death. Death proves an animal was unfit. You go up in a helicopter
and wipe out a herd of deer with a machine-gun and you can justify yourself:
“They were all unfit. The proof is, they’re dead. Therefore they deserved to
die. I was right to kill them.” In fact the killer is always right because
death is always just. The Darwinists have no room for regrets, no room for
tragedy, no room for error, no room for crime. Everything happened as it should
have. Whenever death happens to any animal, it deserved it. Death proves it was
unfit to live.
But let’s look
further. If the lioness had pounced on an even more awkward-running,
spatially-challenged specimen, letting our zebra off the hook (and potentially
able to get in a quickie with a neighbouring female), would this make him fit
again? Apparently. So the zebra’s fitness depends on the lioness’s action, not his
own. You are fit if the predator leaves you alive and able to get your leg
over. You are unfit if you are dead before you had the chance. The predator’s
judgement distinguishes the fit from the unfit. The predator’s judgement
confers fitness. Natural selection is the selection of those the predator
ignored, because by chance he or she saw a tastier dinner or an easier target
running beside them. We can’t actually say anything about the qualities of those
selected. We don’t know what in fact is being selected except the
fact of being selected. Since the only quality we can ascribe to the “fit” is
the accident of survival, the only quality being selected is an accident. One
can see from this muddle the swamp of self-contradictions, absurdities, and
confusion of definitions in which neo-Darwinists habitually flounder around,
and from the midst of which they issue their vague and glib generalizations
which have laid bare all the hidden mechanisms of nature.
This latest act
of legerdemain by the neo-Darwinists in fact empties their theory of all
meaning as a mechanism of evolution. The tautological definition of fitness as
the animal that has the most offspring, irrespective of its physical condition
or genetic make-up, makes it impossible to talk of natural selection any
longer. What characteristics are being selected? If we deny fitness any meaning
but reproductive success, then we deny that reproductive success will favour
any particular characteristic. If reproductive success cannot be co-related
with any characteristic except itself, then it is random. But if it is random
then it cannot be a means of selecting favourable genes and furthering
evolution. The neo-Darwinists are therefore denying that any natural selection
is taking place. But how can this sacred principle then be the mechanism of
evolution? Their entire theory of evolution through natural selection falls to
the ground. This is what the neo-Darwinists have now done: emptied Darwinism of
any meaning as a way of explaining how evolution works.
What this amounts
to is shifting the notion of randomness from the variation to its selection. Darwin believed the
variations in the species were mostly random, but the selection of those
variations was rigorously meaningful: it was the variations which gave a
survival advantage (fitness) that were selected. This is still the official
definition of natural selection that people like Dawkins subscribe to: the
non-random selection of random variation. But now that genetic survival is the
only definition of fitness, randomness has shifted to the process of selection
itself. If selection or survival cannot be co-related with any quality except
itself, then it is random. Natural selection has now become the random
selection of random variation, and as such it has ceased to be a mechanism for
any evolution at all.
Neo-Darwinists do
not seem to understand that they have emptied their theory of meaning, because
they lack honesty and consistency. In practice, they continue a kind of double
talk. Like McGowan in the passages quoted, they vary their definition of
fitness according to the context. When pushed to define fitness, they fall back
cautiously on the tautological definition – the animal that has the
most offspring – because they can’t prove the selection of any
particular characteristics whatsoever. But when watching the lion kill a zebra,
they lapse unconsciously into their old belief that there is some genetic
inferiority being eliminated here. They then talk of selection of the “fittest” in the everyday
sense of the word fittest: healthiest, strongest, fastest. In short, they
pretend to believe in a new, tautological definition of fitness, but continue
to believe in their hearts in an old crude definition. The new definition
cannot be refuted but says nothing. The old crude definition says something,
but what it says can be refuted. Only by dodging from one to the other do they
keep up a semblance of credibility.
Here is another
rather more subtle example of this fudging, from Oxford’s high priest of Darwinism,
Richard Dawkins:
Some bodies are
better at surviving and reproducing than others. Good bodies i.e. bodies that
are good at surviving and reproducing will tend to contribute more genes to the
gene pools of the future than bodies that are bad at surviving and reproducing;
genes that tend to make good bodies will come to predominate in gene pools.
Natural selection is the differential survival and differential reproductive
success of bodies….… Evolution, under the influence of natural
selection, leads to adaptive improvement. 98
Here again we see the subtle
shift from a purely tautological definition of “good bodies” (as those that
actually survive and reproduce most) to an assertion that they are somehow
inherently “good” – and an assertion without evidence that the
selection of these “good bodies” will lead to “adaptive
improvement”. This is again a form of casuistry, but of a more
sophisticated kind than McGowan’s – the sleight of hand is cleverer. You have to look
carefully to see that the expression “good at surviving” is a brilliant
blurring of the tautological definition (the fittest are defined as those that
survive) and an implicit assertion that these survivors possess inherently “good” qualities. Being
“good at surviving” becomes in itself a proof of superiority.
The key to this
sleight of hand is that the term “good at surviving” cleverly creates
a quality “good at…” out of an event : “they survived.” There is in fact
no quality involved here – merely an accidental circumstance, survival. Or at
least that is the point he is required to prove – that survival is
correlated with particular genetic qualities and is not a matter of chance. But
by using the term “good at surviving” he conceals the fact that
he has not established that any characteristic is correlated with this
survival. He creates a purely fictive characteristic “being good at
surviving” with the strong implication that it is a sign of
possessing superior genes. Since the selection of these genes that are “good at surviving” will lead to “adaptive
improvement” of the species, these genes must be superior. In
turning the fact of survival into an inherent quality, he has invented “genes of survival” known to no
geneticist. We are back with the tautologies of Calvin and predestination. The
successful are the elect of God. How do
we know they are the elect of God? Because they are successful. This is ascribing a sort of determinism after
the fact to a chance event. It happened because it had to happen. Animals
survive which are good at surviving. How do we know they’re good at surviving?
Because they survived. Genes are selected which are good at being selected.
Lottery numbers come up which are good at coming up. Those numbers had to come
up, because they possessed a quality which made them come up – the quality of
being good at coming up. “Why does opium cause sleep? – Because it
possesses a soporific power.” Molière satirized the pretentious tautological
explanations of scientific charlatans three centuries ago. An Oxford professor who uses terms in this way
is either aiming to deceive by creating a careful logical fudge, or is simply
ignorant of the rules of logic. Either way he stands discredited on a point
crucial to the whole scientific theory he defends.
But this clever
formulation, the pseudo-quality of being “good at surviving”, reveals itself
as not merely devoid of real meaning but as carrying along with it a certain
number of emotional and moral implications, most of which are unsavoury. This
appears to be the whole point of this sort of logical fudge: to use a tautology
to convey an emotional attitude that was associated with the old,
non-tautological statement. First of all, it is a covert form of determinism:
an assertion that something had to happen merely because it did happen. The
implication is that the fact of survival depended on some mysterious inner
qualities (being “good at surviving”.) Survival is therefore a
proof not only of a superior ability to survive, but of superiority as such. In
short, survival has an intrinsic merit attached to it; the survivor always
merited his survival. I am right because I survived. You’re wrong because
you’re dead. This is indistinguishable from Hitler’s principle that “might makes right”. The killers are
right and the corpses are wrong. A Nazi is better than a Jew because one is
alive and the other is dead. The second implication is that those who did not
survive or reproduce were not good at it, and therefore the species is better
off without them. The weak to the wall and good riddance. Leonardo Da Vinci may
well have been the greatest genius of all time, but since he had no children,
his genes were clearly not “good at surviving”, and therefore the human
gene pool was well rid of them. The same applies to Michelangelo, Beethoven,
Chopin, etc. Though in fact there is a high degree of heritability in musical
and artistic talent, we should have no regrets that these men never had
offspring, as they clearly had inferior genes, lacking that crucial quality,
being “good at surviving.” This comes close
to the principle of Voltaire’s Candide: “Everything happens for the
best in the best of all possible worlds.” It shows the underpinning
of this world-view by the shadow of a religious or superstitious belief in a
universe where everything is governed by some benign, positive principle: those
who survived deserved to, and those who died out deserved to die. Therefore, we
should not only cast aside regret for the failure of the great to reproduce
(since they were clearly not “good at surviving”) but we should not regret
premature deaths either. Darwin
consoled himself for the death of his favourite daughter Annie at 9 because the
survivors were “more vigorous & healthy & can most enjoy
life”. 99 How he arrived at this curious conclusion is not clear,
but arrive at it he must, since we live in a world where everything happens for
the best. Nature is benign and has our long-term interest at heart, however
difficult it is to see it. To lament the mass death of people at Auschwitz or
Hiroshima or the World Trade Centre is foolish, since these people clearly
lacked the right survival genes – they were quite simply “not good at
surviving.” Nature knows best. No matter what dreadful things
happen in the world, says the neo-Darwinist, no matter what the apparent
injustices and harsh losses, we must have faith. It is all leading to the
adaptive improvement of the species, because the right individuals are always
surviving and reproducing, and those that get killed clearly deserved no
better.
This is how
Victorian intellectuals dealt with the death of God, by transferring His benign
governing, judging, selecting role to Nature and the principle underlying the
universe. Underneath the superficial militant atheism of men like Professor
Dawkins lies a world-view that is profoundly religious and profoundly
Protestant in its harsh, relentlessly complacent optimism. Voltaire would have
devoted an entire chapter of Candide
to Professor Dawkins and his religion of complacency. This is merely an
illustration of how the intellectual pride of narrow scientific minds, which
lack any serious grasp of philosophy or even a firm grasp of logic, leads them
to run blindly into the same old mental errors of the past, under the illusion
that they are inventing the new, and that the trendy modern terms into which
they have transposed their thinking will conceal the ancient fallacies that lie
beneath.
What the
chop-logic of the neo-Darwinists conceals is still a blind faith in the
morality of the universe, a view which moralizes the brutally destructive
processes of Nature, as being for the long-term good of all. It is Herbert
Spencer rewritten in the scientific jargon of the day. Now when one examines
the carefully crafted pieces of logical fudging of men like Dawkins it leads
inevitably to the suspicion of deliberate deception, of sheer intellectual
dishonesty. But this is probably unfair. It is unjustly imputing to them a
cunning intelligence that it is doubtful that they possess. These academics are
not cynical Machiavellis so much as Jesuits using a tortuous mental process to
defend what is in fact a deep, quasi-religious conviction. They may even be
desperately papering over a sort of crisis of faith as they glimpse the yawning
chasm in the middle of their theory. What they cannot do is let go of it
because they have nothing else emotionally to sustain them.
The neo-Darwinist
theory of natural selection only survives today by various forms of games with
words – by chop logic and fudged definitions. The word
“fitness” is now the most muddled concept in the history of either philosophy
or biology. Half the neo-Darwinists, those we might call the theologians, the
church fathers like Gaylord Simpson, use “fitness” to mean “having the most
offspring” or “reproductive success irrespective of the qualities of the
individual.” Meanwhile, the fundamentalists (often zealots experimenting in the
field) still have a passionate belief in “fitness” in the old sense (Darwin’s sense) of
strength, size, vigour, adapted body features,
etc. Grant and Weiner claimed that the degree of fitness of finches on
Daphne island could be measured with a pair of calipers; they quantified
fitness as half a millimetre of a finch’s beak. Fitness here could only mean
the qualities making for survival during the drought, not merely reproductive
success, since five-sixths of these big-beaked survivors which they considered
the “fittest” then failed to reproduce because there weren’t enough females
left.100 The evolutionary psychologists adhere to a fundamentalist
definition of fitness also. Some of them have tried to prove that women have
always chosen “short-term mates” (as if this concept generally existed before
1960) on the grounds of their “genetic fitness” rather than their wealth.
Fitness here can hardly mean reproductive success since they have not yet done
any breeding.101 Here again we have the old religion, where
“fitness” means strength, good looks and sexual vigour – the promise of
reproductive success, rather than that success itself. In short, between the
neo-Darwinist theologians and the fundamentalists there is so much difference
on the subject of fitness as to make them proponents of quite different
ideologies, arbitrarily united under the same name. Between the two extremes
stand the confused middle church weathervanes, like McGowan, who dodge between
the two definitions of fitness, the theologian’s tautology and the
fundamentalist’s literalism, depending on the context. Finally there are the
Jesuit missionaries like Dawkins, brandishing the tautology of the theologians,
but by clever tricks of logic trying to give it the emotive overtones of the
fundamentalists. In short, Darwinism has become as riddled with logical
inconsistencies as the religious theories of Paley and others which it replaced
in the nineteenth century. And it is the consciousness that their position is
crumbling that makes the neo-Darwinists so ferocious and fanatical in the
defence of their faith.
The comparison
with religious orthodoxy is an apt one. Neo-Darwinism today is an orthodoxy on
the defensive, and it employs all the tools of repression of its opponents
which the Victorian establishment employed against evolutionists. It is safely
ensconced in the leading universities of Britain
and America, and anyone who
questions the orthodoxy is damned as a “creationist” or a “closet
creationist” in much the same way as Robert Grant and other
forerunners of Darwin
were damned as atheist revolutionaries. Richard Milton recounts in his book Shattering the Myths of Darwinism that
the above-mentioned Richard Dawkins of Oxford used his influence to stop the Times Higher Educational Supplement from
publishing an article of Milton’s critical of Darwinism, by falsely accusing him of
being a creationist. 102 Milton
also recounts the vilification unleashed by American academics against a
television programme he worked on, which, for once, was allowed to call
Darwinism into question by strictly scientific arguments. The abuse he received
was on a level of obscene insult that you would expect from street-thugs rather
than scholars.103 Darwin himself was deterred from publishing for
nearly twenty years by his terror of exactly this kind of intellectual thuggery
from the academic establishment. To imagine that academics have developed more
tolerance of adversaries since Darwin’s time is naive.
Neo-Darwinism is a faith defended with all the fury and viciousness of men who
see their sacrosanct world-view threatened. It is not, according to Popper’s definition, a
scientific theory at all. It is, as the great French zoologist Pierre Grassé
pointed out three decades ago, the reigning pseudo-science of our time, an
exact mirror image of the superstition defended with such lofty sarcasm by
Bishop Wilberforce a century and a half ago.
It is all the
more remarkable that neo-Darwinism has become the latest fossilized superstition by which the scientific
establishment, true to its long tradition of dogmatic error, resists and tries
to suppress new research (such as that of micro-biologists like Ted Steele), in
that its proponents are convinced they are manning the last defences of
scientific thought – against the onslaught of creationists, Christian
fundamentalists, New Age gurus, and sundry representatives of the irrational.
It is a demonstration that there is no greater tendency towards blind
intolerance and totalitarian methods than among those who believe they are
defending enlightenment. A study of the intolerance of modern Darwinist
academics should give us a new understanding of the Churchmen in Galileo’s time or of
Bishop Wilberforce himself. They were perhaps also well-meaning men defending
what they saw as knowledge against the onslaught of the irrational. But there
is something else in the vicious spirit that animates the Darwinists. It is
tempting to surmise that people who believe that life is a ruthless struggle
where the weak go to the wall and survival is the only proof of worth, are
naturally inclined to use fascist methods in the defence of what is at root a
fascist idea.
The more
philosophically inclined Darwinists like the late Stephen Jay Gould like to
imagine that they are sober realists facing the bleak truth of existence and
resisting the temptation of sentimental and comforting religious beliefs. But
in fact their own view is essentially an emotive, quasi-religious belief. It is
an attempt to moralize and rationalize the brutalities of Nature as serving a
higher purpose – that of evolution. The belief in the survival of
the fittest is an enormous moralization of nature – an attempt to
justify the ways of God to man, or the ways of Nature to her creatures, by making
Nature’s cruelty the key to adaptive improvement. This is
what gives their view a sort of axiomatic status in their minds: it is their
moral vision of the way things are. The emotional conviction that the weak and
unfit are eliminated for a higher purpose and that this harsh law is how the
world works is essential to their acceptance of life. They have in their minds
a graphic image of a spindly-legged calf being torn apart by wild dogs and they
must believe this is part of a process of improving the species or they wouldn’t be able to
stand it. If they did not feel there was some purpose, even some justice in
nature’s cruelties, they could not face them – or perhaps, in
some cases, they could not morally justify their own sadistic pleasure in this
spectacle. And if you point out that a wildebeest calf is not in fact a
genetically inferior specimen, but has been picked on because its tender youth
makes it an easy target, and that its death will have no improving effect whatever on the gene pool, they are
full of rage that you have destroyed their rationalization – and therefore
their emotional consolation – for nature’s cruelty. They will reject
your view because they need to believe that nature is just in its cruelty, that
this cruelty is necessary for the adaptive improvement of species. The stern
law of necessity makes this scene palatable: remove necessity and it becomes
intolerable. Natural selection is what they have instead of God to make
emotional and moral sense of a cruel universe, and they will no more give it up
than a believer in a religious faith.
12) DARWINISM AS A RELIGIOUS
WORLD-VIEW
Natural selection
is of course a direct descendant of the Calvinist idea of election, or
salvation by being chosen by God, irrespective of your own apparent deserts.
One might call natural selection “election by the harsh
goddess Nature”, to use Hitler’s favourite expression,
which neatly combines Calvin and Darwin. Both are ways of justifying by some
inscrutable pattern of justice a state of affairs which seems on the surface
cruel, arbitrary and unjust – and which in reality is cruel, arbitrary and unjust. Just as John Milton set out in Paradise Lost to “justify the ways
of God to man”, Darwin
(like Herbert Spencer) set out to justify the ways of Nature to all her
creatures. Nature, said Spencer, is a little cruel in order to be very kind.
Letting the bad workman or the improvident sparrow starve is good for the
species. Darwin, as we saw, even tried to convince himself that Nature was
acting benignly in killing off some of his own children, the products of an
unhealthy first-cousin marriage, because this ensured that the survivors were “more vigorous
& healthy and & can most enjoy life”. This whole impulse is a
fundamentalist Protestant one. It rejects the old Catholic sense of tragedy,
that life is a vale of tears, and desperately tries to prove that not only
salvation in the next life, but survival and prosperity in this one, is an
entirely fair selective process, a harsh but just contest, in which strength
and vigour are rewarded. In fact the main transformation operated by radical
Protestantism is the shifting of salvation from the next world into this one
through the notion of a providential influence on events in this life. The
outcome of our lives on earth must therefore reflect God’s justice. The
virtuous and industrious prosper, the idle and lazy starve. That is God’s plan. It is
just and good. The most godly social system is the one that makes sure this
happens. Life is a competitive struggle and we should make it even more
competitive. It is easy to see what a justification this provides for the laissez-faire capitalist ideology of
unrestricted, ruthless competition.
But it is equally
important to see that the culmination of this Protestant-capitalist ideology of
divine election, or the harsh goddess Nature’s selection of the fittest,
is Hitler’s Third Reich (Joachim’s Third Kingdom),
in which the elect – the fittest and strongest – will rule for a thousand
years, after the final battle of Armageddon to eliminate the corrupt and
degenerate – the hydra-headed beast (Jewry) – from the face of
the earth. A new order where gentlemen in black uniforms will stand at the head
of queues of naked men and women and with a nod of the head judge them fit or
unfit, saved or damned. Auschwitz is a
striking image of the ultimate destination of Darwinism: a selection process where those “good at surviving” are allowed to
continue their slave labour, and those “not good at surviving” are destined for
the fire. But Auschwitz is not so much a
Darwinian hell as a Darwinian heaven – the place where real
selection on the basis of survival capacities can take place unhindered by
those humanist scruples that interfere with the stern processes of nature in
societies still living in the ethical afterglow of defunct Christianity. Auschwitz is, in short, an ideal condition from the
Darwinist’s point of view – one of those ongoing
Malthusian catastrophes of intense competition where quite small variations
among individuals (the thickness of an emaciated thigh, or a greater ability at
collaboration, treachery, informing, cruelty or prostitution) will spell the
difference between life and death.
The conflict
between Darwinism and American Christian Fundamentalist Creationism is therefore paradoxically a conflict between
two currents of Protestantism. Creationism reflects a traditional,
simple-minded faith that every word of the bible is literally true. Darwinism
is a continuation of the Unitarian tradition of Darwin’s family milieu – the progressive
demystification of religion until it transfers the function of God to Nature.
But it is a particular Calvinist version of God that is being transferred to
Nature. This is the God of predestination, of salvation of the elect by divine
grace. This faith presents all the features of
harsh selection, arbitrariness and even tautology basic to Darwinism.
Salvation is not open to all; the vast majority of mankind are damned. Nor does
man choose salvation; his corrupt will is incapable of any virtuous act. It is
God Who chooses His elect by an arbitrary act of grace. And the elect of God
chosen from all eternity are the only ones saved. But there is a peculiar
corollary of this which many believers recognized. Once chosen by God the elect
cannot reject salvation. Even their sins and vices do not compromise their
salvation, because it does not depend on them but on God. God saves by an
arbitrary act of grace, and the works and conduct of the saved make no
difference. But what then of the man who acts virtuously but has not been
chosen? Is his damnation not an indictment of God’s justice? Not at
all, because virtue without God’s grace is an illusion. God’s act of
arbitrary grace decides on the elect, whether seemingly virtuous or not, and
those whom He has not chosen may strive vainly in the paths of virtue without
ever arriving at salvation.
We can compare
this whole viewpoint with that of the neo-Darwinists Simpson, Waddington and
McGowan: fitness is reproductive success, irrespective of the physical
qualities of the animal. Fitness does not depend on inherent characteristics;
it is a state conferred by an external event – survival (i.e.
the lion finding your neighbour more appetizing.) If an animal survived and
reproduced, it was selected, and was therefore superior in fitness, whatever
its individual qualities. And if an individual is saved, it is because he has
been chosen by God, not anything to do with his own moral conduct. It should be
clear by now how closely Darwinism (especially in its modern tautological form)
shadows the doctrines of Calvin – salvation not by one’s own efforts or
virtues but by divine grace. The tautological definition of the elect of God –
those that are saved – mirrors the tautological definition of the fittest – those that
survive. The apparent injustices are referred to an inscrutable divine will – predestination
or the genes of success. All that has happened in the move from Calvin to Darwin is that the
selecting God has become an impersonal Nature. Otherwise the world-view is
essentially the same.
Now it is
interesting that many of Darwin’s contemporaries,
while accepting what they saw as his proof of the evolution of species,
rejected his theory of natural selection. Most of his contemporaries still
preferred Lamarckism. Lamarck’s view, if you remember, is that evolution occurs when the animal, facing new
conditions, changes its behaviour, strives to adapt, its new exertions modify
it physically, and its offspring inherit these modifications. Why would so many
Victorians prefer this picture? Because Lamarckism mirrors the other major
current of Protestantism: salvation not by grace or faith alone but by good
works, keeping the commandments and charity (the doctrine in fact defended by
the Council of Trent in 1545 against Luther’s view that grace alone
saves man.) It is this version that prevailed in Victorian England, especially
among High Church Anglicans and Wesleyans, who had followed the Dutch Arminian
doctrines of the early 17th century. According to this theory, God
does not select His chosen ones in advance by predestination or an arbitrary
act of grace. Men by their own free will choose salvation both by having faith
and striving to lead good lives. If you try hard enough you can be saved. In
the same way, if the animal tries hard enough it can adapt. Fitness is not
genetically pre-determined: we can alter our fitness by striving. That is the
essence of Lamarckism as it is of the Anglican and Wesleyan brands of
Protestantism. Salvation is open to all by striving, man still has free will.
The animal becomes fit through its own efforts. It grows a longer neck by
stretching upwards. Its genes are altered by its own behaviour, not by some
arbitrary, accidental mutation. And man is saved by his own good works, not by predestined
grace. Anglican and Wesleyan currents of Protestantism reject the Calvinist
elect and make salvation democratic and open to everyone to choose. And Lamarck
makes adaptation open to every animal. There is no selection of a privileged
few genetic variations. The animal’s own efforts will save it.
It is Lamarckism that was closer to the majority religious beliefs of Darwin’s England,
and it is not surprising that Lamarckism stubbornly persisted as the preferred
evolutionary theory, being espoused by Samuel Butler, Bernard Shaw and even
Herbert Spencer. One can see how Lamarck’s theory appealed more to
the upwardly mobile liberal middle classes of Darwin’s time: they
liked to believe in an equal chance for all, and hard work, not the privilege
of birth, as the path to success.
Calvinism is
perhaps the beginning of the modern totalitarian impulse, in that it posits the
existence of an elite chosen by God, on a basis known only to Him, and (by
implication) predestined to salvation no
matter what their actions or behaviour. The decoupling of salvation from the
moral behaviour of the individual is a major step in the violation of a natural
sense of human justice. If God has chosen His favourites in advance,
irrespective of their moral conduct, then justice has to be redefined as
something inscrutable, something we cannot judge of by ourselves (only God or
the Party can judge.) What characterizes Calvinism and Social Darwinism as
moral systems is their determination to impose a concept of justice that violates
our natural sense of justice. Calvinism is revolutionary for its violation of
natural human sentiments – and this is the characteristic of all revolutionary
ideologies, whether of the Marxist-Leninist or Darwinist-Hitlerist branch. When
someone tries to persuade us that another human being dying of hunger in the
gutter, or being carted off to a gulag or bombed under a pile of rubble, is not
to be pitied, because his fate demonstrates that God (or Nature, or History)
did not favour him with His grace, and therefore nor should we, then we are in
the presence of a revolutionary violation of natural human morality. Cruel
inhumanity is being represented to us as a higher good, a necessary harshness
in the accomplishment of history’s great plan. We have emerged from a century
where entire peoples and classes of people were exterminated by dictators as
part of a programme to redesign human society according to some ideological
blueprint. There is always a sophisticated ideological reason, an invocation of
the laws of Nature or of History, to show why normal human morality and
compassion for suffering should not apply in these cases. These revolutionary
ideologies always attempt to persuade us that what is obviously unjust is
really just, by some higher reasoning – that what seems cruel is
really moral on another level. This is the key opening argument of Herbert
Spencer’s Social Darwinist opus: nature is a little cruel in
order to be very kind. By letting the bad workman and his family starve, or the
lazy sparrow and her family starve, we are serving the higher purposes of the
universe. These purposes are an inscrutable mystery (like the decisions of the
Communist Party to purge certain comrades) but you must have faith that
progress is thereby being served, that these harsh and cruel sacrifices are a
necessary means to some greater goal. It
is clear that this Darwinist attitude to cruel suffering as a means to an end
imbues not only the capitalist and Nazi ideologies but also the
Marxist-Leninist one (making it easy for so many modern academics to be both
Darwinists and Marxists.) It is essential to see how Calvinism transcended the
fading of Christianity and imposed itself on the post-Christian world-view –
above all in the belief in the movement of mankind towards millennial salvation
under the direction of an elite arbitrarily chosen and acting according to
inscrutable principles. The moral ideology of various strains of Protestantism
pervades the entire world-view of the 20th century. Darwin himself
was hopelessly muddled on an emotional level by his attempt to reconcile his
Christian faith in God’s providence with the harsh facts of existence,
including such tragedies as his favourite daughter’s death. He ends
up paradoxically rejecting Christian belief but replacing it with a peculiar
belief that Nature in its harshness and cruelty is working for the best. But
why should it be working for the best? That is the unexplained premise of the
Darwinist viewpoint. It is a hangover from Christian optimism about the universe,
but without God. And this kind of optimism is even uglier and more irrational
without God than with Him.
Classical and
Renaissance man’s attitude to Nature was far more ambiguous and
contradictory than the Darwinists’. Most often he found in Nature a pattern of
behaviour that was balanced, harmonious and just, illustrating his own moral
precepts, in which case he could find:
….tongues in trees, books in
the running brooks,
Sermons in stones and good
in everything. 104
This view gave rise to the
genre of fables, whether of Aesop or La Fontaine, where animal behaviour seemed
to provide us with moral lessons for our own lives. Human beings enjoyed seeing
in the animal world the mirror of their own moral and mental qualities: the
industry of the ant, the slyness of the fox, the rapacity of the crow. Nature
also seemed to have a force of self-regeneration and balance which man looked
on as a model. Molière saw Nature as a guiding principle in a society whose
luxury, vices and mental perversions were distorting man. The romantics saw
Nature as a spiritual force having a therapeutic effect upon the soul newly
oppressed by a harsh industrial environment. But whenever classical man saw
Nature’s brutal and cruel side, he stepped back and
distanced himself from it, and invoked his own allegiance to a higher law, as
Hesiod does in the passage we have already quoted:
The Son of Chronos gave this
law for men:
That animals and fish and
winged birds
Should eat each other, for
they have no law.
But mankind has the law of
Right from him,
Which is the better way. 105
Classical and Renaissance
men saw in Nature what they wanted to, using it to reinforce their own social
and humane instincts when it agreed with them, and invoking a higher, divine
law when it did not. The divine law they invoked always prescribed the kind,
just, and co-operative behaviour needed for a happy and prosperous society.
Classical writers did not see the world as necessarily a good or happy place,
but they saw man as having a duty to obey a divinely inspired moral law in his
own life. Most classical philosophers from Aristotle to Cicero thought this moral law was universal,
that it took precedence over the laws of states, and that all human beings had
access to it through philosophy. They would never have dreamed of recommending
humans to imitate the predatory behaviour of animals, however common it might
be in practice. Plautus’s remark “Man is a wolf to man” was a
condemnation of this behaviour, not an endorsement. The Social Darwinists’ belief that the
pattern of Nature is a merciless dog-eat-dog struggle where the strongest
prevail, and their belief that man, as merely another animal, is subject to the
same struggle and must follow its rules, was the most damaging attack on human
morality ever made, and it led straight to Auschwitz.
And Darwin is
the prime culprit in this revolutionary attack on man’s moral and
humane sense. This is not to say that Darwin
personally was an evil man or sought to undermine traditional moral behaviour.
But his ideology opened the gates not only to the Social Darwinists, with their
jungle capitalism, but also to Hitler – and many of his modern
followers have a distinctly Hitlerian cast of mind. They believe, with Darwin
and Spencer, that the most ruthless competition, letting the weak go to the
wall, is the best way of regulating human affairs, because it is what happens
in Nature. And while this ideology remains a major, popular influence on our
civilization, with all the prestige of an allegedly scientific description of
the universe, our societies will continue to fail in their goal of promoting
human happiness.
13)
REPLACING DARWIN
What then is the future of Darwinism? Is it on the point
of collapse? Are we likely to get an official repudiation of Darwinism, an
admission of error from the scientific establishment over the next decades?
Probably not. The cult of sheer intellectual dishonesty and bad faith that now
pervades the universities in every field will ensure that Darwinism is never
formally repudiated, but is merely shifted gradually to the margins, referred
to less and less, and finally ignored by a new generation, without its
fanatical, totalitarian disciples ever being denounced as wrong. We will shift
from Darwinism being unquestionable dogma to Darwinism being an unmentionable
embarrassment, without transition or debate. We have only to look at what has
happened to other cases of error or fraud in recent academic history to see the
bad faith that awaits us on the subject of Darwin. Karl Marx’s theories have now been
discredited, both morally and politically, in almost every country where they
were put into practice, and shown to have been responsible for over a hundred
million deaths. But not a single Marxist professor has lost his job in a
Western university for peddling an evil, mad ideology to his students. They
still continue doing it. Even more spectacularly, Alfred Kinsey’s famous reports
on sexuality which revolutionized the sexual climate in the United States
and the Western world in the post-war period, and became the bible of
progressive sociologists for fifty years, were revealed a decade ago to be a
gigantic fraud. 106 Kinsey was a liar and a cheat who took his “samples” of a “cross-section” of the American
population from the particular social areas which would support his
pre-ordained conclusions. One quarter of his sample of males were convicted
prisoners, half of whom were serving sentences for homosexual acts, at the time
a crime. When one eighth of your sample are convicted homosexuals, and one
quarter are in prison, cut off from women, it is not surprising that you come
up with the “statistical finding” that ten per
cent of American males are homosexual, and thirty-seven per cent have had
homosexual experiences (more serious recent studies have shown the first figure
is 300 per cent wrong, and the second figure 600 per cent wrong.) Among
females, he also picked and chose the groups that would give him the results he
wanted – evidence of high rates of sexual promiscuity. He
thought that black college women would be promising material and sent out
surveys to a large number of them. When their responses in fact showed
unusually conservative sexual behaviour, he cut this group out of his results.
Yet despite the devastating exposure of Kinsey’s methods, there
has been no huge scandal, no earthquake in academia to find out how this fraud
was possible, and how it passed for so long undetected. Among his disciples,
ensconced in their departmental chairs and continuing to revere this charlatan,
no heads have rolled. So little attention has been given the revelations about
him that Kinsey has just been made the subject of a Hollywood
film glorifying his scientific achievements. Social scientists continue to
quote Kinsey as an authority. His methods may have been flawed, they say, but
his results were still a fair reflection of the reality. He supported the set
of ideological and moral beliefs that they subscribe to (the creed of sexual
liberation and the normality of homosexuality) so he was still basically right,
a courageous rebel against the stifling conservatism of the time. In short,
Kinsey is an icon of the sexual liberationist and gay left and is therefore
untouchable. Evidence not only of his fraudulent methods, but of his complicity
in the paedophile abuse of hundreds of children during his “research” into child
orgasm, are dismissed as the product of ideological hatred, “homophobia” or religious
fanaticism. Since the attacks on him come largely from academics with religious
convictions, they are rejected in advance as biased. They must in no way be
allowed to detract from Kinsey’s iconic status.
Darwin
occupies an even higher position in the natural sciences and on the right wing
of economic theory than Kinsey does in the social sciences and on the left. We
can therefore expect no dethronement of this idol either. It is in fact almost
impossible in Britain to
publish anything even remotely critical of Darwin. Though his theories are the
underpinning of right-wing capitalist ideology, he has iconic status also on
the left for his supposed demolition of Christian beliefs – which are now
seen in academia as a sinister form of right-wing populism. British and
American academics are now the guardians of a rigid materialistic orthodoxy, whose
authority must never be challenged, in case it encourages “irrational” world-views. The
fact that Darwin
is being attacked by the Christian fundamentalist right makes his theory – the
foundation stone of both right-wing capitalism and Nazism – appear to be some
sort of bastion of “rational” scientific thought for the academic left as well.
For academics to admit that the chief idol of their pantheon was wrong in his
basic theory would cast unacceptable doubt upon the infallible status of
academic “science”. Academia is no longer a
space for open enquiry. It is a fortress of committed resistance to what it
fears is the rising tide of an irrational “spiritual” backlash.
Academics see the threat of Christian fundamentalism as a new barbarian
invasion, and any tactic to fight it is justified. In this new intellectual
war-zone there in no concept of truth or integrity left. Any concession could
give a fatal advantage to the enemy. The academic establishment has quite
simply lost its capacity for indignation at fraud, systematic lying, and the
totalitarian suppression of the truth. All that counts is to win the culture
war against the ideological enemy.
We can expect
then no public announcement of Darwin’s fall from grace, but
simply a gradual half-embarrassed turning of academic backs upon him, a
neglect, a gradual forgetting, so that he and his fanatical disciples fall out
of favour without ever being refuted or denounced. As with Marx, he will retain
his status as a great pioneer, despite the catastrophic and murderous errors
into which he misled the world. But there is no doubt that Darwin’s actual theory (like Marx’s) will one day
be discreetly shelved. When this happens, what will be put in its place?
14) EVOLUTION AS GROUP DIVERGENCE
A new theory will
probably put together a number of factors into a composite rather than a simple
view of evolution. Natural selection and sexual selection will be retained for
those areas where it has been convincingly demonstrated as a motor of
evolution: the development of ornaments among males of arena species and of
size and armaments among the males of harem species – in both of which
differential breeding undoubtedly takes place. Among most other species, only
resistance to disease and the development of larger and rounder body shapes
against cold will be ascribed to natural selection. For the rest of evolution,
other mechanisms will be invoked by which new varieties may arise. Even the
arch-Darwinist Dawkins, in discussing the causes of the divergence of new varieties
and species tells us that “nobody doubts that the most important ingredient is
accidental geographical separation.” 107 This bypasses any Darwinian notion of natural selection of random
mutations completely. The reduction of a gene pool through isolation on an
island or across a mountain range is enough to form quite different
permutations and combinations of genes in the descendants than would have
occurred if the group had remained in breeding contact with a much wider group.
Such a limitation of gene pools is probably in itself a major cause of new
varieties arising. And there are other ways in which this genetic isolation is
reinforced.
Hostility between
different colonies may also play a major role in the genetic isolation of
groups. Ants and rats systematically attack and kill any member of their
species that does not belong to their colony but makes the mistake of wandering
into it. This hostility among tribes and colonies of the same species makes
breeding between them impossible and in effect separates each group
genetically, laying the basis for a long-term evolution into different
varieties and eventually perhaps into different species. We are beginning to
understand the extent to which colonies of birds are also genetically isolated
from each other by refusal to cross-breed, but more research needs to be done
here. Do we know whether year after year all the migrating birds that return to
a particular place to nest are the same individuals or their lineal
descendants? Do they also refuse to breed with outsiders, or refuse to let them
into the colony, and can they tell who belongs to the colony, as rats and ants
can, because of tiny genetic differences? There is of course strong resistance
to cross breeding between species (Weiner speaks of “sexual repulsion”), but it also
exists between varieties of the same species, or they could not remain
distinct. We know that a similar form of hostility to, or reluctance to breed
with, those outside the tribal group is found among humans. It is called racism
or tribalism. The great variety of tribes each with distinct physical features
on the African continent, often living in close proximity, would not have been
possible unless strict rules of tribal exclusiveness had prevented
cross-breeding. This urge to prevent tribal cross-breeding lies at the root of
the caste system in India
(where the invaders sought to keep themselves racially distinct from the people
they conquered) as well as of various forms of racism and tribalism among other
nations. It appears that in many species, including man, once races and tribes
develop a different physical appearance (that is, become distinct “varieties” of the species,
whose children inherit their particular features) each race seems to feel an
urge to preserve its distinctness and refuses to breed with the others. Races
of different appearance may not be actively hostile to each other but they will
prefer not to inter-marry. The crucial question to test racist attitudes to
other peoples has always been: would you like your daughter to marry one? Most
people on the planet, of all racial origins, would probably still, in the case
of very different races, reply no. The instinct to preserve racial gene pools
and transmit their own distinctive features to grandchildren is still stronger
than the current ideology of multi-racialism, product of muddled, post-colonial
Western guilt. Perhaps we will one day see what we might call “reproductive
racism” – the reluctance to breed with other races – as merely part
of the evolutionary process whereby different varieties of human beings seek to
preserve their genetic isolation from one another, in exactly the same way
varieties of birds do. Beliefs about the inferiority or wickedness of other
races, nations, tribes or castes may simply be rationalizations of a deeper
urge towards gene pool separation. Language divergence itself may have had a
function in separating tribes, since preventing communication would hinder
cross-breeding and preserve separate identity. Language and culture (distinct
dances, music, clothes, stories, songs, art, religion) may all have functioned
as divergence mechanisms, isolating the racial gene pool, in the way that the
development of some ornament, mating song or mating dance will genetically
isolate a bird variety, and push it towards sub-speciation. In short, we may
see all the cultural identity mechanisms of each tribe and race as part of a
process of gene pool isolation, leading each group to develop a more and more
distinctive physical appearance.
The long-term
direction of this (before we shrunk our planet by travel, colonization and
migration) may have been toward sub-speciation, the development of races among
humans which would have no desire and finally no capacity to cross-breed. Darwin thought this would
probably have taken place with Africans over the next ten thousand years, if
whites had not settled that continent. 108 It is notable that
repugnance to cross-breed seems to come much earlier in the process of
divergence than any biological inability to cross-breed fertile young. Many
similar but distinct species (lions and tigers, buffalo and cattle, even horses
and donkeys) can sometimes be made to breed fertile young (mules are infertile
but hinnies are not always), which suggests that for them the main barrier to
hybridization is an instinct against it, not a biological impossibility. When
the instinctive barrier to hybridization breaks down, there may be particular
environmental causes. The Grants found a high degree (ten per cent) of
hybridization between different species of finch on Daphne in the Galapagos
after the population boom and bust of 1983. 109 This may possibly be
explained by the overcrowding of the boom period. The Grants observed that
sometimes young birds learn the song of the species next door, instead of their
father’s song. This “misimprinting” makes them fight with wrong-species males
singing “their” song and sometimes to mate with wrong species females.110
This would perhaps be more likely to occur in conditions of overcrowding, where
parental “cultures” are more difficult to transmit to offspring – and where
even feeding habits may blur as species poach one another’s food sources, thus
confusing the young about their real “culture”. Hybridization is known to occur
more readily among domesticated species, perhaps because “cultural” differences
(of lifestyle and feeding habits) no longer play their separating role. In
other words a blurring of “cultural” differences may remove the sexual
repulsion between different species or varieties which prevents hybridization –
a repulsion which is a key expression of the universal drive towards species
divergence.
There is further
evidence for an instinctive drive towards divergence in the behaviour of lek or
arena species. Darwin
was at a loss to explain the taste of the females of these species for male
decorative features such as long tails or extravagant ruffs or colourful
crests. What makes the females consider a particular trait beautiful and worth
breeding with? He ended up with a circular explanation, that they will be
attracted to the features they know other females will be attracted to, thus
guaranteeing the future reproductive success of their descendants. This is
highly unsatisfactory, because it suggests these characteristics are chosen at
random by the females, and this does not explain why they all make the same
choice. It would seem more logical to suggest that the characteristics of those
males in lek species which win the display contest and get to breed with all
the females are always the characteristics which are most typical and
distinctive in that species. If a species has a bright red ruff, then the male
with the reddest ruff will win the day. If it has a remarkably long tail, the
longest tail will win the day. There seems to be a collective instinct in lek
species to allow the most typical “pure” specimen of the
species to breed the most and influence its future, thereby reinforcing its
divergence from other species. Even among monogamous finches, Weiner thought
females judging a suitor looked intently at his beak. This would make sense if
the beak was the feature that most differentiated the species.111 We
could posit then an instinct towards gene-group divergence as one of the
driving forces of evolution. Whenever a variety develops distinctive
characteristics, they will see these characteristics as sexually attractive and
will mate in ways that accentuate them. This could explain why in both lek
species and harem species the distinctive characteristics (wide antlers, long tails)
will keep being developed long after they have ceased to be of any practical
use and have become in fact maladapted for survival. The dying out of the Irish
elk because its antlers got too large to run in forests is a case in point. Why
keep developing a feature which actually endangers survival? The answer could
be: because of the instinct to make the species yet more divergent from others – to reinforce its
specificity. This would answer the question: on what grounds do the females
judge certain characteristics of the males to be desirable or beautiful (red
ruffs, long tails, etc.) What is the basis of their attraction, and why do they
all make the same choices? Darwinists themselves have tended to split between
those who saw these choices of ornament as purely aesthetic, and those who
thought the ornaments were selected as signs of good health. But what if the
ornament is considered beautiful because it is species-specific, and the
attraction of the female is towards whatever feature makes the species most
distinct from others? This would parallel the sense of beauty among human
beings. People tend to consider beautiful the traits that are most specific to
their particular race. Among white people a very white skin was traditionally
valued; among Africans, the blackest skin was traditionally preferred (as
Darwin himself points out.) Among the Nordics, tall stature, blond hair and
blue eyes were considered beautiful; among the Greeks, curved noses; among
certain South East Asian peoples, slenderness and delicacy of feature. Does
this not suggest there is a universal attraction towards – and an instinct to
promote – those characteristics of one’s own variety or race that make it
distinctive – in other words, an urge to make it diverge further?
It seems clear
then that once a variety or species exists, its innate tendency is to make
itself more and more distinct from others by developing its most specific
features. But how does the initial process, the formation of a new variety, get
going? How does the initial gene-pool isolation, which is at the root of
species divergence, arise?
Sometimes this
gene pool isolation may be accidental. In one case in a laboratory at Rockefeller University, New York, a number of fruit flies of the
variety Llanos-A were kept for five years in isolation. This was enough to make
their descendants incapable of breeding fertile hybrids with other strains of
fruit fly – which had been perfectly compatible with them five
years before. Five years of genetic isolation and inbreeding had pushed the
flies towards sub-speciation – an inability to breed fertile young outside their
group.112 But in most cases
in nature, the gene pool isolation takes place through geographic separation of
some kind. This geographic separation may be total and in a sense involuntary,
as when birds migrate to another island and settle there, and lose all contact
with their parent group. But sometimes a number of individuals voluntarily
isolate themselves genetically from others of their species, by moving away and
forming their own gene pool. What mechanism makes them do this? How do we get
the impulse of separatism within a species? One answer is: because within a
species there is a tendency to form different “cultures”. Cultural separatism
leads to racial separatism.
Within a species
different lifestyles and methods of food gathering often develop, as
individuals spread out to fill all the available feeding niches in an
environment. Some birds may feed on one kind of seed, some on another, some on
insects, some on fruit, all involving different techniques and habits. This
happens regularly within populations of the same species, because it is simply
easier to find food if not everybody is going for the same kind. These
different feeding habits become literally “cultures” in that the young imitate
their parents and learn how to gather food from watching them.113
Among birds the “culture” includes not only learning
their parents’ food gathering techniques, but their mating songs – of which there
are often two within the same species. (Scientists have also discovered that
among certain fish the electrical mating signals divide into two sorts, with
some males responding to only one signal by the females, and other males the
other signal.) Now the formation of these different “cultures” or lifestyles
within a species will naturally push the species towards division into
subgroups – provided the environment allows some measure of
geographic separation. Sometimes it doesn’t allow this, and these
cases are highly instructive.
Let us take the
example of the Cocos
Island, a tiny island
north of the Galapagos group. On this island, all the finches are of one
species, physically identical even in beak shape. But different lifestyles have
developed among them. Here is how Jonathan Weiner describes them:
Some
eat bugs, others crustaceans, still others nectar, fruit, seeds. There are
specialists that eat mostly on the ground, others in bushes, others in tall
trees. Normally to assemble a list of
birds with such a wide range of specialities one would have to collect not only
many species, but many genera, or even many families, groups of genera. Yet the
finches of Cocos Island are a single species. These
finches cannot diverge and ramify on Cocos the way their siblings have in the
Galapagos archipelago. On Cocos island they can’t get away from
one another. The place is too small, and the nearest land is too far away..…There is no
chance for geographic isolation. Insects
and snails can radiate in such a place, because for them even a tiny island is
big enough for them to present, in effect, an archipelago of isolated habitats,
but birds do not radiate on single isolated islands. 114
It is strange to see a
writer get so near to a key idea and fail to grasp its full significance.
Weiner’s Darwinist mindset prevents him from shifting this crucial observation
to centre stage in his thinking. The origin of new species is not random
mutations or minute variations selected by the ruthless struggle for survival.
The origin of new species is the formation of separate “cultures” (feeding habits
and lifestyles) within a species, in a geographic situation that permits the “cultural group” to isolate
itself genetically and then adapt itself physically to its distinct lifestyle –
something they cannot do on Cocos
Island.
Weiner comments on the fact that, although the finches on
Cocos Island have a wide range of different,
specialized food-gathering habits, they are not very efficient at these tasks.
In fact they are rather clumsy and bad at them. Why? Because they have not been
able to adapt themselves physically, notably in beak shape, to their own
specific lifestyle needs. They have not developed specialized tools for the
job, because they are still in the same breeding pool as other finches with
other specialized “trades” – so they can’t agree, for example, on
which way their beak should be modified. One might want a longer, thinner beak
for his food gathering lifestyle, but another wants a shorter, deeper beak for
his particular trade. Since they all interbreed, they have all kept the same
beak and continue with the same non-specialized tool, doing each job rather
badly. If they had the geographic space the various cultures would separate
into different gene pools, breed only with those following the same lifestyle
or trade, and develop the tools (notably the beak shape) to enable them to do
their particular job better. This is what finches appear to have done on the Galapagos islands. And this seems to explain the
evolution of new varieties and even new species (whichever the Galapogos
finches finally turn out to be.)
The crucial bone
of contention, of course, is whether in this process of specialization of their
tools, the main path has been natural selection – the higher
breeding success of the few individuals accidentally endowed with a slightly
more specialized beak – or Lamarckism – the constant effort of a
cultural group to use their beak in a particular way, switching on a gene to
push the beak in a particular direction in future generations to make this task
easier. I would go for Lamarck.
The reason is the speed of the process. Physical
adaptation happens a lot faster than has been thought. In 1967 a hundred
finches from the US Government Bird Reservation on Laysan Island in the Pacific
were transported to other finch-free islands (Pearl and Hermes Reef) a few hundred miles
away as a reserve pool of birds because the Laysan finches were endangered.
Only twenty years later it was found that the descendants of these hundred
finches had already developed various different beak shapes, corresponding to
different food-gathering habits.115 Now this would seem to be far
too short a period to allow the chance mutations, followed by selection of the
favourable ones, required by the neo-Darwinist theory, which normally posits
hundreds of thousands or even millions of years for such changes (a change of
one per cent in the length of an organ over a million years is defined as one “darwin”, a suggested
unit of evolution – so the Darwinists are normally expecting
excruciatingly slow change.) 116 Yet the birds from Laysan changed
their beaks in twenty years, or some half-dozen generations. Researchers have
excluded bill wear through use and “founder effects” through having eccentric
founding couples on different islands. This leaves either natural selection of
an extraordinarily rapid sort, or the direct effect of different food gathering
habits on the beak itself. The adaptation does seem rather faster than can be
explained by any process of chance mutations or the repeated selection of tiny
random variations. One researcher cites as a precedent Grant’s evidence
already discussed of a beak evolution among the survivors of the drought on
Daphne in the Galapagos. We have already commented on the dubiousness of the
larger beak size claims when the survivors were mostly older males – which by
definition have the largest beaks (and also the muscle to defend their food
patch better in tough times.) No larger average beak size was preserved in the
population over the long term, even after a catastrophic elimination of 96 per
cent of the population. An updated form
of Lamarck, theorizing the possibility that genes can be switched on as a
result of stresses and pressures within the lifetime of the individual, making
offspring better able to cope with those stresses, is perhaps a better
explanation. If you have striven all your life to develop longer legs or bigger
lungs, your descendants may be born with a tendency to develop them. We know
that the Aymara Indians of the Bolivian Andes have bigger lungs, and that this
is at least partly genetic – despite being a characteristic which all those who
grow up in the Andean highlands develop to some extent. In other words it is an
environmentally acquired characteristic which some races now have to an unusual
degree and transmit genetically. We also know that European migrants to America in the last century grew taller in just
two generations – something Darwin
comments on. Something as fast as this was at work on the Laysan finches.
It is this question of adaptive change and the
Lamarckian hypothesis of the direct influence of the behaviour of the animal on
its own physical structure which is still the subject of bitter dispute in
evolutionary theory, despite the Darwinists’ claims to have “discredited”
Lamarck. Many famous biologists,
including the great French zoologist Pierre-Paul Grassé, refuse to accept Darwin’s natural
selection as capable of causing the extraordinarily sophisticated adaptations
we see in all living things. As we have argued, natural selection can explain
some things very well: the evolution of size, armaments, or disease-resistance
(and the subcategory, sexual selection, can explain the evolution of ornaments
in non-monogamous species with differential breeding.) But what of a beak which
has adapted itself perfectly to the task of opening one particular type of
pine-cone, like the various species of crossbill, whose bills, as the name
suggests, actually cross over at the ends to make them into fine little
wrenches? The problem with natural selection as a mechanism of change is that
it requires huge rates of death in order to change a beak, by selecting the
tiny handful of most adapted ones. As the Grants saw on the Galapagos, to
change a finch’s beak four per cent in depth even temporarily, 96 per cent of
the females of a species had to die prematurely of starvation, 75 per cent of
the males also had to die, and five sixths of the survivors had to remain
without reproducing. But death rates like this cannot be responsible for the
adaptations of a beak to specialized niche-feeding (such as one type of
pine-cone) because specialized niche-feeding must be voluntary. Surely the
species would change its feeding habits and abandon that niche rather than suffer
such a high death rate from starvation. Nature cannot bludgeon creatures into
ultra-specialization by inflicting mass death on those that fail at it. They
can only be enticed into it by the success it brings. Large amounts of failure
would induce the species to return to different ways of feeding. The problem with
very specialized niche-feeding (such as crossbill finches tearing open a single
kind of pine-cone) is that only the successful will persist in this niche.
There is no obligation in a luxuriant forest to feed on only one type of pine
cone. There are lots of other birds eating other things. Niche-feeding can only
be driven by success, not failure. Yet natural selection is driven by huge
rates of failure. The most adapted beaks can only be selected and developed by
mass death of the less adapted. But any repeated selection drastic enough to
change the beak would long before then push the species to look for other food
instead. Niche-feeding, in short, appears to be chosen by success, and the more
successful it is, the less selection there will be. How then does the adapted
feature (e.g. the crossbill finch’s beak) keep evolving and becoming more
specialized, if this feeding habit is highly successful, and mass death is not
culling the less adapted beaks and promoting the more adapted ones? In short,
the only mechanism Darwinism proposes for shaping a beak for a niche-feeding
habit (such as a particular type of pine-cone) is a rate of starvation (from
being unable to open the pine-cones) that would discourage the species from
pursuing this niche-feeding habit, and push it back towards more varied
feeding. Natural selection is a self-sabotaging method which cannot lead to
voluntary specialization in feeding habits – and yet specialization is the very
path that most evolution of new species has evidently taken. This is the crucial weakness of Darwin's theory of natural selection. Natural selection is a mechanism whereby evolution is driven by mass death of the less adapted. But the problem is most evolution is towards specialization in food gathering habits, and developing the physical tools most adapted to that specialization. This specialization cannot be driven by mass death, because mass death woud lead the species to abandon that specialization. Specialization can only be driven by success. Only success can drive a species to specialize further and further in a particular food gathering habit. Failure, a 96 per cent death rate, would lead them to abandon that food and try another one. Persistent failure and mass death is at the heart of natural selection; only persistent success can drive specialization, which is the path of most evolution of species.
The alternative
evolutionary theory, that of Lamarck, would explain the crossbill finch’s beak
like this. The use of the beak in a particular way places stress upon it, which
would be relieved if it changed physically in a certain direction. This stress
influences which of the slightly varying copies of the bird’s DNA is
transmitted to offspring, and the descendants gradually, over time, come into
the world with a beak that facilitates more and more the uses to which it is
habitually put, thereby relieving the stress upon it. Now Lamarck of course,
did not know about DNA and would not have explained it quite like this. But he
argued that environment and behaviour act directly on organisms, and the changes
they make can be transmitted to offspring. He cited in particular the use or
disuse of limbs having an effect on their size. Darwin himself believed Lamarck’s theory in these
cases (such as the disuse of wings in flightless birds, or the stronger leg-bones
of domestic ducks compared with wild ducks), but twentieth-century
neo-Darwinists reject Lamarck with the most vehement contempt. They insist on
the absolute imperviousness of the genetic code carried by an organism to any
influence by its behaviour, its own physical development, or its environment.
But the principle announced a century ago by Weismann that the genetic code
that governs procreation cannot be influenced by any change in the body cells
because the two are separated by a firewall is under attack from much new
research. Many experiments have proved that this firewall does not operate. For
a start it is known that it does not operate in plants, which readily transmit
to offspring the modifications made to them. Ted Steele, an Australian micro-biologist,
has demonstrated a method by which acquired characteristics can be inherited by
animals: viruses are able to replicate mutations in body cells and transfer
them to sexual cells, where they become inheritable, a process known as “reverse transcription”. His “Somatic Selection
Theory”, suggesting the Weismann barrier can be penetrated,
provoked controversy in the scientific world, with major thinkers such as Sir
Karl Popper and Nobel prize-winner Sir Peter Medawar hailing it, and
anti-Lamarck fanatics like Dawkins trying desperately to discredit it. 117
Steele’s experiments built on the work of Medawar, who
proved that tolerance of foreign tissue by the immune system can be acquired if
alien tissue is injected into newborn mice. They would later accept a
skin-graft from the same tissue without their immune system rejecting it. This
acquired tolerance was shown by Reg Gorczynski to be inheritable in the case of
some descendants of the mice but not all – an experiment that remains
controversial. 118 C.H.Waddington, one of the few neo-Darwinists
open to Lamarck’s ideas, made the important suggestion that environmental
influences (stress, psychological states, the individual’s own life
experience) might possibly affect which of the slightly varying copies of DNA
sequences are selected for transmission to offspring. An athletic woman, with
physical qualities acquired by intense training, may well transmit athletic
genes to her children because her activity has somehow influenced which copy of
the DNA sequences she transmits.119 There is now a movement among
the more independent-minded researchers to discover ways in which acquired
characteristics can be inherited, simply because it corresponds to a common
sense view of the world. Steele points out that the callouses on the knees of
African warthogs and the chests of ostriches, caused by rubbing the ground
where they rest on these body parts, are present in the embryo, which has never
rubbed against anything. It seems self-evident that at one stage this must have
been an acquired characteristic (a product of a behaviour pattern) which is now
inherited. How could random mutations have arrived at this? Do we see any other
evidence of random mutations occurring which cause callouses on other parts of
bodies where they are not in the least useful? 120 Moreover, if
natural selection is to explain this phenomenon, then we would also need proof
that the callouses give such a huge advantage to these animals that the few
individuals where they randomly occurred then outbred the others and took over
the species. But a lot of nature’s little peculiarities seem
a mere convenience to the animal, not a vital necessity giving it a crucial
survival advantage. Steele even points to the different squatting postures of
Asians and Australian Aborigines, which have modified the bones of their feet
differently to make the posture more comfortable – a modification present in
their babies. This characteristic can only be the result of generations of
behaviour – which has somehow got transmitted genetically to
offspring as a kind of convenience. Yet it surely presents no vital advantage
that would increase survival or reproduction rates so much that one mutated
individual would take over the race. These are the kinds of common sense observations
which fuel the search for a mechanism by which acquired characteristics can
become inherited. The pretence that there is a law of nature to prevent this
happening merely because Weismann demonstrated that mutilated rats don’t transmit the
mutilations to offspring is merely dogmatic negativity in the face of one of
the most exciting fields of scientific research.
Darwin himself
(though his fanatical disciples try to make us forget the fact) was a convinced
Larmarckian. He believed in the inheritance of acquired characteristics and he
demonstrated it with reference to domestic ducks. He showed that the
sub-species of domestic duck has developed heavier leg-bones and lighter
wing-bones than the ancestral wild duck, and he attributed this to more walking
and less flying. Changed behaviour had, as Lamarck argued, changed the bone
structure, and domestic ducks now appear to inherit this characteristic. This
evidence for Lamarck has been silently ignored by neo-Darwinists, under the
influence of the Weismann doctrine that acquired characteristics cannot be
inherited because of some alleged firewall between body cells and germ cells.
But let us look for a moment at how a neo-Darwinist would explain the thicker
leg-bones of the domestic duck.
The neo-Darwinist
theory would go like this. The struggle for survival among domestic ducks is so
strenuous and hazardous, as they stroll endlessly round the barnyard,
clambering over the broken terrain of tractor ruts and cow pies, that this
takes its toll on those individuals not born with sturdy leg-bones, and most of
them collapse and die of rheumatoid arthritis of the knee before they reach
reproductive age. Even if they survive the rigours of the daily barnyard
marathon and stagger on to mating age, they will be despised as breeding
partners for their puny thighs, and die celibate, or leave only a pitiful
brood, compared with their prolific brethren, happily equipped with the chance
mutation of sturdy leg-bones. What is more, foxes that occasionally raid the
barnyard are preternaturally disposed to pick on those ducks with thin legs,
and they pay a terrible toll, while their accidentally mutated brethren look on
with the serene compassion of those endowed with superior leg-bones. Thus, over
time only those individuals with sturdy leg-bones have survived and reproduced,
and all domestic ducks today are descended from this select few, the lucky
survivors of the harsh competition of life in the barnyard.
Isn’t it a little
easier to believe that when you walk a lot your leg-bones grow thicker? That
the leg-bones of all of them got thicker through exercise, which their
wild-duck ancestors didn’t get because they never walked anywhere? And that
no selection actually took place – they all evolved these
thicker leg-bones together? And that after several generations of developing
thicker leg-bones through walking, a gene for thicker leg-bones was switched on
and added to the genetic blueprint for a domestic duck? Isn’t this Lamarckian
theory a little easier to swallow than to believe that strolling round the
barnyard is a gruelling exercise which only those mutant individuals with the
thickest leg-bones survived?
15)
DOES EVOLUTION REQUIRE GENETIC CHANGE?
But the obsession
with genes may perhaps be a red herring. Lee Spetner and Richard Milton have
both drawn attention to how little correlation there is between the genetic
differences between animals and their actual difference in physical form. There
is more genetic difference between certain species of frog than there is
between a bat and a whale. The majority of human genes are present in a
cabbage. Spetner suggests that many evolutionary changes may be purely adaptive
to changed habits and may not necessarily be genetically encoded at all: they
simply keep recurring because the habits of the animal in each generation are
the same. Spetner’s theory becomes in fact an important rival (or
perhaps complement) to Lamarck’s. 121
Spetner argues
that evolutionary change of a kind that simply involves an adaptation of the
physical form (phenotype) of the animal, without any necessary change in the
genes (genotype) may occur far more often and rapidly than we think. He points
to the example cited already of the Laysan finches, whose beaks changed after
only twenty years on Pearl
and Hermes Reef. 122 He argues that this change was far too rapid to
have been brought about by natural selection. Instead it seems to have been a
spontaneous collective adaptation to environment, resulting from the plasticity
of the phenotype – the ability of bodies to grow differently in
different conditions. Is this evolution? Can these finches be said to have
evolved into different varieties or even species? Would this depend on whether
the change gets programmed into the genes? Tests on these birds so far appear
inconclusive.
Darwin noted this
ability of bodies to spontaneously adapt to new conditions in one or two
generations when he commented on the taller stature of European immigrants in America. He put
this down to the variation that occurs in new geographic conditions – one of
the reasons he favoured emigration of whites throughout the world – to make
them vary. But now this sudden evolution of tallness which was first noticed in
European immigrants in America
has happened to Europeans in Europe – which
would rule out geographic relocation as the cause. Dutchmen (the world’s
tallest people) are now nearly three inches taller than Americans, and their
height is steadily increasing, as is that of most Europeans, including the
British. This is in marked contrast to the nineteenth century when Americans
were much taller than Europeans, and the Dutch were quite short. Now it has
always astonished me how little attention has been paid to this by
evolutionists. Surely man’s evolution is as interesting and important as that
of a finch? European man has undergone an increase in average height since the
mid 19th century of some fourteen centimetres, or about eight per
cent, for the Dutch, and around nine centimetres for many other nations such as
the British.123 This change of height in the European race is the
most rapid and visible example of human evolution that has ever been observed,
and it has been totally ignored in discussions of evolution. The reason is the
sheer embarrassment it causes the Darwinist establishment. They don’t want to
call it evolution, or even to evoke it in discussions of evolution, precisely
because it has obviously not been caused by natural selection. They reserve the
word evolution exclusively for those changes that seem to illustrate the
Darwinian process. Thus they prove by another tautology that all evolution is
caused by natural selection: if it isn’t, it can’t be called evolution. Yet the
rise in height of European man over the past 140 years is undeniable. If this rapid
change of size had occurred to a species of finch on the Galapagos they would
be babbling about another “proof” of Darwinism. So how can this very obvious
example of evolution be understood, and what mechanism has transmitted this
modification (if it is in fact transmitted) to offspring?
Presumably, the
change in height is related to changed conditions of life: better food,
exercise, cleaner air, less hard work at a young age, more caring parenting,
better medical care for mothers and babies, and so on. But what is the
mechanism by which these changed conditions have altered us physically? Now the
neo-Darwinists would have to say that height is such an advantage in the
struggle for survival – enabling one to beat off murderers and attract and
impregnate more women – that the taller men of the late nineteenth century
had more offspring than the short men, and their taller offspring had more in
their turn, until the few tall men of the late nineteenth century took over the
race and we are all now the descendants of that happy elongated few. That is
the only way neo-Darwinism can accept that an evolutionary change occurs – the selection of
favourable random variations by the rigours of competition. The only thing
wrong with this explanation is that we know it did not happen. We are not all
the descendants of the few tall men of the nineteenth century. The tall men of
today are the great grand-children of the short men of a century ago. We have
the evidence to prove it in the form of military records of men’s height in the
armies and military academies of several European countries, which show a
steady increase in height since the mid-19th century. We have the
living evidence of generations of men in one family, in which grandfather is
170 centimetres, father is 175 and son is 180. And the idea that grandfather
was cuckolded by a taller neighbour is something that grandmother is there to
deny. So the evidence is there before us that a collective evolution has
occurred over several generations, and not some kind of selection. We are not
descended from the taller few of yesterday. The tall did not have more
offspring than the short. All the evidence indicates the contrary. There was a
correlation of class and tallness in the nineteenth century, since the upper
classes already benefited from modern conditions of food and exercise. The sons
of the gentry at Sandhurst military academy in
the mid-19th century were 22 centimetres taller at sixteen than the
poor orphan boys of the Marine Society. 124 And we know from statistics
that the upper classes did not have more children than the lower: in the 1890’s the upper
classes in England
had roughly half the number of children on average that the workers had. It was
the constant worry of the Malthusians and the eugenicists that the stupid poor
were outbreeding the clever rich, as they still do in much of the world today.
We are faced therefore with a situation where the shorter part of the
population (the poor) had twice as many children as the taller, but the result
was a general increase in height over the past four or five generations. Since
it is clear that this evolution did not occur through Darwinian natural or
sexual selection of the tallest few, how did it happen?
We can consider
this a case of what Spetner refers to: a characteristic repeatedly acquired
within each lifetime, in other words a modification of the phenotype alone.
When children receive good food, medical care, exercise and a caring
upbringing, they grow taller. The rise in living conditions over the past hundred
and forty years therefore led each generation to respond to a more favourable
environment by growing a few centimetres more. We could see this as merely an
adaptation to new conditions in one lifetime, an acquired characteristic,
without any need to suppose that it is inherited or genetically encoded. The
characteristic of greater height would simply have been reacquired in each
generation, as they all faced better conditions, with no necessary
accumulation. According to this approach, if we took a Dutch baby born today,
transported him to Pakistan, sold him to a carpet-maker, and subjected him to
the child labour and poor diet typical of the 19th century, he would only grow
to the height of a nineteenth-century Dutchman, about 170 cm instead of 184 cm.
In other words, if we remove the conditions that have led to greater height, it
will not occur, as it is a purely adaptive characteristic acquired in one
lifetime. That is one possibility. The other theory would be Lamarck’s. A modern
Lamarckian would say that the greater height produced by these improved
conditions has already affected the genes, perhaps by switching on a dormant
tallness gene. Tallness has therefore continued to develop cumulatively over
several generations, each one being taller than the one before. According to
this theory, if you transport a Dutch baby to Pakistan and subject him to
nineteenth-century working conditions, he will lose some of the height gained
over the past century, but not all of it. The gain in height, a Lamarckian
would say, has been cumulative and is now genetically encoded, so it would not
be wholly reversed by a change in conditions in one generation.
Who is to say
which explanation is right – Spetner’s idea or Lamarck’s – since we cannot
perform experiments by selling Dutch babies to Pakistani carpet-makers? On the
face of it, the Lamarckian hypothesis seems to have a strong case. There does
seem to be evidence of a cumulative gain in height, generation after
generation, which suggests each one started from a higher platform than the one
before. Furthermore, if the extra height were purely a response by each
individual to environmental conditions (that is, an acquired characteristic,
which is not passed on through the genetic code, because of the famous Weismann
barrier) we would expect to find much taller people among the well-fed upper
classes of the past. They already enjoyed modern conditions of food and
exercise: why didn’t they grow to a modern height? Now though there was
a gap in height between nineteenth century workers and gentry, even the gentry
of the past were shorter than the average person today. The elite Sandhurst graduates, sons of the aristocracy, taller than
either their American or German counterparts in the mid-19th
century, and vastly taller than workers, stood at 174 cm. That is two centimetres shorter than the average
Englishman today, of all classes. 124 This would suggest that even
for the aristocracy, height has increased over the past century to a degree not
easily ascribable to better food. In fact the evidence of every castle and
Tudor cottage doorway suggests that the rise in height has been going on since
the Middle Ages. Even the aristocrats of the 15th and 16th
centuries, stuffing themselves on venison and exercising vigorously, were not
as tall as the men of today, as every suit of armour in museums testifies. The
rise in height may not have been continuous: research suggests there were both
rises and falls in height over the past thousand years. Some researchers think
that a thousand years ago European men were taller than six centuries later –
173 cm declining to 167 cm (though this may have been racial, with the
dominance of Nordic stocks among early medieval rulers, whose skeletons would
also be the ones that have survived.) 125 According to this theory
there was a decline towards a low point in the 17th century, and
then Europeans began to grow again, with another drop in the late 18th and early 19th centuries. None of
these movements in height can be explained by natural selection, and John
Komlos has fairly convincingly linked them with the availability and price of
food. He thinks that population growth, high food prices and the movement to
cities, cutting more people off from fresh farm food (meat and dairy products),
is largely responsible for the late 18th century decline in height.
At the end of the 19th century better food transportation, through
techniques of canning and refrigeration, made better food available to urban
populations, and with rising wages heights began to rise again. 126
The crucial
question is: is the new tallness of Europeans now inherited, and is it genetically encoded? The experts seem to
agree that height is the result of both genetic and environmental factors, but
how they interact remains obscure. Can a genetic factor originate in an
environmental factor, as seems to be the case of the bigger lungs of the Aymara
Indians of Bolivia? The historical evidence of a gradual and cumulative gain in
height favours this Lamarckian notion. But Spetner’s idea, that of a
repeated adaptive change within each life-time, which is not inherited (in
other words, a mere change in phenotype, not genotype), can still not be
excluded. What we know for certain is that natural selection had nothing to do
with this development.
It appears that
the question of the change in height of modern Europeans may well prove to be
one of the most fruitful fields for testing the Lamarckian hypothesis – of the
inheritance of an environmentally-induced characteristic. Several lines of
research suggest themselves. Would it be useful to find out from hospital
records whether European babies are born longer today than in the nineteenth
century? If babies of all classes are now born longer on average (and not
merely heavier, which might reflect the mother’s diet more directly), would
this not be proof that the gain in height over the past 140 years is now
inherited and genetically encoded? Would not this be a crucial experiment (in
Popper’s sense) to test Lamarck’s hypothesis, that environment can cause
inheritable changes? But no doubt objections will be made that greater length
of new-born babies simply reflects the mother’s nutrition, and not any genetic
change. Is it possible to compare the genetic code of 19th century
people (the Dutch, for example) and today’s much taller specimens? This is an
area where further research could bring crucial breakthroughs in understanding
how bodies change. One fact that suggests that tallness is now a genetic
characteristic among the Dutch in particular is that their height is still
increasing today: boys of twenty are taller than men of thirty-five. But is the
environment (food and medical care) still improving? Has there been that much
improvement in Dutch diet since the early 1980’s (a period when European
economies began to go down rather than up)? Surely a boy born in 1970 ate as
well as one born in 1985? A rising number of young Dutchmen are now close to
210 cm or nearly seven feet, a height which is usually thought to involve
health risks rather than benefits. Surely this galloping growth is genetically
driven? But how did these genes get into a population which in the 19th
century was relatively short? Can dormant genes (which have long been
suppressed by an unfavourable environment, inadequate food) be switched on in
response to environmental factors? There are good reasons for expecting that
this Lamarckian idea will one day be confirmed, and that natural selection will
be shown to be only one of several mechanisms of evolution, and almost certainly
not the main one.
16)
THE MOTOR OF EVOLUTION: CATASTROPHE OR OPPORTUNITY?
One of the
fundamental problems of Darwin’s theory is its
origins in Malthus’s vision of catastrophic over-population. Darwin believed that
catastrophic conditions of vicious struggle by persistently over-breeding
species result in the harsh culling of the less adapted, and that the more
fiercely this process occurs the faster the process of evolution. This is now
thought to be a distortion of what happens in nature, where populations tend to
be controlled by internal mechanisms (including widespread infanticide of
surplus offspring) rather than simply by predation or starvation. 127
His bias towards seeing adversity and hardship as the mother of evolution seems
to have been shared by many American academics of the mid-twentieth century – not only because
of their Puritan ideological background, but perhaps because they had childhood
memories of depression and poverty. To them it seems axiomatic that life is
tough and ruthlessly selects the fittest, and it must be this that powers
evolutionary change. But it seems obvious even to a casual observer that
evolution has given rise to the richest diversity of species in benign rather
than harsh conditions. Anyone who wanders into the rain forests of New Zealand can
only be struck by how easy life looks for the myriad bird species. In a climate
almost monotonously temperate, with winters without snow, autumns where the
trees keep their leaves, and summers where the grass stays green, with abundant
flowers, vegetation of cloying lushness, no native mammals and no native
predators, life looks good for the birds. And they have indeed evolved into an
extraordinary range of unique species. Before man got there, they must have
lived a life of ease and plenty, not to say sloth – with the result
that one of their peculiarities is that many of them forgot how to fly. Now no
convincing argument has ever been put forward as to how birds could lose the
power of flight for competitive reasons. There was no advantage they could
achieve by losing it. It didn’t give them any sort of edge in hard times. The idea
that there was a competition for muscle power between legs and wings, and those
that lost wing-power gained running speed, does not hold water. Many New Zealand
birds have never been seen to break into a run; their habitual gait is a
dawdle. They lost the power of flight because they had no predators to flee
from and there was no panic to get to the food. And they must have lost it
collectively, by slow atrophy of the wing muscles. There was no selection,
because there was no fierce competition going on with premature death for the
losers. If there had been, they would have started flying again.
Now it is amusing
to see how disdainfully the atrophying of wings is regarded by the
neo-Darwinists as an almost disgraceful degeneration of a species. There are
disparaging remarks about the relaxation of selective pressure on features
leading to their decline, as if this was a culpable form of slatternly laziness
and letting oneself go. It is like an attractive woman giving up diet and
exercise and becoming an overweight slob in a dressing gown. A decent, self-respecting species would have
kept up the effort and preserved its wings in tip-top shape, ready for instant
flight from predators, just in case one happened to appear after a million
years of tranquillity. These flightless birds have let the team down in a
disgraceful manner. Now this attitude reflects the competitive obsession of the
neo-Darwinists. Anything that happens out of an absence of competitive pressure
is degeneration – it cannot possibly be positive evolution. Like a 19th
century slum-born American capitalist, the only thing they understand or
respect is the selective rigours of competition in harsh conditions. But the
inconvenient fact is that evolutionary diversity seems to flourish most in
benign conditions. Species branch off and enter new evolutionary niches when
niches become available. It is opportunity, not hardship, which is the mother
of evolution. Otherwise you would find more extravagantly diverse life-forms in
Antarctica than in New Zealand,
or in the Australian desert than in the jungles of Queensland. And we know that this is not the
case.
Similarly it is
in time periods of opportunity, not of disaster, that evolution seems to have
gone through sudden spurts of extraordinary advance. It is probable that the
Cambrian period, when there was a sudden explosion of life forms, was one of
benign rather than harsh conditions. There is a new and increasingly respected
theory (put forward by Harvard geologists Paul Hoffman and Daniel Schrag,
working on an idea of Russian Mikhail Budyko) that the earth went through a
snowball stage of total ice cover about six hundred million years ago, followed
by a “global warming” resulting from volcanic activity and the build-up
of carbon dioxide. Its proponents point to fossil evidence of the Cambrian
explosion of new life forms shortly afterwards, as the primitive marine life
suddenly found itself in a new warm water world without any competitors.128
It is the absence of harsh conditions or ruthless competition, the sudden
availability of a multitude of new niches for existence, which leads to massive
evolutionary diversification. Opportunities for new life, not the pressure of
death, is the main motor of evolution. And when one looks at human history, and
the conditions in which societies have become innovative, inventive and diverse
in their activities, one sees a similar pattern.
17)
REQUIEM FOR A DEAD IDEOLOGY
Assuming that one
day, as its fanatical disciples die off, the neo-Darwinist ideology of natural
selection and the survival of the fittest is dropped, and a composite
evolutionary theory, including a large element of Lamarckism, is adopted in its
place, what difference will this make to our world view? For a start the notion
of life as a jungle where only the strong survive will hopefully vanish from
our popular thinking. Ruthless aggression will no longer be seen as the
governing principle of life. The most pernicious popular philosophy ever
devised, which has given rise to ruthless capitalism, ruthless colonialism and
Nazism, will at last be deprived of its supposed scientific justification. The
newspaper pundits will stop rabbiting on about the Darwinian world of struggle
we live in, as if this world-view had all the authority of established science.
They will stop confusing the simple and obvious fact that animals eat one
another with the discredited theory that selective massacre is the motor of
evolution. Lamarckism, by contrast, posits a collective, peaceful process of
evolution, not a competitive and eliminationist one. The entire species (or the
divergent race or variety) changes in direct adaptation to new environmental
conditions or new food-gathering habits. It
does not change through the accidental mutation of a select few
individuals which then take over the species through ruthless competition and
the elimination of all the others. Neo-Lamarckism would emphasize the collective
survival instinct of species, their ability to adapt rapidly to changing
conditions, and their ability to cut back their own procreation in times of
food shortage (as birds do by laying fewer eggs, and plants by dropping fewer
seeds.) It would promote a model of co-operation and collective action among
the human race, rather than an image of perpetual struggle and warfare as the
life-principle. In short, neo-Lamarckism would be a philosophy for an era of
peace and co-operation, just as Darwinism presided over a long era of war and
rivalry.
We have emerged
from a century in which war and conflict on an unprecedented scale have not
only been our lot, but have been glorified as the basic principle of life by a
rogue ideology. This ideology of war and struggle, of the survival of the
fittest, has unconsciously influenced our entire conception of life and of how
society should be organized. It is time to find a new paradigm, a new image of
how life on earth develops. It is insidious and dishonest that evolutionists
are stealthily moving away from Darwin
by endless ad hoc modifications of
his theory which have gutted it of meaning without publicly announcing that he
was wrong and that the popular Darwinian vision of nature is false. They are
leaving the popular paradigm in place while changing all the technical details.
It is time to knock the paradigm over. The pernicious ideology of the survival
of the fittest has done enough damage. It is time to drop it, and think of our
universe as the collective development of all living things, in a balance in
which there is room for all to flourish if they adapt intelligently and
maintain stable populations. The Lamarckian theory of evolution would favour a
co-operative world where we tackle problems collectively that will affect us
all : diseases and epidemics, environmental pollution, the scarcity of
resources, the imbalances of trade, the spread of nuclear weapons, the
suppression of national rights by tyrannical states, the poverty and
overpopulation of certain parts of the world and the demographic suicide of
others, and the need to regulate migrations and stabilize all populations at
replacement levels in order to maintain social and cultural cohesiveness. It
would favour the collective process of democratic debate, leading to action by
elected governments in co-operation with one another, rather than the ruthless
pursuit of profit by gigantic private corporations and their megalomaniac
managers.
Adam Smith’s
superstition, that the hidden hand of the market will guide the egoistic
decisions of individuals towards the outcome that best serves the common good,
is the economic equivalent of Darwin’s superstition that nature guides the
ruthless struggle of each against all towards the survival of the fittest and
the evolutionary changes most favourable to the future of the species. Both
ideas are irrational myths and the Darwinist superstition has become the
pseudo-scientific underpinning of the laissez-faire capitalist one. The belief
that the market, like nature, favours the best and eliminates the worst, lies
at the heart of the capitalist cult of unfettered competition. This belief is
instinctive among capitalists. If Walmart is eliminating its rivals, then
Walmart must be the best. The fittest always survive. The losers are always
wrong. The fact that in macroeconomic terms the success of Walmart is a
disaster because its rock bottom wages depress the purchasing power necessary
to fuel other businesses, that it is in fact a parasitic company, dependent on
the purchasing power provided by more generous employers, is lost in the
contemplation of its isolated success against its rivals. In reality, the
hidden hand of the market has no natural tendency to favour fair, sustainable
competition, or companies that pay decent wages. Instead it favours monopoly,
the elimination of all competition, cheating, ruthless methods, the brutal
exploitation of employees, and gross distortions between supply and demand.
Governments can and must intervene in the market to secure its fairness, prevent
monopolies, impose decent conditions, and promote fair collective
wage-bargaining so that purchasing power will keep pace with rising production.
The misguided laissez-faire policies being followed today are not only allowing
Walmart to create a swathe of working poor across America, but are also
allowing China to pursue a mercantilist policy of exporting but not importing,
producing frantically while keeping wages so low (under a repressive
dictatorship) that its workers cannot consume. China is as parasitic as Walmart,
dependent on the purchasing power of other nations, and contributing
insufficient purchasing power of its own to the general pool because its
repressive system does not let its workers bargain for fair wages. Both are
destabilizing forces, exploiting a prosperity which they are systematically
undermining until they bring about an inevitable crash.
The cult of
globalization that rules today is merely this Darwinistic cult of ruthless
competition writ large and imposed on the entire planet. It means that
multinational companies get around the social progress in wages and working
conditions which Western societies have struggled for a hundred years to
achieve, by shifting their factories all over the globe in search of the lowest
wages and least regulated conditions. This has led to a race to exploit the
poorest workers in the countries that offer them the least protection.
Totalitarian China,
with its official minimum wage at 44 dollars a month, has become the new Mecca
of Western companies – which are transferring their manufacturing operations
there as fast as they can. A totalitarian state which was condemned by American
capitalists as a wicked tyranny when it kept their factories out has now become
flavour of the month since it has let them in to join in the exploitation of
its slave labour. The outlawing of free trade unions, the arrest, imprisonment
and torture of labour leaders – things which were denounced as the unacceptable
face of communism back in the 1960’s and 70’s – have now become the very
attraction of the system, the basis of the success of China’s new “market” economy. The
argument that market freedoms will lead inevitably to political freedoms is the
cynical alibi of hypocritical Western politicians. They know that the last
thing Western businesses in China
want to see is political freedom, and that the only reason they are there is
the absence of freedom. Western businesses have adopted exactly the same
callous “good conscience” as they adopted towards the African slave trade: it
is not our fault if these people are slaves, they would be slaves anyway, we
are merely buying the cheapest labour available at local market rates, and
using it to produce goods at favourable prices for our customers. The very
people who still ritually deplore the African slave trade which was banned two
hundred years ago are engaging in the new slave trade in China without
the slightest moral qualms. Like their 18th century counterparts,
they are simply dealing with the real world as they find it – using the
conditions that exist in other countries (beyond their control) to their own
advantage. The only question is whether a movement of moral awakening as to the
reality of what they are doing will strike in the 21st century as it
did in the late 18th century. But the capitalist class today may be
beyond any moral redemption, as its predecessors in 18th century Britain were
not.
It is beginning
to be understood that this entire cult of the free market shows a profound
ignorance of the basis of Western democratic societies. The new cult of
privatization and liberalization is taking the latest phase in a long history
of Western social evolution and imposing that phase alone on the rest of the
world as though it were the key to our success. It is not. Western societies
are the products of a long, complex history in which political liberty,
democracy, the rule of law, individual enterprise, national pride, a free
press, state interventionism, reforming governments, trade unions, community
values, the ideal of public service, and the Christian ethic of love thy
neighbour have all played a part. The parable of the good Samaritan is more
central to Western culture than free market capitalism. It lies behind all the
social reforms of the past hundred years that distinguish our societies from
the most brutal dictatorships. Above all it lies behind the welfare states
created after the Second World War by interventionist governments in the name
of social solidarity. And without the safety net of solidarity put in place by
social democracies animated by a Christian, humanist ethical code, the code of
“love thy neighbour”, the free market simply means a ruthless, exploitative,
dog-eat-dog society, where inequalities increase until they fuel violence,
revolt, and brutal repression. The ultra-free market is not the blueprint for
the kind of humane society the West has arrived at, and it is only gross
ignorance of our own history that is allowing a generation of capitalist
technocrats to pretend that it is. This gross distortion of our understanding
of reality is part of the pernicious influence of the ruthless, competitive
Darwinist ideology.
But beyond its
role in underpinning extremist free market economic policies, Darwinism has had
an even more destructive effect on our moral behaviour. Darwinist thinking, in
its popular form of the survival of the fittest and the weak to the wall, is
responsible for a great proportion of the evil, violence, greed, dishonesty and
unscrupulous-ness of the present age. Every CEO of every major company sees the
world as a jungle of ruthless competition, in which the fittest survive. The
surest methods of survival are the most unscrupulous. At its crudest, exploit workers, squeeze suppliers, cheat
customers, lie to investors, sabotage rivals, and trash the environment. The
corporate criminals of Enron, enriching themselves with sums beyond the
capacity of any mortal to spend while despoiling their own employees of their
hard-earned pensions, were typical products of Darwinism. Darwinism is the
glorification of selfishness and the justification of riding roughshod over
others. It flies in the face of every ethical code man has devised over the
ages. The belief that a ruthless, selfish struggle of each against all is the
deepest reality of life, the underlying principle of nature and the motor force
of evolution, has had a profoundly corrupting and brutalizing effect on human
behaviour. The Darwinian reflection that after all life is a jungle where the
weak go to the wall is the thought that passes through every mind about to
commit an act of despicable selfishness, treachery, cruelty, or oppression. The
truth is that life has no principle except what we humans decide to give
it. And what we can discern from the
pattern of nature gives us at least as many reasons for believing in collective
adaptation and harmonious co-existence as in the contrary principle of violent
competition to conquer and eliminate all others. Paley’s vision of
nature as a cozy scene of harmony was certainly false; but Darwin’s vision of a ruthless
eliminationist struggle of each against all is equally false and far more
damaging. The theory that the brutal elimination of “the unfit” is the motor
force of all “adaptive improvement” of species is
now known to be wrong and scientists should stop pretending to believe in it.
They have in fact long since stripped the notion of “fitness” of any content
except survival itself (“being good at surviving”.) Having
discreetly and surreptitiously killed Darwinism off they should now have the
decency to announce the death and bury the corpse, whose stink is a moral
poison that continues to pollute the world.
CHAPTER SIX: MARXISM
1) REVOLUTION AS A VERSION
OF APOCALYPSE
In Darwin’s writings
aggression, violence and elimination of the weak are central to his vision of
how nature works, but only implicit in his vision of how men should act. In the
works of Karl Marx violence is explicit : it is the recommended way of bringing
about political and social change. His contribution to the violence and
aggression of the 20th century is even greater and more direct than Darwin’s. Of the tens of
millions of human beings murdered world-wide in the century that has just ended
by state persecution, extermination, and starvation in labour camps, three
quarters were killed in the name of Karl Marx. The mass purges and slow extermination in prison
camps carried out by Stalin, Mao and Pol Pot, added to the revolutionary civil
wars and the famines deliberately organized by Stalin and Mao during the forced
collectivization of farms, killed many times more people than Nazism did, and
more than both Nazism and all the wars of the 20th century put
together. Jung Chang, author of the acclaimed historical novel Wild Swans, was given unprecedented access
to Chinese archives in order to write her biography of the Great Helmsman, Mao, the Unknown Story (jointly with her
husband, Jon Halliday, a specialist historian of the USSR.) After long research
she put the number of Chinese victims of communism at over seventy million.
Historian Norman Davies puts the victims of Soviet Communism at fifty-four
million, which would give a total figure of a over hundred and twenty million
deaths due to communism over the last century. A lifelong specialist in the field
of genocide and what he terms “democide”, Political Science professor R.J.
Rummel of Hawaii University puts the total number of
victims of communism at 148 million (and those of Nazism at twenty million.)1
Even if the caution of future historians eventually reduces these numbers
considerably, the slate with Karl Marx’s name on it is still likely
to be the heaviest in human history.
To these deaths
may be added all the miseries of seventy years of communist tyranny and
mismanagement, the extraordinary waste of wealth and energy in the Cold War,
and the disastrous revolutionary regimes and rebel movements that mired much of
Africa, Asia and South America in senseless
conflict and economic failure. The exacerbation of labour conflicts in all
industrial nations in the twentieth century owes much to the work of Marx’s acolytes,
tenacious, obsessive and dedicated to their single-minded goal of the
destruction of capitalist society. Whether they contributed anything to the
improvement of the conditions of the working class anywhere is doubtful. Almost
all successful reform was achieved by the rival democratic socialist traditions
which Marx spent his life denouncing and which his followers did everything to
sabotage. His ideas may sometimes have inspired militants, but the ruthless
extremism of communism frightened and galvanized opposition from all other
sectors of society and probably delayed reforms rather than speeding them up.
The extraordinary transformation that has come about in the conditions of
workers in Western countries over the past hundred years has occurred in all
cases through that step-by-step, democratic reformism that Marx so detested.
Today his theories have been discredited and his reputation is in tatters in
nearly all the lands where his ideas prevailed. But he is still widely quoted
in the West for his waspish comments on contemporary events, and his insights
into certain aspects of capitalism. His most lasting legacy, apart from the
ruin of large parts of the world, is probably the effect he has had on the
pattern of thinking of Western intellectuals. The cult of political hatred, the
paranoid determination to see history in terms of deliberate, organized
oppression by dominant groups rather than in terms of ignorance, greed,
selfishness, bigotry and superstition, left its mark on the way late 20th
century Western intellectuals were to deal with such diverse issues as race,
colonialism, women’s rights and even gay rights. Along with this
paranoid, conspiracy-theory world-view went a special morality which saw truth
as expendable in the great cause of social progress. Marx’s own
distortions, lies, grotesque exaggerations and falsification of evidence became
a kind of cancer which infected the methods of all the leftist intellectual
movements that he inspired. While Marxism has collapsed or been discredited as
an economic system, it remains entrenched in Western universities as a way of
seeing the world and interpreting history. Its very tenacity in the face of
history’s devastating judgement upon it demonstrates the
extraordinary capacity for self-deception and bad faith which is the most
striking characteristic of the minds of its disciples.
The roots of Marx’s violent
revolutionary thinking in a biblical vision of apocalypse have been well demonstrated
by recent critics. Marx was raised a devout Protestant Christian, and was
confirmed at fifteen. A drama he wrote at eighteen, “Oulanem”, is about
Satanism, and religious imagery and references to the devil fill his adolescent
poems. The vision of the destruction of the capitalist Babylon came to him early. As a youth he was
fond of quoting Goethe’s Mephistopheles: “Everything that
is must be destroyed”.2 Much later came the construction of a
theory and practice to bring this cataclysm about. The key to the destruction
of the society he hated lay in the class conflict he saw beginning to flare up
in industrial disputes and in such mass movements as Chartism. The vision of
history as a succession of class conflicts leading to the greatest class conflict
of all, the one that would (after a careful fanning of the flames by the
revolutionary vanguard) lead on to the final battle of history (Armageddon) and
the overthrow of the detested capitalist system – this vision can
fairly be called a cult of conflict and apocalypse. The theoretical
underpinning of this view he found in the Hegelian dialectic of thesis,
antithesis and synthesis. Conflict and antagonism are the principle of life
itself. But its emotional drive comes not from Hegel’s ponderous and
obscure ruminations but from the apocalyptic tradition. It is as a prophet,
predicting the overthrow of tyranny and the revenge of the oppressed, not as a
philosopher, that Marx has influenced the course of history.
One of Marx’s most
interesting early works is an essay on “the Jewish Question”, or Jewish
emancipation in Germany.
He is reviewing a book on the subject by a fellow-radical, Bruno Bauer. Bauer
argues that the Jews can only be emancipated (that is, obtain political rights)
when they as well as the Germans are emancipated from the delusion of religion
itself, and embrace a scientific worldview. Marx, on the other hand, sees
Judaism not as a religion but as something else.
Let us look for the secret
of the Jew not in his religion, but rather for the secret of the religion in
the actual Jew.
What is the secular basis of
Judaism? Practical need, self-interest.
What is the worldly cult of
the Jew? Huckstering. What is his
worldly god?
Money.
Very well! Emancipation from
huckstering and money and thus from practical and real Judaism would be the
self-emancipation of our era.
Thus we perceive in Judaism
a general and contemporary anti-social
element….
The emancipation of the
Jews, in the final analysis, is the emancipation of mankind from Judaism. 3
He spends the rest of the
essay elaborating on this idea, which equates Judaism with the money-worship of
capitalism. According to this idea
Judaism is already in control of society: “The Jews have emancipated themselves
in so far as the Christians have become Jews.” He concludes four pages later by
repeating the earlier formula: “The social emancipation of the Jew is the
emancipation of society from Judaism.” 4
It is clear that
Marx (the grandson of rabbis on both sides of the family, but who was baptized
a Protestant, his father having converted to evade a Prussian law banning
Jewish lawyers) sees the stereotype of the Jewish usurer as an image of all of
capitalist society. He quotes from the English commentator Hamilton
on the wholly materialistic, money-making interests of the inhabitants of New
England, for whom even religion is a business, and sees it as proof of “the practical
domination of Judaism over the Christian world in North
America.”5 But this use of “Judaism” as a sort of
trope for materialism, money-obsession and capitalism in general – ignoring
completely the actual doctrines and practices of the Jewish religion – has a sinister
resemblance to the paranoid theories of Hitler. One may see Marx as starting
from an anti-Semitic hatred of Jewish capitalists and then widening it to the
entire bourgeois class. Hitler, on the other hand, retained a narrowly racist
focus on Jews, but interpreted their pernicious influence as not merely their
obsession with money but their attempt to dominate the nation and pervert it
from its true nature by a sort of racial contamination. The two men’s theories are in
fact strikingly similar, in that both saw the redemption of mankind through the
elimination of a class of vicious exploiters. Once free the world of
Jews/capitalists and the natural goodness of man will somehow assert itself.
Vices and injustices of all kinds will magically disappear. The existence of an
evil group of enemies of society becomes for both of them a total explanation
of human evil, in an almost magical, metaphysical sense. The elimination of
that group becomes the solution to all humanity’s problems.
Given this
curious excursion into religious thinking early in Marx’s career, and
his identification of Judaism and
capitalism, it is perhaps worth looking more closely at the religious roots of
his philosophy – which he always pretended, of course, was “scientific”.
The cult of
conflict central to Marxism was not a new idea. Hegel claimed to derive his
dialectic from the Greek philosopher Heracleitus, who announced, with Greek
succinct- ness, that war is the father of all things. The 3rd
century Persian creed of Manichaeism (to which St Augustine subscribed in his youth) posited
a perpetual war between light and dark, good and evil. But it is in
Christianity and the violent struggle to reform it that we must look for the
roots of European revolutionary thinking in general. In the Middle Ages the
Church played a far greater role in the lives of people than the State.
Revolution in the Church preceded revolution in the State and laid down the
mental paths it would follow. Paradoxically the Reformation of the Church was
the origin of both capitalist and revolutionary thinking.
The Protestant
Reformation, which drove people back to reading the bible for themselves
instead of accepting the Church’s interpretation of it, developed two distinct
currents of thought – one based largely on the Jewish Old Testament and
the other on the Book of Revelations. The Old Testament God was one who was in
active control of the world, who intervened in men's lives, who looked after
his own people, who gave instructions to his chosen ones, struck down his
enemies and punished those who were unfaithful to him. History, however bloody
and tumultuous, was basically an unfolding of God's plan for his chosen people,
and God constantly intervened in the process to put things right, sometimes in
answer to prayer, sometimes by striking down the wicked. This view of the world
leads to a certain complacent optimism: God in the end rewards virtue in this
life and punishes vice. This means that disaster comes to be seen as a
visitation upon our sins, while success and wealth are a mark of God's favour.
It is only a step from here to equating wealth and success with virtue, and
poverty and failure with vice. This becomes the moral underpinning of
Protestant capitalism, as it was, to some extent, of Jewish capitalism. God
looks after his own. Success is God’s blessing upon his
favourites. “We are blessed” is a subtle way of suggesting that we deserve it,
unless God has got things badly wrong. “God will provide” is the idea
embodied in the term Providence,
the favourite English word for the deity in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries.
But there was also a contrary current of thought in
Protestantism. The years of persecution of Christians under the Roman empire
had produced the Book of Revelations, which became a cult book for certain
Puritan sects in the seventeenth century, which were also persecuted. This book
saw the world as under the control of an evil empire, Babylon, a corrupt tyranny ruled in its final
days by the Antichrist. This tyranny, which would reach a paroxysm of violence
and evil, would at last be overthrown and cast down by the forces of good in a
tremendous final battle, Armageddon. After that, the thousand-year reign of the
Just over the earth would begin. Certain extremist Puritans of the English
Revolution of the 1640’s began to see this as a process happening within
history and even within their own time. Armageddon was a revolution, and they
themselves, the revolutionaries, were the Just, the elect of God, the “Saints” who would rule
for a thousand years. In the English Revolution we see millennial religious
vision becoming revolutionary ideology. It is the nexus of all the political
thought of modern times.
To get some flavour of this junction of Revolutionary
ideology and radical Protestantism, one
should turn to the pages of Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in France. Here Burke attacks the sermon
preached by the Non-conformist (or in our terms, radical, fundamentalist)
minister Dr Richard Price, extolling the French revolution as the fulfilment of
biblical prophecies. Burke quotes Dr Price:
“What an eventful
period this is! I am thankful that I have lived to see it; I could almost say,
Lord now lettest thou thy servant depart in peace, for mine eyes have seen thy
salvation…….. I have lived to see thirty millions of people,
indignant and resolute, spurning at slavery, and demanding liberty with an
irresistible voice; their king led in triumph and an arbitrary monarch
surrendering himself to his subjects.” 6
Burke points out that this
same scriptural text was used in a public prayer in Whitehall by the Reverend Hugh Peters, after
leading King Charles in triumph to his trial in the English Revolution of a
century and a half before. Clearly the overthrowers of Kings saw themselves as
agents of a millennial transformation of the human condition. Their direct
inspiration, at least in England,
was the bible – the jeremiads against the mighty in the books of
the Old Testament prophets and above all the forecast overthrow of the
Anti-Christ in the Book of Revelations.
We have therefore two quite contradictory currents in
Protestantism, two distinct ways in which religious thinking shades into
political ideology – in short, two opposing visions of the world. In one
view, based largely on the old Testament, the world is a more or less benign
place under the providential control of God. In the other view, based mostly on
Revelations, it is a Babylonian tyranny ruled by the Beast, the servant of
Satan. In one view the world is a fair playing-field where virtue is rewarded
and vice punished. In the other, it is a testing-ground where the faithful are
persecuted by triumphant evil. In one, success and wealth reflect God’s favour. In the
other, wealth is the sign of corruption, the mark of the Beast. In short, one
is a conception of the world and the prevailing order of things as basically
good; and the other a view of things as fundamentally evil, and requiring a
radical redemption by a divine intervention of a catastrophic sort. This is the
opposition between, on the one hand, the complacent view of society developed
by the established Church and the ruling class in the eighteenth century (the
divinely ordained harmony of the universe) and, on the other hand, the
subversive view of the Puritan sects, which continued in a direct line from the
revolutionaries of the English Civil War to the enthusiastic fans of the French
Revolution. This is the dichotomy of world-views which will underlie the
conflict between the established order and revolutionary socialism in the
nineteenth century.
But in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries the
millennial idea (Armageddon, followed by the thousand year reign of the Just),
which had so agitated minds in the English Revolution, entered Western thinking
under another, more subtle disguise: the idea of progress. Until the
mid-seventeenth century the prevailing view of history was one of decline from
a golden age. Evidence of decay was seen everywhere, and man was thought to be
in his dotage, sinking gradually into complete degeneracy. For some reason the
millennial hysteria of the English Civil War and the final return of the
established order in the Restoration unleashed a curious wave of optimism about
man’s future. The ideas which Francis Bacon had put forward fifty years
earlier about reforming the methods of learning to make possible an endless
advancement in knowledge suddenly came into their own. This was the period of
the setting up of scientific societies, of Newton’s discovery of the laws of
physics and Locke’s pioneering empirical philosophy, the basis of the
scientific world view. Suddenly man began to have a future, and human progress
became the prevailing idea. Swift even recorded the extraordinary debate which
took place over whether the ancient or the modern authors were better – “the Battle of the Books”. It was the
first time modern European man had dared to elevate himself above his classical
masters, and to imagine that the future might excel the past. But this new
progressive view of history soon split into two distinct tendencies. There were
the more conservative voices who believed that man’s innate corruption,
original sin, would prevent him from ever attaining any paradise on earth.
There were others, reinforced by the influence of the French Enlightenment and
its radical challenge to the dogmas of Christianity, who believed that original
sin was an illusion. Man was innately good, and if he acted badly it was
because society (education, religion, traditional morality, class rule, the
economic system) had corrupted and deformed his nature. Man is infinitely
perfectible: all we need to do is change the conditions in which he lives. But
this view again split into two currents. There were those who thought that this
progress and perfection of man was something almost inevitable, which would be
achieved gradually as ignorance was abolished and man became more enlightened.
There were others who thought the system more profoundly corrupt and rotten
than that. Only a catastrophic change could release man and his natural
goodness from slavery and the distortion of his nature. In short, the
progressives split between the gradualists and the revolutionaries. This was
the mental landscape in which the French revolution played out its bloody
dramas across Europe. It was a movement of
rationalism (inspired by the Enlightenment) but animated by the fanaticism of a
sort of secular faith – a millennialist craving to start human history
again from zero and redesign the world (a throwback to the English Puritan
visionaries who thought their apocalyptic revolution meant the end of history – though France
having crushed bible-reading Protestantism, its revolutionary imagery was
classical rather than biblical.) The French revolutionaries literally put the
calendar back to year one as if the entire past could be abolished. And after
it was all over, betrayed, defeated and discredited, this was the mental rubble
from which nineteenth century radical thinkers like Marx began to pick up the
pieces. Needless to say, Marx was heir both to the revolutionary millennial
tradition of violent Apocalypse, the restarting of history, and also to the
naive Enlightenment creed of the perfectibility of man, once the evil
conditions of his existence were abolished.
The question then became to define the evil conditions of
man’s existence. What was the nature and origin of the evil system he lived
under, and how could change be expected to come about? Rousseau had already
pointed to man’s acquisitive urge as the basic culprit. And to
anyone living through the early days of the industrial revolution with its
enslavement of human beings to the factory system, the nature of the evil
seemed clear – capitalism itself. But if man was naturally good
then where did the evil impulse to create and sustain this evil system come
from? The answer in a post-Enlightenment age could no longer be found in
Satan – evil had
to come from man himself. But how can evil be in man’s own nature and
still permit hopes of human perfectibility? The neat answer to this problem was
found in the dialectic which Marx took from Hegel. Reality itself is built on
antagonisms and contradictions which sharpen until a violent resolution is
found. Evil is not inherent in man, but in an external, material condition of
his existence: the relationship of the class he belongs to with the means of
production. The class that owns and controls the means of production is evil by
virtue of this relationship. Those who are exploited by them are virtuous by
this same class relationship. Marx managed in fact to divide mankind into good
and evil categories, by virtue of the relation of these groups with the means
of production. The proletarian majority are good, innocent, perfectible. But
the minority who have monopolized the means of production are incurably
vicious; they have conspired to enslave the rest for their own profit. The
progress of mankind must therefore consist in the acting out of the inherent
antagonism between the two classes, a long struggle by the proletariat to
overthrow and exterminate the vicious ruling group. Once this vicious part of
mankind has been eliminated by a short period of dictatorship, evil will
disappear, since its cause, a particular relationship with the means of
production, will have gone. Man’s innocent nature will thus flourish uncorrupted by
class relations. The state itself, with its laws and restraints, will become
unnecessary and will “wither away”, and the reign of the Just
on earth will begin.
It is this
curiously naive dogma of man’s natural goodness, inherited from Rousseau, which allows Marx to be so utterly
indifferent to the political structure of the future state and to ignore the
need for democratic, constitutional checks and balances to prevent the abuse of
power. This had been the obsession, by contrast, of the pessimistic
eighteenth-century American rebels. They were heirs to an earlier Puritan tradition
where original sin loomed large, and where no man could be trusted with
unlimited power. It is because he does not believe in original sin, that man is
corrupt and prone to abuse power, that Marx can blithely propose the
dictatorship of the proletariat, or rather of a group of intellectuals like
himself acting in their name – what the
anarchist Bakunin called scornfully “a government of scholars
(quelle rêverie!)”, adding with prescience that they “will be the most
oppressive, most hated and most despicable in the world”.7
Marx could only answer this with his lame insistence that this class
dictatorship of the workers would only last until the economic basis of class
society had been destroyed, after which the state would wither away. In other
words the justification for dictatorship is that it will be short. Now only the
most gullible believer in the moral innocence and perfectibility of man could
possibly imagine that a complex human society could do without the state in any
form – that we will one day not need policemen, courts, judges, parliaments,
or laws. That one should pass rapidly from a situation needing a ruthless
dictatorship for the coercion of the wicked bourgeoisie to a condition where no
state will be needed at all is even more improbable. How is this magical
transformation to operate? How are these recalcitrant bourgeois scoundrels to
be converted to such incorruptible goodness that no laws or government will be
needed any longer? The clear implication is that they will simply be exterminated,
that their physical liquidation will solve all problems. It is this combination
of fantastically naive optimism about human nature with a colossal murderous
ruthlessness that is most disturbing in Marx. It becomes the defining
characteristic of most of those who followed his philosophy.
This combination
of naivety and ruthlessness informs the whole Marxist movement throughout its
history. It seems perpetually surprised by the “betrayals” of this or that
Marxist dictator, as if absolute power does not inherently corrupt. When a
Marxist ruler is condemned (as Stalin
was by Trotsky and his followers) reasons must be found explaining where the
traitor went astray in his theories. Only a doctrinal heresy could possibly
explain the murderous tendencies of a Marxist ruler. The idea that abuse of
power is inherent in man is something no Marxist could ever admit, because then
he would be forced to concede the vital importance of democratic accountability
and the rule of law, and the utter evil of dictatorship. Basically, as long as
a Marxist government is only killing members of the bourgeoisie it is not doing
any wrong in the eyes of its followers. Right and wrong are defined in terms of
the class of the victim, not some universal standard of human rights applicable
to all. Extermination is inherently part of the Marxist programme, because this
extermination is removing the source of evil, the corrupt part of the human
race, so as to leave it purified and eternally innocent from then on. In this
Rousseauist vision of natural human goodness lies the blueprint for mass
murder. The naivety is what gives birth to the ruthlessness.
2) MARX AND FACTORY REFORM
Marx’s ignorance of
human nature was only exceeded by his ignorance of the working class. The idle
son of a prosperous lawyer, Marx never held a job (apart from some short-lived
editorial posts on radical newspapers in Paris
and Cologne
during his twenties), but cadged off family and friends all his life. He spent
his days in stifling, inbred communities of exiled, mostly German-speaking
revolutionaries like himself, with minimal contact with local working people.
As Paul Johnson points out, Marx’s indifference to finding
out about the real conditions of the workers is astonishing. As far as is
known, Marx never set foot in a factory, mine or mill in his life. He refused
invitations to visit the factories of his friend Engels, and showing no
curiosity about the business of his uncle, the Dutch capitalist Philips, who
started the manufacturing empire. When he finally met working class socialists
after the founding of the Communist League and the International, he despised
them at once for their caution and reformist tendencies and systematically
excluded them from any positions of influence (something Lenin was to repeat in
Russia.)
Their knowledge of actual factory conditions is something he had no respect for
or interest in. As Karl Jaspers argues, Marx’s so-called “scientific” approach is not
that of investigation, since he discards all facts that do not suit his theory,
but vindication; and “it is the vindication of something proclaimed as the
perfect truth with the conviction not of the scientist but of the believer.” 8 He is not interested in finding out about working class conditions
or how to improve them; he is interested in demonstrating that here lies the
explosive material that will lead to that violent mass upheaval which will
destroy the society he detests. And anyone who questions that axiom is reviled
as a heretic with a hatred and violence of quite astonishing intensity.
The source of Marx’s knowledge of factory
conditions was exclusively the bookworm
study of factory inspectors’ reports, parliamentary
speeches, newspaper articles and statistics in the reading room of the British Museum. On the basis of this theoretical
study, Marx thought he could demonstrate that capitalism is inevitably driven
by the almost mathematical laws of his bizarre theory of value to render labour
conditions worse and worse until workers are so desperate they will rise up in
violent mass revolt. Workers’ representatives themselves, engaged in a daily
struggle to bring about step-by-step reform and witnesses to the radical
improvements made in their lifetime, were highly sceptical of this theory. When
Marx attacked the German workers’ leader William Weitling for
his lack of “scientific doctrine”, the latter
retorted by dismissing him as a man who dreamed up his ideas in a study and
knew nothing of working-class life. Marx was speechless with rage. 9
But the extraordinary thing is that Marx’s own description in Capital of the history of factory
conditions does not bear out his own theory. In both the chapters on “The Working Day” and on “Machinery and
Modern Industry”, what is demonstrated by the facts he cites is
exactly the opposite of his own beliefs. It is an extraordinary exercise in
intellectual blindness which it is worth examining.
Marx relies
almost entirely for his account of working conditions in “The Working Day” on damning
reports by English factory inspectors and indignant speeches in the House of
Commons during debates over bills to reduce working hours. This reduction (to
ten hours a day) was in fact achieved in the successive Factory Acts beginning
in the late 1840’s. The story Marx tells in this chapter is that of a
dramatic struggle by certain elected politicians and conscientious bureaucrats
to reform a factory system they considered morally unacceptable, and their
extraordinary success in doing so in the teeth of factory-owner opposition. In
other words the spectacle Marx is describing is of the brilliant success of
reformist strategies in changing the conditions of workers. Yet he is utterly
incapable of drawing the logical conclusion from his own evidence – that reform does work, that
parliamentary government (even with a limited franchise) can cure these evils.
His very own testimony would seem to demonstrate that the idea of pushing
worker discontents to the point of violent revolution is unnecessary, absurd,
and therefore evil.
Marx’s heroes in the
chapter “The Working Day” are the English Factory
Inspectors. Far from portraying them as engaged in ineffectual tokenism, Marx
sees their struggle to get the factory laws changed and enforced as vitally
important and little less than heroic. He hails these laws as milestones in the
improvement of the lives of the working class. Here is how he speaks of the
laws they managed to pass to regulate with great precision the hours of
employment, initially of women and children, and then of men:
It has been seen
that these minutiae, which with military uniformity, regulate by stroke of the
clock the times, limits, pauses of the work, were not at all the products of
Parliamentary fancy. They developed gradually out of circumstances as natural
laws of the modern mode of production. Their formulation, official recognition,
and proclamation by the State were the result of a long struggle of classes. 10
Coming from Marx this is
praise. He emphasizes the importance of such details as the length of the
workers’ lunch-breaks, and praises the laws that imposed
these rules on factory owners who would have liked to drive their workers till
they dropped. He recognizes how vital these laws were by describing the
struggle of the factory owners to stop their enactment: “Capital now
entered upon a preliminary campaign in order to hinder the Act from coming into
full force on May 1st 1848…..” 11 He describes how the factory
owners pressured their workers into signing petitions against the Factory Act,
but how the Factory Inspectors interviewed the workers personally, discovered
they were really in favour of it, and overrode the factory owners’ objections. “The preliminary
campaign of capital thus came to grief and the Ten Hours Act came into force
May 1st 1848….” 12
The factory owners
then tried to get around the limited hours by eliminating the lunch break. They
tried to make workers eat their meal before starting work in the morning, and
then to work ten hours straight. Again the Factory Inspectors objected and the
crown lawyers “decided that the prescribed mealtimes must be in the
interval during the working hours and it will not be lawful to work for ten
hours continuously, from 9 a.m. to 7 p.m., without any interval.” In short, the
courts backed the workers. When further subterfuges were tried by the factory
owners, the Inspectors took them to court again. When the Home Secretary tried
to limit the cases they brought against factory owners Marx describes how “the English
Factory Inspectors …. declared that the Home Secretary had no power
dictatorially to suspend the law, and continued their legal proceedings against
the pro-slavery rebellion.” 13
After showing the
heroic legal campaign of the inspectors, Marx then describes the problems they
were up against when the courts were sometimes presided over by part-time
justices who were themselves cotton manufacturers. The Factory Inspectors
vigorously protested against this built-in bias of the courts.
“These judicial
farces,” exclaims Inspector Howell, “urgently call for
a remedy – either that the law should be so altered as to be
made to conform to these decisions, or that it should be administered by a less
fallible tribunal, whose decisions should conform to the law….when these cases
are brought forward. I long for a stipendiary magistrate.” 14
Marx here endorses, utterly
without irony, the view that one of the remedies of the great wrongs of the
working class would be a “stipendiary magistrate” (that is, a paid
professional judge, not an unpaid part-timer drawn from the class of factory
owners.) What informs the whole discussion is Marx’s huge respect
for the judicial struggle of the Factory Inspectors, his sense of the
importance and effectiveness of what they were doing and their admirable
motives. And here are the results of their campaign to limit working hours, as
he sees them:
However the
principle had triumphed with its victory in those great branches of industry
which form the most characteristic creation of the modern mode of production.
Their wonderful development from 1853 to 1860, hand in hand with the physical
and moral regeneration of the factory workers, struck the most purblind. The
masters from whom the legal limitation and regulation had been wrung step by
step after a civil war of half a century themselves referred ostentatiously to
the contrast with the branches of exploitation still “free”….. It will be
easily understood that after the factory magnates had resigned themselves and
become reconciled to the inevitable, the power of resistance of capital gradually
weakened, whilst at same time the power of attack of the working class grew
with the number of its allies in the classes of society not immediately
interested in the question. Hence the comparatively rapid advance since 1860. 15
One puts down this chapter
of Capital with a sense of
consternation. Why on earth did this man, who analysed so admiringly the
struggle for legal reform of the factory system, and judged it so effective for
“the physical and moral regeneration of the factory workers”, take a totally
anti-reformist, anti-democratic stance and insist on violent revolution and
dictatorship as the only possible solution? Why, if one could pass effective
legislation and force the factory magnates to “resign themselves
and become reconciled to the inevitable”, not continue on that
course?
Having
acknowledged the genuine improvement in working conditions brought about by the
Ten-Hour Act (“the physical and moral regeneration of the factory
workers” which even the “masters” saw as positive), how can he,
eight years later in his Critique of the
Gotha Programme, write the following:
The whole
capitalist system of production turns on increasing this gratis labour by
extending the working day or by developing productivity, that is, increasing
the intensity of labour power, etc; that consequently the system of wage labour
is a system of slavery, and indeed of a slavery which becomes more severe in
proportion as the social productive forces of labour develop, whether the
worker receives better or worse payment. 16
How can he write this, when
he has himself seen the power of parliamentary legislation to curb the
exploitation of workers and to improve their conditions, and stressed the
enormous importance to the health of the workers of limiting working hours?
Even in Capital, where he broaches
the question of the intensification and speeding up of work rhythms to
compensate the shortening of hours, he is quoting members of parliament who are
denouncing this abuse and introducing measures to stop it. The whole chapter “Machinery and
Modern Industry” bears witness to the new struggle of the reformers
to stop the factory owners getting around the limitations on hours by
increasing the rhythm of work. It also foresees the real prospect of expanding production without worsening
conditions by increasing the efficiency of machines. How can Marx continue with
his absurd axiomatic belief that technical progress under capitalism can only
enslave the worker further, and that reformist legislation is futile, when he
has seen the opposite with his own eyes?
One senses a
total mismatch between Marx the journalist, narrating with excitement and
admiration the tenacious struggle by determined inspectors to reform factory
conditions, and Marx the dogmatic theorist, denying it could ever work. His
theoretical side seems to draw on the frustrated, embittered personality that
could only find emotional fulfilment in the vision of a social cataclysm.
Instead of advocating reformism as the way forward, and recognizing that it was
in fact accelerating tremendously towards the end of his life with the
extension of the vote to the working class and the growth in trade union power
(with demands already for an eight-hour day), he stubbornly clung to the notion
that all this was merely a preparation for some ultimate violent revolution
(increasing the “power of attack of the working class”.) One cannot
help seeing in Marx two people: a generous-hearted journalist of great ability
in describing and commenting on social ills, wedded to a revolutionary theorist
of psychotic, megalomaniac personality, obsessed with violent conflict,
catastrophe and a kind of cosmic revenge.
3) THE FAILED REVOLUTIONARY
BLUEPRINT
It is a paradox
that Marx’s allegedly scientific theories inspired so many revolutionaries, and
yet not one revolution ever followed the pattern he predicted. All so-called
Marxist revolutions occurred in under-developed countries (which he strictly
ruled out as impossible), and were carried out with the help of movements of
peasants or disaffected soldiers, not industrial workers. The pauperization of
industrial workers which he foresaw under advanced capitalism has never
happened (except for short periods of recession or depression where millions
were thrown out of work, pauperized not by the system but by its temporary
collapse) and has never led to the revolutions he predicted. (What has happened
more often is the pauperization of the middle class, and their recourse to a
middle class version of Marxism, fascism.) It is rather war and foreign
invasion destabilizing defeated governments and disrupting food supplies that
led to the conditions of mass insurrection exploited by revolutionary leaders.
All Marxist revolutions have been opportunistic coups, or resulted from peasant
guerrilla wars. Not one has followed from the ineluctable economic laws Marx
spent his life erecting into a system. The essential points in common between
his theories and the practice of his successful disciples reside in the
building of an authoritarian party, the utterly ruthless conduct of this party
towards the people it allegedly serves, the absolute, brutal dictatorship it
establishes once it has seized power, and the state control of the entire
economy down to the last farm, shop and taxi. All his elaborate theories of
capital accumulation, surplus value and the rest have utterly failed as ways of
predicting what will happen in capitalist societies. But these predictions of
the inevitable collapse of capitalism through its own contradictions, however discredited,
have played a huge emotional role in the world-wide faith he inspired. The very
obscurity of his theories only added to their power as magical, esoteric
doctrines. Like any other prophet predicting apocalypse, he gave his followers
the conviction that the future was theirs, that salvation lay ahead, if only
they continued the struggle to the end. For people suffering appalling poverty
in the slums of underdeveloped countries, it is a spiritual need to believe in
the inevitability of the fall of the system of oppression. That is why Marxism’s appeal has been
so similar to that of a religion. Prophecies of an imminent apocalypse that
will relieve their suffering and bring down their tormentors are all that the
desperate have to keep them going. Their fantasies of revenge give them an
illusion of future power in the very depths of their despair and helplessness.
It is difficult
to avoid the conclusion that for Marx too his entire intellectual system is an
enormous fantasy of revenge on a world which he not only found terribly unjust
but in which he himself failed spectacularly. He never worked a day in his life
(perhaps allergic to the notion of wage-slavery) but lived by scrounging from
his wife (till her money was spent), from his parents (till they gave up on
him), from rich relatives like the Dutch industrialist Philips (founder of the
multinational electronics company), and finally from his factory-owner friend,
Engels. Yet even sponging on Engels to the point of taking half his total
income, he never managed to escape poverty and squalor, because he was hopeless
with money. It was this permanent failure that perhaps gave him the need to
invent some system whereby he would become unimaginably powerful. Comparisons
with that other desperate failure and prophet, the young Hitler, may not be
entirely fair (if we credit Marx with real feeling for the oppressed) but they
are interesting. Pathological hatred animates the work of each, and each
attempts to give this hatred a vast, apocalyptic, world-historical perspective.
They both start from a vicious anti-Semitism, which Marx gradually broadens
into a hatred for the capitalist class as a whole, while Hitler narrows
socialism back down into its anti-Semitic origins. (Since one was of Jewish
descent and the other suspected he might be, since his grandmother became
pregnant while a servant in a Jewish household, there may be a twisted element
of self-hatred in the anti-Semitism of both.) 17 It is significant
that while the young Marx seems to have fallen into the hands of Jewish
money-lenders because of his ineptness with money, the young Hitler was more
obsessed in Vienna with the part played by Jewish pimps in running prostitutes,
and their sexual contamination of “pure” German girls
(that is, naive, impoverished small town girls, drawn to the big city and
ending up in the gutter, just like himself, after his rejection from art
school.) There is a strong hint of sexual jealousy in Hitler’s writing on this
subject, as well as the shocked tones of a provincial boy suddenly exposed to
city vices. He sees the greasy dark Jewish pimp exploiting (and sexually using)
the hapless blond girl as an obscene racial oppression of a higher by a lower
type. The Jew-as-usurer obsessions of Marx and the Jew-as-racial-contaminator
obsessions of Hitler seem to have their roots in these early experiences. From
these roots grew their respective world-views by a process of paranoid
exaggeration. For Marx the entire bourgeoisie had become a Jewish usurer. For
Hitler the whole German nation was threatened by Jewish racial contamination.
Each man targeted one group as responsible for all the ills of human society,
and exhorted others to work towards the overthrow and annihilation of that
group. Each man sought to use the alleged oppression of a large victim group,
with which he deeply identified, as a trampoline to his own personal power – with Marx, a
class he did not belong to, and with Hitler, a nation he belonged to only by
adoption, or by a racial concept of the nation. The main difference, as far as
their success is concerned, is that Marx was personally charmless, a dirty,
foul-tempered drunkard who quarrelled violently with every single associate
except Engels, while Hitler, after his youth as an outcast, developed a
charisma and an orator’s gift which inspired a fatal degree of loyalty and
devotion. The one ended his days in obscurity and squalor, execrating the world
(his favourite phrase to socialist rivals was “I will annihilate
you!” 18 The other achieved his dream of
absolute power and monstrous revenge upon the designated scapegoats. Marx would
have to wait for the vicarious and posthumous fulfilment of his own
mass-murdering fantasies till the coming to power of his disciples, Lenin,
Stalin, Mao and Pol Pot, none of whom there is any reason to believe he would
have disavowed.
Of course, we can
only surmise, not demonstrate, that Marx would have approved the colossal
violence of those who put his theories into practice. He never had the
opportunity in his life to engage in more than verbal violence. But that verbal
violence was extreme and disturbing. He constantly urged the use of physical
force and killing. He addressed the Prussian government in 1849: “We are ruthless and ask no
quarter from you. When our turn comes we shall not disguise our terrorism.” 19 His “Plan of Action” distributed in Germany
the following year called for mob violence: “Far from opposing the
so-called excesses, those examples of popular vengeance against hated
individuals or public buildings which have acquired hateful memories, we must
not only condone these examples but lend them a helping hand.” 20 He was furious at the failure of the attempt to assassinate the
Emperor Wilhelm I in 1878. But his most violent wrath was usually reserved not
for the capitalist enemy, who would be exterminated by a scientific,
ineluctable process, but for his rivals among socialist thinkers – men like
Proudhon and Lassalle. The latter, a rival for leadership of the International,
was variously called by Marx “the Jewish Nigger”, “a greasy Jew
disguised under brilliantine and cheap jewels”, “as the shape of his head and
the growth of his hair indicate, he is descended from the Negroes who joined in
Moses’ flight from Egypt (unless his mother or grandmother on the father’s side was
crossed with a nigger.) This union of Jew and German on a Negro basis was bound
to produce an extraordinary hybrid.” 21 None of this racist and anti-Semitic abuse has the excuse of being
indignant wrath directed at the wicked capitalist oppressor. It was all
directed at a rival socialist. Its physicality is striking – especially when
the physical characteristics held up for contempt were so close to his own (he
was not only of Jewish parentage himself, but he had a sallow complexion and
shock of black hair which led his family to refer to him as “the Moor”.) But can anyone
doubt that a man animated by this degree of savage hatred of fellow leftists
would have found the back-stabbing Stalinist purges of the Thirties a perfectly
congenial atmosphere? They merely translated into action his own violent
intolerance of anyone who differed from his own doctrine by a hair’s breadth, or
challenged his own pre-eminence. In Marx we see a perfect example of how the
verbal and ideological violence of the nineteenth century laid down the basis
for the physical violence of the twentieth.
To argue that
Marx’s work already contains all the seeds of the violence of Marxist
regimes goes against a certain current among his disciples which has tried to
distinguish between “pure Marxism” and its perversion by
Lenin, Stalin and the rest. But if we take a particularly violent passage of
Lenin’s, what is striking about it is how closely it resembles Marx. Here is
Lenin commenting in 1906 on the failure of the 1905 Moscow Uprising:
We should have
taken up arms more aggressively, energetically and resolutely; we should have
explained to the masses that it was impossible to confine things to a peaceful
strike and that a fearless and relentless armed fight was necessary. And now we
must at last openly and publicly admit that political strikes are inadequate..… We should be
deceiving both ourselves and the people if we concealed from the masses the
necessity of a desperate, bloody war of extermination, as the immediate task of
the coming revolutionary action. 22
This is language Hitler
might have used. There is no disguising the murderous intent of the
revolutionaries: bloody extermination of their opponents, the entire bourgeois
class. And this is not mere rhetoric: Lenin and Stalin set about doing it. But
is there anything to distinguish this from Marx’s rhetoric? Is it
not similar to his “Far from opposing the so-called excesses, we must…
lend them a helping hand”? Nearly all
Marxists of the twentieth century accepted that Marxism called for a violent
revolution and the extermination of the class enemy. Régis Debray at the start
of his Critique of Arms quotes this
passage from Lenin with approval as the orthodox Marxist-Leninist view, and
then argues, regretfully, that this kind of armed struggle may no longer be
possible – not for moral or humane reasons, of course, but
because of a shift in the balance of force due to the armaments and training of
modern armies. The difference between Marx’s and Lenin’s attitudes to
violence, in so far as one can discern any, is merely the difference between
the theoretician and the practitioner.
4) PITY AND HATRED: THE
REVOLUTIONARY SYMBIOSIS
Yet the starting
point of this apotheosis of class conflict, violence and extermination is still,
one must suppose, an initial compassion for the suffering and exploited working
class. Throughout his life Marx expressed solidarity with various oppressed
groups, from the Irish nationalists to the refugees from the Paris Commune, to
some of whom he gave shelter. But this compassion tends to disappear in Marx’s work as the
hatred of the class responsible for all oppression grows more extreme. His
contemporaries commented on his misanthropic personality. Bakunin wrote of him:
“His heart is not full of love but of bitterness and he has very little
sympathy for the human race.” Another revolutionary, Techow, who knew him well,
commented: “If his heart had matched his intellect and he had
possessed as much love as hate, I would have gone through fire for him.” But “he is lacking in
nobility of soul. I am convinced that a most dangerous ambition has eaten away
all the good in him…. The acquisition of personal power is the aim
of all his endeavours.” 23
How are we to
explain this paradox of compassion for the suffering of the oppressed felt by a
personality filled with hatred, violence and hunger for power? Should we see
that compassion as a hypocritical pose, covering a cynical view of the workers
as merely the instruments of his revenge? Yet the genuine emotion that seems to
pervade certain passages of his work precludes this cynical interpretation.
There is perhaps, paradoxical as it may seem, an odd symbiosis between violent
hatred and compassion. Graham Green describes his Mexican communist police
official in The Power and the Glory
in a brilliant phrase: “a dapper figure of hate carrying his secret of love.” That could stand
as a description of many a twentieth century Marxist. Pasternak in Doctor Zhivago tries to convey something
of the same in his portrait of the ruthless revolutionary commander Strelnikov.
The starting point of the revolutionary commitment may be love, compassion for
the oppressed, but the end point, after enough civil war and revolutionary “justice”, is a hatred and
cruelty that begin to be directed against pity itself, as though it is a cause
of pain and must be suppressed. Every act of violence and cruelty in the
revolutionary combat becomes a way of scratching the wound left by the initial
love. Pity for suffering inspires a violent aggression against the one held
responsible for the suffering. In order to steel the heart to commit acts of
cruelty against the enemy, one must feel a surge of compassion for the victims
of that enemy. As we have noted, the Nazi special police battalions in Poland, when
ordered to kill Jewish women and children, were urged to think of the German
women and children at that moment being burned alive in Allied bombing raids.
Compassion for some children was seen by the officers as a spur to murder other
children. In a curious mirror image, British bomber pilots who had problems of
conscience about incinerating German women and children were given pep talks by
the likes of Koestler on the genocide going on in the Nazi death camps. In this
way compassion can be used to incite violent indignation, which in its turn
incites aggression and hatred and the necessary hardness to carry out the mass
murder of those held responsible for the suffering. It is no accident that the
nineteenth century, the age of a new compassion and pity for suffering, should
have given birth to an ideology of implacable hatred and violence towards those
who caused that suffering. We might even suspect that it is only compassion and
moral indignation that can provide the intensity of conviction necessary for
large-scale projects of mass-murder. And the key here is the element of moral
self-righteousness that compassion induces, the enraged conviction that those
who cause this suffering are diabolically evil. One need look no further to see
this process at work than the mind of the Oklahoma bomber, Timothy McVeigh – enraged by the FBI’s massacre of
innocent people at Waco and bent on revenge on what he saw as an evil force.
There in microcosm we see the paranoid revenger mentality which lies at the
heart of both Marxism and Nazism. And it plays its part in the mindset of every
extremist group from the terrorists of Al Qaeda to the animal liberationists,
whipping themselves on to acts of violence with images of the tortured victims
whose cause they espouse.
It is significant
that the indignation which compassion inspires in this sort of mind almost
always leads to a paranoid theory of the enemy group as diabolically evil. The
belief in absolute evil is what Marx drags up to the surface from the underground
apocalyptic tradition. The eighteenth century Enlightenment had virtually
abolished the notion of evil. The French philosophes,
with their atheistic leanings, tended to accept Socrates’ notion that evil
was merely ignorance, and would gradually be eliminated by the spread of
knowledge. Marx (who appears to have read his bible in his youth, at least till
his Confirmation at fifteen) dredges back up from the bas fonds of the European consciousness the whole mad extremist
vision of the most purple passages of Revelations
about the Whore of Babylon, the Beast and the Antichrist. This becomes the
moral climate of the twentieth century in both Marxist and fascist countries: a
heroic, ruthless struggle to the death against implacable, diabolical evil. The
history of Marxism reeks with imagery from The
Apocalypse. Jean Ziegler, a Swiss Marxist, says he was urged by Che Guevara
to stay in Geneva and not go off to join Third World revolutions, because in the city of
international banks he was “inside the brain of the Beast.” 24 International capitalism as the Beast from Revelations is the symbolism that underlies the whole theology of
Marxism. The overthrow of the Beast by one last cataclysmic battle – Armageddon, the
revolution, one last orgy of violence against absolute evil – is the goal of
human history, the means of liberation of man’s natural
goodness, which will usher in the millennium, the thousand-year reign of the
Just.
But should we
search for other reasons for this revival of evil as a key element in the
nineteenth-century world view? Were the bloody violence of the French
Revolution, the unspeakable atrocities of the Vendée war, or the massive
carnage of Napoleon’s battles factors in this return of the concept of
evil? Was it romanticism with its diabolism, from Goethe’s Faust to Poe
and Melville? Should we evoke the Gothic horror story or the romantic
death-wish? Or the hellish physical ugliness of the new factories, the polluted
towns, the stinking purple-dyed rivers? Or was it a new obsession with the
machine, with Blake’s “dark Satanic mills”, a sense that
oppression was no longer human, not a living outgrowth of age-old inequalities
of property, but was an organized system, a giant machine crushing its victims
with inexorable purpose? Whatever the causes, the change of ethos between the
two centuries is extraordinary. Marx’s favourite quotation from
Goethe’s Mephistopheles “Everything that is must be
destroyed!” stands in striking contrast to Voltaire’s gentle satire
of the eighteenth century deist: “Everything is for the best
in the best of all possible worlds.” The dividing line is both
the French Revolution and romanticism. And the great problem of romanticism was
that absolute evil was reintroduced into a world that had lost God. Blake had
already inverted God and devil, seeing an evil force in control of the world
and rebellion as the divine spark. Shelley’s Prometheus likewise
exalted revolt against a diabolical deity as the only hope of redemption. When Nietzsche declared God dead,
he left the world in the hands of the devil. And the devil can only be fought
with weapons of violence and implacable hatred. For revolutionaries like Marx,
God had receded into the vague and distant benevolence of historical processes,
which became the guarantor of the ultimately happy outcome of the violent human
struggle, to be waged alone and without divine help against the Beast.
If we can sum up
an era briefly without too much distortion, we have the conjunction of three
things in the early nineteenth century: a new sensibility to suffering and
injustice (which had become more visible with the factory system); a new belief
in absolute evil as the cause of suffering; and finally an inability to see
this evil as a forgivable part of man’s natural corruption (a result
of “original sin”), because man’s nature had now been
declared innocent and perfectible. Lacking religious faith, a belief in
original sin or a sense of tragedy, certain nineteenth century minds could only
incorporate the new sensibility to suffering into a cosmic moral melodrama, in
which pity for the oppressed generated fanatical and murderous hatred for the
oppressor. It is this that lies at the heart of the revolutionary ideology. And
the remnants of that ideology still govern the world-view of much of the
Western intelligentsia today.
5) MARXISM AND
SADO-MASOCHISM
That
Marxist-Leninism as a movement has in it something that is harsh, brutal,
ruthless and violent, which glories in the crushing of sentiment, sensitivity
and humane scruples, is clear from its
actual practice over the past hundred years. But the passionate attraction of
millions of idealistic and compassionate men and women for a totalitarian
movement dedicated to violence and extermination led to perversions of the
human soul that future ages may have difficulty comprehending. One
characteristic that becomes essential to the loyal Party member is masochism.
The emotional and moral atmosphere of Marxist-Leninism in action is best
conveyed in the works of fiction written by its repentant ex-militants. Arthur
Koestler’s Darkness at
Noon is a stunning exposure by an insider of what was going on mentally
behind the show trials in the USSR
in the 1930’s (later to be repeated in Eastern
Europe after the Second World War.) Recent allegations (after his
death, when he could not answer them) of Koestler’s own sexual
violence can, if true, only serve to emphasize how deeply this ideology both
perverted the human personality and attracted the pathologically violent.
In a central
scene in the novel, a communist commissar explains to an arrested party member
who is to be tried and executed, why all this obeys some historic necessity,
with which the victim himself has a duty to co-operate.
“Not to perish,” sounded Gletkin’s voice. “The bulwark must
be held, at any price and with any sacrifice. The leader of the Party
recognized this principle with unrivalled clear-sightedness, and has
consistently applied it. The policy of the International had to be subordinated
to our national policy. Whoever did not understand this necessity had to be
destroyed. Whole sets of our best functionaries in Europe
had to be physically liquidated. We did not recoil from crushing our own
organizations abroad when the interests of the Bastion required it. We did not
recoil from co-operation with the police of reactionary countries in order to
suppress revolutionary movements which came at the wrong moment. We did not
recoil from betraying our friends and compromising with our enemies, in order
to preserve the Bastion. That was the task which history had given us, the
representatives of the first victorious revolution. The shortsighted, the
aesthetes, the moralists did not understand. But the leader of the Revolution
understood that all depended on one thing: to be the better stayer……
“The Party’s line was
sharply defined. Its tactics were determined by the principle that the end
justifies the means – all means without exception. In the spirit of this
principle, the Public Prosecutor will demand your life, Citizen Rubashov.
“Your faction, Citizen
Rubashov, is beaten and destroyed. You wanted to split the Party, although you
must have known that a split in the Party meant civil war.… If your
repentance is real, then you must help us to heal this rent. I have told you,
it is the last service the Party will ask you.
“Your task is simple. You
have set it yourself: to gild the Right, to blacken the Wrong. The policy of
the opposition is wrong. Your task then is to make the opposition contemptible;
to make the masses understand that opposition is a crime and that the leaders
of the opposition are criminals.… Your task is to avoid
awakening sympathy and pity. ….
“Comrade Rubashov, I hope you
have understood the task which the Party has set you.”
It was the first time that Gletkin had called Rubashov “Comrade”. Rubashov raised
his head quickly. He felt a hot flush rising in him, against which he was
helpless. His chin shook slightly while he was putting on his pince-nez.
“I understand.”
“Observe,” Gletkin went on,
“that the party holds out to you no prospect of reward. Some of the
accused have been made amenable by physical pressures. Others by the promise to
save their heads or the heads of their relatives who have fallen into our hands
as hostages. To you, Comrade Rubashov, we propose no bargain and we promise
nothing..….. You were wrong and you will pay, Comrade
Rubashov. The Party promises only one thing: after the victory, one day when it
can do no more harm, the material of the secret archives will be published ……… And then you,
and some of your friends of the older generation, will be given the sympathy
and pity which are denied to you today.”
While he was speaking, he had pushed the
prepared statement over to Rubashov, and laid his fountain-pen beside it.
Rubashov stood up and said with a strained smile:
“I have always wondered what
it was like when the Neanderthalers became sentimental. Now I know.”
“I do not
understand,” said Gletkin.
Rubashov signed the statement. 25
Koestler adds a
note in a later edition to explain that when the head of Soviet Military
Intelligence for Western Europe, General Walter Krivitsky, defected, he
confirmed that this was exactly how some of the leading old Bolsheviks on trial
had been brought to confess. Why, he asks, did they “flagellate
themselves for crimes which they never could have committed and which have been
proved to be fantastic lies?” He then answers: “Although several
factors contributed to bringing the men to the point of making these
confessions, they made them at last in the sincere conviction that this was
their sole remaining service to the Party and the revolution.” 26
It is difficult
for a normal human being to comprehend the minds revealed in this passage of
Koestler’s. The apparatchik who revels in the ruthless
destructiveness of the Party, its crushing of its own agents as expendable
cannon fodder, who glories in the absolute brutality and moral perfidy of his
own cause, and can then elicit from the accused veteran communist complete
co-operation in his own humiliation and psychic annihilation for the sake of
the party – this is all
alien to a normal, civilized mind. That the old communist can be moved almost
to tears by this appeal is the final stroke. Such is the emotional
sterilization of this person that the appeal to party loyalty alone awakens a
response, as if it is the last emotional neurone still alive. This kind of mind
has become a machine in the service of a cause to the point of annihilating its
own sense of personal worth, dignity, pride, and intellectual and moral
integrity. This mind even feels a perverse satisfaction at the end in
annihilating the last shred of its own dignity in the service of the Party. The
masochism of this mental condition goes beyond what one would have thought
possible. This is the triumph of a cult of power, aggression and murder over
one’s own life and soul, so that one wills to crush and humiliate oneself
and obtains a perverse pleasure from doing it. This is the notion of military
discipline, total surrender of mind and body to the organization, the
hierarchical leadership, the superior authority, taken to the point of psychic
suicide. And it is of course only military-type organizations, only those which
are themselves engaged in exterminating and murdering and crushing their
enemies, that ever elicit this kind of absolute loyalty. In order to crush
oneself willingly under a machine, one has to identify with the power of the
machine to crush others, one has to revel in its destructiveness, and that
destructiveness must be infinite and awe-inspiring. That is the only way to
transform the violence done to oneself as passive object into violence which
one actively identifies with and takes part in. To revel in one’s own destruction
is only possible if in so doing one can contribute to some wider and more
appalling process of destruction. Since I wrote these words, the suicide
attacks on the World
Trade Center
and the Pentagon by airliner-hijackers have given a horrific illustration of
this mental condition.
The remark about
Neanderthals is revealing; Koestler’s character feels that the
human type represented by the party apparatchik is a throwback to a
pre-civilized man, to something so brutal as to be only proto-human. Something
has happened to human beings which has made them unlike any human beings in a
civilized society. It is not the cruelty that is in question here, or the need
to utterly humiliate traitors. Brutal tyrannies have existed in the past which
executed people in public with gruesome tortures to compel them to confess and
glorify the king or the church before they expired. But one cannot help
thinking that they did not enslave the souls of men so completely as to
convince them of the moral rightness of their own annihilation. There is a
degree of moral masochism here that is pathological. And there seems to be
something here that strikes one as primarily a masculine pathology – something driven
by testosterone. Masochism, in its pathological forms, is primarily a male
sexual perversion, because of the ferocious amount of aggression against the
self which it requires. But in addition
there is here an identification with the power and destructive capacity of the
entity that is destroying one; there is the enjoyment of the crushing of one’s own weakness,
one’s own softness, one’s own sentiments, compassion, and self-pity; and
there is the notion of an abstract idea prevailing over the love of life
itself. The film Dr Strangelove ends
with the fantastic image of the cowboy pilot riding the atomic bomb down to its
annihilation of mankind, yelling and waving his hat in triumph. His own death
is nothing compared to the big bang he is about to make. It is the mentality of
the suicide bomber. The male, as Freud thought and suicide statistics confirm,
has a far greater tendency than the female to suicide, to a death wish. Every
suicidal charge in battle requires the identification of the soldier with a
powerful aggressive machine which he is part of, even though it will probably
destroy him. We have in this scene of Koestler’s a passion for
self-annihilation which may be the ultimate perversion of the ultra-masculine
mind, the very nadir of the distortions of human nature of the masculine century.
What explains the
extraordinary seduction that Marxism exercised over the minds of twentieth century intellectuals? Perhaps it
is this very combination of compassion and cruelty, of love and hatred, of pity
and aggression. It is the sheer range of human emotions satisfied by the
Marxist world view that perhaps explains its appeal. What other ideology allows
one to revel in the mass murder of droves of reactionary poets in labour camps,
while at the same time shedding tears for the oppressed, or waxing lyrical
about the future race of proletarian saints? And these contradictory emotions
are linked. It is pity for the sufferings of the oppressed and delirious dreams
of a future paradise that fuel the violent and vindictive urge to destroy the
oppressor, the saboteur of human happiness. This channelling of compassion into
violent aggression is perhaps more natural for people of a masculine,
high-testosterone personality: they cannot endure others’ sufferings
passively. The religious world-view of Christianity in its Catholic or Anglican
form is in many ways a feminine emotional state: submission to the will of God,
a fatalistic acceptance of evil and suffering, efforts to lessen suffering on
an individual level, but without rejecting the total world-system within which
it occurs. This spirit of acceptance can lead Alexander Pope to declare “Whatever is, is
right!” Certain Buddhist teachers have tried to explain
that paradise is already here on earth but we don’t have the purity
of soul to recognize it. This spirit of world-affirmation of the mystic looks
like complacency in the face of suffering. The unendurable tension of this
passive world-view is already felt by Blake, who in an angry explosion against
it inverts God and Devil, and ends up with a Manichean vision in which the
material universe is Satan’s work and the divine spark is eternal rebellion
against him. It is this new spirit of revolt, rebellion, refusal to accept the
world order which romanticism brings into human consciousness. Rebellion suddenly
shifts from being the sin of pride to being the liberating virtue. The
romantics stood Milton on his head and claimed
that the rebel Satan was really the hero and Milton was of the devil’s party. What brought
this change of perspective? Perhaps the new energy and activism of man, as he
entered an age of industrial and political upheaval and began to feel his own
power to transform the world, made the quietism of established Christianity
seem cowardly. The shift from the passive, feminine acceptance of suffering to
an ideology of violent combat against the system that causes it signalled a
new, aggressive, masculine approach to life. To conceive of the whole of life
and of history as a ceaseless war (not a spiritual war against one’s own vices but a
violent struggle against external enemies) shows a new masculine combativeness
of spirit, a perception of life in terms of aggression, which is completely
new. All previous religions saw the enemy as essentially within man, his own
corruption and sinfulness. Their crusading periods against external enemies or
infidels were short-lived and exceptional: the essential battle was against the
self. In the masculine century the self-doubt, self-awareness or self-criticism
that made man see his own nature as primarily to blame for evil is replaced by
a permanent projection of evil onto the other, the oppressor class, the
conspiring enemy. The moral combat to overcome one’s own vices and
purify one’s own soul is replaced by a political combat to
overthrow and exterminate the enemy oppressor. This new mood makes political
violence the basic impulse through which man engages with the world, overcomes
evil and attains salvation.
6) MARXISM AS ETERNAL
WARFARE
It is this
transfer into the political sphere of the moral struggle to the death against
evil that makes Marxism an enemy of democracy. The problem with Marxism is the
perception of the adversary as evil. There can be no compromise with those who
have different opinions and interests, because the struggle against them has
become a religious and moral struggle to remove human suffering, to redeem
mankind, to vanquish evil. It has become a redemptive struggle against Satanic
forces, which admits of no compromise. An Italian communist who went to Moscow often and met Lenin
and other leaders reported: “What struck me most about the Russian communists,
even in such really exceptional personalities as Lenin and Trotsky, was their
utter incapacity to be fair in discussing opinions that conflicted with their
own. The adversary, simply for daring to contradict, at once became a traitor,
an opportunist, a hireling. An adversary in good faith is inconceivable to the
Russian communists.” 27 If this was their view of their own dissident comrades, we can
imagine the degree of violent hostility they felt for their non-communist
opponents. The refusal to see the interests of the enemy class as legitimate,
the belief that any compromise with them would be moral betrayal, makes
democracy impossible for Marxists. This is what caused the two great
experiments to bring about Marxist socialism by parliamentary means – in Spain in the 1930’s and in Chile in 1970 – to end in
catastrophe. In both cases a revolutionary extreme refused the compromises
needed to maintain constitutional government in an evenly divided country where
the opposition had enough votes to block legislation in parliament. In both
cases the left took to street violence and illegal means to do what they could
not do legally. In both cases they defended their illegality by an appeal to
the higher morality of their cause. And in both cases a military coup and a
bloody dictatorship wiped out all the moderate gains in social justice they
could have made by sticking to legal methods.
The very
perception of the other class as the enemy rather than the opponent, the denial
of the other’s legitimacy, the introduction of self-righteous,
moralizing hatred (to the point of seeking to physically eliminate the other)
into a political contest between social groups – this is the
poison that Marx introduced into political life. It is in fact a religious
element: an element of demonization of the bourgeois enemy, conceived of as an
absolute of evil, because held responsible for an absolute of suffering. As we
have argued, this demonization is the direct consequence of the sentimentality
and compassion which the early nineteenth century developed above all previous
ages. Pity demands a diabolical cause for the sufferings it cannot endure to
see. Victim and oppressor become almost different species, the one so
martyrized that he must embody all virtues, the other so evil that he is beyond
redemption. Yet when Marx’s own friend Engels was a successful capitalist
factory-owner who paid Marx’s living expenses out of capitalist profits, when
his own uncle founded the Philips industrial empire (and also regularly lent
him money), this racist view of his own bourgeois class as an enemy to be
exterminated must surely have struck even him at times as fanatical and
monstrous. That is the blind spot – the disconnection between
fanatical theory and human reality – which makes Marxism a
monstrous, inhuman ideology – as evil as Nazism, if not as immediately repulsive.
To murder people for their class is just as monstrous as to murder them for
their race. It is just as much a denial of their humanity as individuals. And
in the twentieth century, class-based murders outnumbered race-based murders by
at least five to one.
But despite the
fall of Soviet communism, the key idea which Marx bequeathed the world – that
of the eternal combat against an absolute of evil oppression – is far from
extinct. It animates every cause that
came out of the “new left” explosion of the 1960’s: feminism,
anti-racism, anti-colonialism, homosexual liberation. All of these movements are
neo-Marxist in that they accept Marx’s premise of a class of evil
oppressors exploiting a victim class by means of a diabolically evil ideology.
Both the oppressor class and their ideology must be fought in an unending
struggle for justice and liberation. Of these the anti-racist, anti-colonialist
ideology (they are in practice inseparable) is the most direct descendant of
Marxism, and may be considered its logical development.
By the 1960’s Marxism had run
into some serious problems. It had become embarrassingly obvious that its
predictions about the inevitable pauperization of the workers under advanced
capitalism had not come true. An update had to be concocted which would explain
the failure of these prophecies, and the failure of the revolution to come
about. In general, the division of society into a good proletariat and an evil
bourgeoisie was only credible while class differences remained glaring and
obvious. In the prosperous sixties, mass consumerism eroded the obvious
differences between the two classes, as Western workers began owning cars,
houses and taking holidays abroad, and styles of life, dress and speech became
democratized. But even while the class gap was closing, another gap began to
yawn: the gap between the soaring living standards of the West as a whole and
the impoverished stagnation of non-Western countries. The Marxist intellectual
of the nineteen-sixties concluded that the real proletariat was now the "Third World", and the oppressive bourgeoisie was now
the entire Western race. Capitalism had temporarily saved itself by co-opting
its working class into a new global bourgeoisie, exploiting a new global
proletariat. It was in the new struggle between the Third
World and the capitalist West that the fate of mankind would be
played out, and the apocalyptic climax achieved.
7) MARXISM AS RACISM
Imperceptibly,
Marx's class division of mankind thus became a race division. White became the
colour of the oppressor, and black that of the oppressed. Of course this shift
was influenced by the civil rights movement in America, which was simply an
assertion by black Americans of their
rights under the Constitution, which southern whites had denied in order to
maintain their own dominance. It had been part of the process of North-South reconciliation
after the Civil War to turn a blind eye to the continued unofficial oppression
of the liberated slaves in the South, so as not to upset the entire social and
political apple-cart. Leaders like Martin Luther King took the American
Constitution seriously and wanted it applied: they believed in American
democracy. But of course the civil rights struggle soon radicalized and threw
up the inevitable Marxist extremists – those blacks who rejected
reformism and espoused violence in the service of some ill-defined racial
revolution. This new creed of racial revolution became the leading edge of the
new form of neo-Marxism world-wide. It seized on the example of South Africa – where a
neo-colonial regime of white rule still existed, and blacks were struggling to
achieve majority rule through a violent liberation movement – as the symbol
and focus of a global struggle. Beyond the South African blacks the leftists
saw the shadow of hundreds of millions
of Third World peasants struggling to
overthrow the global tyranny of Western imperialism. To this mix was added the
whole issue of black immigration into European countries, and the hostility and
rejection many immigrants faced from the society around them. Out of this
cocktail of different issues, a new evil was distilled and identified: white
racism. And its most diverse manifestations were exposed, denounced and
campaigned against, as though this were the new incarnation of Satan in our
time.
Anyone who looked
at the rising tensions between different ethnic communities in Western
countries and ventured to propose a halt to further immigration became at once
the new racist enemy, the voice of a diabolical belief-system that was at the
root of all human suffering. Any suggestion that white people had a right to
their own countries or the right to keep other races out of them was equated
with Hitlerism. It became the goal of the anti-racist movement to end the evil
of “white rule” anywhere on earth, by putting an end to the
obscenity of all-white or even majority-white nations. It was crucial to this
ideology to promote open immigration into Western countries as the only morally
acceptable policy. For a country to limit its immigration on grounds that might
even be suspected to be racial was enough to make it an object of universal
vituperation. Australia’s “white Australia
policy” of the 1950’s was placed in the same
moral category as Hitler’s genocide of the Jews. Moreover, all Western
societies had to become not only multi-racial but multi-cultural. Not only was
it wrong for them to shut out immigrants of other races, whether or not they
needed them; it was wrong to try to assimilate immigrants once there. The
desire to assimilate other races into one’s own culture implied a
wicked belief in one’s own cultural superiority: it should be the
immigrant’s culture (and even language) that one sought to
understand, preserve and promote. In this way some militants seemed to hope
that a permanently separate and alienated racial minority could be implanted in
every Western country, and eventually, through their higher birth-rates, the
oppressed non-whites of the earth would end up as the majority everywhere. That
is why South Africa
became such a potent symbol. Its liberation was a foreshadowing of what the
Marxists hoped would eventually be the fate of all Western countries – the overthrow of
the wicked white race by the global non-white majority and the replacement of
white racist tyranny by the universal rule of the oppressed.
The terrorist
attacks on America
in September 2001 may have dented the confidence of some Western leftists that
all evil will be brought to an end with the overthrow of the wicked white race.
But the assumptions of this ideology of Western self-hatred still underlie much
of the debate about a range of subjects: racism, refugees, immigration, Third
World debt, Third World aid, anti-poverty
programmes, underdevelopment, affirmative action, and the sporadic demands for
compensation for the African slave-trade. All these debates are still imbued
with a smouldering moral indignation at what is considered an enormous racial
injustice: the relative prosperity of the white race all over the planet and
the misery in which many people with darker skins live. To those with a
somewhat tenuous grasp of the history of the world, this state of affairs could
only have resulted from the organized white oppression of other races. The
notion that wealth is not something that grows on trees, but can only be
created by industrialized systems, and that the non-industrialized parts of the
world are therefore poor, is not readily accepted by those who have come to
regard industrialism as the first of evils. The poverty of Africa and parts of
Asia is not therefore seen as resulting from the lack of something – namely, industrial
development, efficient, modern economic systems and honest, democratic
administrations – but rather as resulting from some criminal act, by
which the wealth that is every human being’s natural birthright was
somehow snatched away from Third World peoples by wicked imperialist
exploiters. The poverty of the under-developed world is the result of our
criminal oppression – this is the deep conviction of large numbers
of “progressive” people all over
the West. An old-style communist like the Swiss Jean Ziegler, recycled as a UN
development official, declares in a rage of indignation that the poverty of
blacks in northern Brazil is the direct fault of the “white, dominating
Westerners” in Switzerland and the EU.28 How exactly
they exert this malign influence is not made clear – perhaps by
keeping their savings in banks which lend money to foreign governments and then
outrageously expect something back. The whole history of colonialism is seen
not as a ham-fisted, autocratic Western attempt at development of Africa and Asia (both for their own good and for ours), but as a
long regime of criminal plunder which caused their present poverty. No railway,
road, bridge or harbour built, no school, hospital, post office, civil service,
law court or parliament established by the colonizers can possibly be admitted
to have had any benevolent motive or positive effect. It was all part of an
enormous tyranny, a cultural aggression, a genocide, a destruction of a way of
life. All the problems and poverty of the Third World
today result from this one evil – colonialism. The
neo-Marxist vision cannot admit of mixed motives – that generosity
and greed, assistance and exploitation, the urge to develop and the urge to
rule might have co-existed (or struggled for supremacy) in the minds of the
colonizers. History can only be the story of single-minded, ruthless oppression
of helpless innocents – a saga of diabolical forces forever destroying a
golden age.
That this golden
age was in large areas of the world one of perennial famine, precarious
subsistence farming, tyranny, slavery, tribal warfare, cannibalism, and human
sacrifice, cannot be admitted for one moment. All such images of the Third World are held to be either a figment of Western
man’s racist bigotry, or else the product of colonialism itself. It is
seriously believed in many leftist circles that slavery and tribal warfare were
brought to Africa by the wicked white man.
Genocidal tribal wars in Africa today (such as
the massacre of Tutsis by Hutus) are routinely blamed on the colonizers who
left forty years ago. The multiculturalist neo-Marxists are committed to a
notion that the world was naturally a garden of Eden, inhabited by gentle,
peace-loving indigenous peoples, in simple but prosperous and “sustainable” economies, until
an odious serpent – the white man and his capitalist ways – entered that
Eden and destroyed it. And by a fiendishly clever process of plunder, this
diabolical entity has transformed his own part of the planet into a zone of
prosperity, while leaving the exploited husk of the rest of the earth to fester
in misery and deprivation.
8)
WESTERN SELF-HATRED: THE TRIUMPH OF NEO-MARXISM
The ultimate
result of the extraordinary capacity for aggression developed by Western man
over the last century and a half has thus been the turning of this aggression
against himself. Highly-educated Westerners over the last thirty years have
developed a more violent hatred of their own civilization and even their own
race than the ruling class of any other society in the history of the world.
The men who invented parliamentary democracy, human rights, science, modern
medicine, industrial systems, advanced technology and levels of mass prosperity
beyond the dreams of all previous civilizations, the men who banned slavery and
torture for the first time anywhere on earth, gave women political rights and
asserted the equality of all human beings – these Western men have
somehow become, in their own eyes, the villains of human history, defined by
four words: colonialism, slavery, racism, sexism. On the neo-Marxist left, the
hatred of Western man has reached such a level that it has become legitimate to
call openly for the extermination of the white race. Susan Sontag (awarded the
Prince of Asturias prize in 2004, just before her death) declared early in her
career: “The white race is the cancer of human history.” She went on: “It is the white
race and it alone – its ideologies and inventions – which eradicates
autonomous civilizations wherever it spreads.” She never
deviated from that belief – even finding justifications for the terrorists of
September 11, 2001.29 Jean-Paul Sartre approved the murder of white
people by black as a revolutionary, liberating act – and would no
doubt have applauded 9/11 as a blow struck for the oppressed.30 In
fact the terrorists of 9/11 were only carrying into action the views preached
by Western leftist intellectuals for the past forty years. If Western
capitalists are the evil exploiters of the planet, if world trade is a
conspiracy against the poorer nations, then why not kill three thousand wicked
agents of imperialism as they sit at their desks in their megalomaniac towers
plotting the subjugation of humanity? This view is what explains the
undisguised glee of many Western leftists after the September 11 attacks. One
American history professor declared to his students: “Anyone who can
blow up the Pentagon has my vote.” 31 This has gone beyond the zany anarchism of the Vietnam
generation. The history of mankind taught in many Western schools and universities
for the past three decades has been a systematic brainwashing in Western guilt
and self-hatred. A large proportion of people of college education think that
the extermination of the American Indians, the slave trade, the oppression of
blacks, colonialism, sexism and the genocide of the Jews are the essential
facts of history, and nothing else needs to be known of that muddle of
unpleasant goings-on that happened before they were born. These are the salient
events that govern an entire generation’s emotional
relationship with the past and with their own culture and nation. Most of the
recipients of this kind of post-1968 education have no idea that there is
anything in their culture worth preserving, anything in their political systems
worth fighting for, or anything that their ancestors achieved which might be a
cause for gratitude or even a source of pride. They have been taught that their
past was one long evil, that their grand-parents were part of a gigantic system
of global oppression, and that the prosperity they now enjoy was stolen from
others. They think that the freedom and democracy that makes Western nations so
attractive to other people is simply the natural condition of things, achieved
without any struggle, any intellectual vision or moral heroism, and that its
absence elsewhere can only be the fault of Western colonialism and oppression.
The result is a profound and muddled guilt complex and a collective death-wish.
This neo-Marxist education has deprived the average young Westerner of his
roots, of his history, and of any real grasp of his place in the world, other
than as the villain of the planet.
9)
HISTORY AS A FABLE OF WESTERN EVIL
It is difficult
at first sight to grasp how the academic establishment in advanced and free
countries, with access to all the facts, could fall into the ideological
dogmatism, lockstep thinking and suppression of the truth that now
characterizes American, British and to a lesser extent other Western
universities. How do intelligent people arrive at collective self-intoxication
and self-brainwashing in the hatred of their own civilization? It is worth
looking at this for a minute or two, because this is the last twist in the
fascinating story of Marxism and its influence on the world.
One reason for
this intoxication in guilt and self-hatred is the highly selective view of the
past that many people now have – a view almost entirely determined by emotion.
History presents an infinite number of facts and we cannot focus on all of
them, or even take all of them into account. The selection we make of which
facts to look at, and in what sort of narrative to assemble them, unless guided
by the traditional academic authority of the experts in the field, is generally
made on emotive or ideological grounds. And there is no emotion that human beings today are more prone to
when looking at the past than indignation. This is because of the extraordinary
change in moral and humane attitudes that began in the 18th century
European Enlightenment and went on up to the late 20th century. This
evolution in our moral attitudes and sense of humanity has rendered much of our
own past (let alone that of other peoples) shocking to the sensibility of our
age. The study of history is not for weak stomachs. Two hundred and fifty years
ago British criminals were disembowelled in public, their innards burned before
their faces, before being butchered and cut into quarters to be mounted on the
city gates. Elsewhere they were broken on the wheel or burned with red hot
irons. Slavery was a universal institution, and the vast trade out of Africa
sent millions across the Atlantic in
conditions fit for cattle. Why do we find these things appalling? Because we
have stopped doing them. It is the very progress in moral and humane attitudes
over the past two centuries in the West that makes the past a fertile field for
the exercise of moral indignation. But this moral evolution towards humane and
enlightened behaviour, which over the past two centuries provided a narrative
vision of Western progress towards a higher civilization out of the depths of
universal human cruelty, has in this age been drastically reinterpreted.
Instead of the vision of progress towards enlightenment and humane ideals,
these same ideals are now used to condemn the entire Western past (in
particular and above all others) as a shameful saga of vicious and brutal
oppression. The past of our civilization is now singled out for sweeping
condemnation by the very standards of morality and humanity it managed (by a
unique and unprecedented intellectual struggle) to arrive at. Instead of the
abolition of the slave trade by Britain
(for the first time ever on earth) being hailed as moral progress, it is seen
only as a terrible indictment of what went before. Western civilization is seen
not as the first to put an end to the immense cruelties of the past, but as the
exemplifier and even originator of these cruelties, the source of all evil on
the planet. And the more humane and enlightened we become the more we are
contorted with paroxysms of guilt and self-hatred because we had not yet
arrived at these moral heights two hundred years ago. The further we advance,
the more shocking the path behind us looks, and the more we beat our breasts
for our past depraved state. There is no attempt to understand the past, only
to deplore it. No attempt to see contexts, causes, effects, relative progress,
heroic struggles to put an end to these horrors. Only an emotional rejection of
the whole wicked history of our nations, which our grandparents, brainwashed
with bigoted chauvinism and racism, had been taught to see as a glorious saga
of progress towards enlightenment.
One of the
features of this reinterpretation of our past in the universities and schools
today is the propensity for academics outside the field of history to seize
upon past events, react to them with the emotions of the present, and pass
sweeping moral judgements on the perpetrators, without having the slightest
understanding of these events in their historical context, or how widespread
this moral behaviour was at the time. It is the views of non-historians (like
Sontag and Choamsky) that have come to dominate how the past is seen in the
universities and schools of America
and the West in general. The charlatan theory of “post-modernism” that has
infected the literature departments encourages students to look at a text from
their own personal perspective, “deconstructing” it in the light
of their own political prejudices, and ignoring what the writer himself, bound
by the perspectives of his own age, was trying to say. The academics influenced
by this intellectual trash tradition read history in the same personal way,
without any attempt to understand the conditions and context of those times.
And the distorted perspective of these academics, based on ignorance,
indignation and emotional hysteria, has become the basis of the politically
fashionable view of the past that is now taught to students. History now
consists of a series of sensational atrocity stories about the enemy, told not
by historians but by fanatical ideologues from other academic disciplines. And
the enemy in question, for the neo-Marxist academic establishment, is simply
Western civilization itself.
The ideology of
Western self-hatred rests largely on deliberate historical misrepres-entation.
Part of this is a peculiar foreshortening of historical perspectives. History
is viewed as if it began with the rise of Western colonialism, which began with
capitalism, which was the original seed of all evil. The method of the dominant
neo-Marxist ideology has been to represent all the evils of the past – tyranny, class
oppression, slavery, torture, cruelty, sexism – not as universal
human evils, found in Europe like everywhere else (until the best European
minds campaigned to end them) but as specifically European crimes, the poisons
introduced into the world by our civilization. One of the axiomatic beliefs of
this vision of things is that Western nations in their wicked imperialism
invented slavery and imposed it on the innocent Africans. Instead of being seen
as the first nations on earth ever to abolish slavery – a universal
institution as old as time – Europeans are now widely regarded as the only
nations that ever practised it. This delusion is so widespread and popular,
especially among the younger victims of neo-Marxist education, that it merits
looking at in detail.
10) THE MARXIST
REWRITING OF THE SLAVE TRADE
Slavery was
practised everywhere by almost all peoples until the early 19th
century when Europeans (starting with Britain) abolished it for the first
time in history. The fact that African slaves were used by Europeans in their
American and Caribbean colonies at the time of this abolition has made it seem
that Africans were peculiarly the victims of this institution, and that
Europeans were peculiarly the perpetrators, and that somehow racist attitudes
lay at the root of it. None of this is true. In reality, slavery, the
compelling of some human beings to provide servile labour for others on a
lifelong and even hereditary basis, has been found in all ages and in all parts
of the world, and has nothing to do with race. Rules concerning slavery figure
in the earliest surviving code of laws, that of the Babylonian Hammurabi,
dating from around 3700 BC. 32 The main basis of slavery was the
capture of enemies in war (who were frequently the same race and sometimes even
the same nation – Germans enslaved Germans just as Africans enslaved Africans
and Aztecs enslaved Aztecs.) It was also sometimes used as a punishment for
criminals. But once a person became a slave, by whatever means, he was then
bought and sold as a labour-saving device without any sense of guilt, or any
concern as to how he had become a slave. Slavery was practised everywhere on
earth from China to Scandinavia; it was a deep-rooted tradition among the
Amerindians and the Polynesians. In the Old World it played the biggest role in
the Mediterranean and Africa. Slaves easily
outnumbered citizens in Sparta, and they may
have amounted to a third of the population of Rome
during the early empire.33 After the fall of Rome
with its hordes of slaves from every conquered nation, the vast majority of
slaves in Europe until the 15th
century were white. They were mostly Slavs – hence the word slave – because these
were the easiest pagans for the northern Europeans to get at. Christianity,
like Islam, at first accepted slavery as a fact of life, the natural product of
war and of man’s sinfulness, but both religions preached kindness towards
slaves, and disapproved of enslaving co-religionists. This meant targeting
infidels. The pagan Slavs were traded southwards to Arab Spain by the Franks,
and later to Arabia and Byzantium by Swedish Vikings (themselves pagan.) 34
For the first eight hundred years after the fall of Rome, the majority of
slaves in Europe were therefore whites, captured by other whites, and often
sold to non-whites. But once the Vikings settled down in the Slavic lands as
rulers rather than raiders, built powerful Slavic kingdoms, and all of them converted
to Christianity, slavery in the north of Europe came to an end (in about the 12th
century.) They had quite simply run out of pagans to enslave. In the south,
however, slavery persisted in an unbroken line from Roman times till the 19th
century, as it did in the Islamic world. The Arabs who conquered Spain in the 8th century enslaved the
Christian Visigoth inhabitants by the hundreds of thousands – shipping thirty
thousand white slaves as a tribute to the Caliph in Damascus immediately after the conquest. 35
As the small Spanish kingdoms in the north fought back against the invader, the
long war of the Reconquista soon took the form of slave raids between Muslim
and Christian areas. This practice was kept up when the Arabs had been pushed
out of Spain and Portugal completely at the end of the 15th
century, and slave raids across the Mediterranean
continued in both directions for hundreds of years. After the Turks captured
Constantinople in 1453 and conquered most of the Balkans and Eastern
Europe, the supply of slaves from these areas to the Mediterranean
countries dried up (the Turks enslaving the young men for their own army and
navy and the women for the rulers’ harems.) The only area open for expansive
European energies was the Atlantic and the
African continent. The Portuguese, in quest of gold and an alternative way to
get to the East now that the Turks had blocked the land route, made voyages of
exploration down the African coast to Cape Verde. There they discovered
the enormous black slave markets of Senegambia.
To their amazement they found that twenty-five slaves could be bought in
exchange for one horse. 36 What need to put their lives at risk in
military raids to snatch Arabs from the North African coast when they could buy
black slaves peacefully for a song? So slave-trading soon replaced
slave-raiding. When the Portuguese and Spaniards opened up their colonies in
the New World and meddling monks like
Bartolomé de las Casas tried to stop
them enslaving the local Indians, they had their solution. Buy the cheap,
ready-made slaves of Africa and ship them
across. It was an example other nations were to follow.
A belief in the
racial inferiority of Africans was not a reason ever given for the Atlantic
slave trade in its beginnings. The Portuguese and Spaniards used African slaves
in the Americas
simply because they were strong, cheap and plentiful. As the Spanish King
Ferdinand put it, he wanted to send “the best and strongest
slaves available” to work in the gold mines of Hispaniola.37
Blacks were far stronger and more resistant both to tropical diseases and to
European diseases than the Caribbean natives. The latter soon began to decline
drastically in numbers from disease and overwork, and it was reported to King
Ferdinand as early as 1511 that the work of one black slave was equal to that
of four Indians. 38 Africans were also easier to get hold of than
Arabs. They could be bought cheaply in the slave markets of Senegambia,
whereas Arabs (whose mixed-race colonial descendants largely controlled the
West African slave markets) could only be captured by military raids, as
Muslims did not sell Muslims. All these reasons explain why Africans became the
slaves of choice and edged out the slaves of other nations – Arabs, Caribbean
natives, Guanches from the Canaries and the few Greeks and Slavs that could
still be bought from the Turks. Far from opposing the traffic that now vastly
expanded, African rulers were overjoyed at the trading opportunities that
opened up. Africans became the biggest slave-merchants on earth, and probably
profited from this trade far more than any European. Some of them, such as King
Tegbesu of Dahomey, who in the mid 18th century sold about nine
thousand slaves a year for an annual profit of £250,000, earned incomes far in
excess of any Liverpool slave merchant or English landowner of the time.39
Slavery was a deep-rooted custom in African society, and tribal wars, often
fuelled by hostility between Muslim and infidel tribes, kept up an endless
supply of captives. The 18th century traveller Mungo
Park estimated that three quarters of
the population of Senegambia were slaves.
Slaves were so plentiful that a thousand of them were ritually sacrificed on
the death of the King of Ashanti in 1824.40 When the British banned
the transatlantic slave trade in 1807, after a long moral campaign by Christian
reformers, African rulers protested furiously. Slavery was the basis of their
wealth and power, it was allowed by the Koran, sanctioned by universal custom.
Some even accused the British of attacking Islam in banning the trade. 41
African monarchs kept slavery and the internal slave trade going for another
eighty years – and the external trade wherever possible, since
other countries defied the British navy’s attempts to enforce the
ban on the entire world. 42
The movement to
abolish the slave trade was fuelled by Enlightenment philosophers like
Montesquieu, Rousseau and Voltaire in France
and by Christian campaigners like Wilberforce in England. The battle was long and
hard, and it was in the course of this campaign that racist attitudes came to
the fore which had not been evident at the start of the trade. The Portuguese
accounts of the arrival on their shores of the first black captives taken in a
North African slave raid in 1444 show no trace of racism. Eye-witnesses were
filled with pity for the plight of the captives. They were described as varying
from white to mulatto to very black, since the group probably included Africans
enslaved by the Arabs. Their descriptions in no way set them apart from other
human beings.43 But when in the 18th century the
Enlightenment philosophers began talking of the universal rights of man, those
with a vested interest in the African slave trade – which was by then making
fortunes in Britain and France – had to find reasons why these newly discovered
rights should not apply to African slaves. The first reason always given was
that the condition of slaves in Africa was infinitely worse and more cruel than
when they were bought by European masters in the Americas and given the chance
of “advancement”, as one observer put it, “under the benign influence of the
law and Gospel”.44 It was claimed that the slaves being sold were
either captives taken in tribal wars or condemned criminals, who, if not bought
by Europeans, would either remain slaves in Africa or else be killed. Some
British traders refused to take slaves they suspected of having simply been
kidnapped locally (though they seldom inquired how those from the interior had
been obtained.)45 When cases occurred of African princes or noblemen
being sold into slavery by treachery, Europeans reacted with indignation. Such
was the theme of a popular story by Aphra Behn, Oroonoko or the History of the Royal Slave, which was turned into a
hit play, at which English audiences wept over the plight of an African prince
sold into slavery. Nor was this mere fantasy. In one actual case in 1752 two
young African princes transported as slaves to America by treachery were set
free and taken to England as guests of the President of the Board of Trade,
Lord Halifax. He educated them and introduced them into London society, where, ironically, they got
to see a performance of Oroonoko and
wept over it as well.46 Their acceptance by English aristocratic
society seems to confirm that racial prejudice was not a major factor in the
institution of slavery. Slaves were considered a class, not a race, and
Africans who did not belong to this class were accepted as equals. They were,
however, seen as physically unattractive. This appears from the Russian poet
Pushkin’s story of his Ethiopian great-grandfather’s adventures at Peter the
Great’s court, where the Tsar’s proposal to marry him off to a young
aristocratic girl causes her to faint with shock. The poignancy of the story is
that the girl’s father admires the African for his character, but does not want
descendants that look like him. 47 This physical unattractiveness of
Africans to 18th century Europeans began to enter the moral debate
over whether slavery should exist. As the institution of slavery began to be
condemned as not only inhuman but a legal impossibility by French Enlightenment
philosophers (a condemnation already voiced by Pope Urban VIII and repeated by
Benedict XIV in 1741), the difference in appearance of Africans began to be
used by the pro-slavery lobby as a justification for making them exceptions to
the emerging notion of universal human rights.48 Montesquieu
satirizes the pro-slavery argument with biting irony in 1748, after mentioning
Africans’ colour, the different shape of their noses, and their preference for
glass beads over gold: “it is impossible for us to suppose these creatures are
men, because if one were to allow them to be so, a suspicion would follow that
we are not ourselves Christian.”49 Some have seized on this remark
as evidence that Africans were not generally considered human beings at the
time, but this is false. The very effectiveness of the satire lies in the
outrageousness of the statement, just as the effectiveness of Swift’s “A Modest
Proposal”, in which he suggests that Irish babies should be eaten, lies in the
outrageousness of the idea. If either statement had been considered acceptable
by the average reader, the whole satirical point would have been lost.
But it is clear
that the belief that Africans, while obviously human, were an inferior race of
humans and somehow fit for slavery – a belief which had never been a factor at
the beginning of the slave trade to the Americas, when slaves of all races
were still widely used – was openly voiced in the bitter debate about ending
it. In fact we have the most evidence of racist attitudes from the vigorous
arguments of the abolitionists against them, as when Charles James Fox asked
dramatically in the House of Commons in 1791: “Why, might there not be men in
Africa of as fine feelings as ourselves, of as enlarged understandings, and as
manly in their minds as any of us?”50 This suggests that some in his
audience might have needed convincing on this point. It also makes clear how
the debate over the morality of slavery had shifted from the legal basis of the
institution itself to an argument about the nature of Africans and whether or
not they were the equals of Europeans. But a belief in Africans’ intellectual
inferiority, which Thomas Jefferson expressed, was not incompatible with
believing that slavery was an abomination that should be ended. Jefferson
called slavery a “violation of human rights” and as president oversaw a bill
banning the importation of slaves in 1807, at the same time as Britain’s wider
and much better enforced abolition.51 He did not manage to abolish
slavery itself, but he tried repeatedly to do so, and he believed that the
intellectual inferiority he attributed to Africans in no way lessened their
rights. (“Whatever be their degree of talent it is no measure of their rights.
Because Sir Isaac Newton was superior to others in understanding, he was not
therefore lord of the persons or property of others.”52) But this
defence of equality of rights while asserting a racial inferiority of intellect
has not endeared him to the modern American left. Jefferson
has thus come in for criticism among them for his “ambiguous” views on slavery,
even though he was seen by later abolitionists such as John Quincy Adams as
their inspiration. Jefferson’s attempts to secure abolition began as early as
1769 in the Virginia
legislature, and he blamed the British government for vetoing this and other
abolition bills in all the colonies. In the Declaration of Independence, which
he wrote, he blamed King George III, among other crimes, for “violating (human
nature’s) most sacred rights of life and liberty in the persons of a distant
people which never offended him, captivating and carrying them into slavery in
another hemisphere .… and suppressing every legislative attempt to prohibit or
restrain an execrable commerce.”53 Paradoxically, English law had
taken a different position from that of crown policy in the American colonies.
The great jurist Blackstone had declared in the 1760’s that slavery was illegal
in England, and that “a slave or negro, the moment he lands in England, falls
under the protection of the laws and … becomes … a freeman” – an opinion
confirmed by the courts in a test case in 1772.54 But slavery, while
it was an alien institution in England, was a fact of everyday life in America,
and especially Virginia, whose production depended on it entirely. The problem
for Southerners like Jefferson was what to do
with the large numbers of black slaves in their states once they were freed. It
is clear even from Blackstone’s remark just quoted (“a slave or negro”) that by
this time blacks and slavery had become indissolubly associated in the minds of
most Westerners, as the popular memory of the white slaves of the European past
(and of the universality of the institution) was gradually lost. The myth had
already taken root that Africans had been enslaved because of their race,
instead of simply happening to be the last representatives in the Western world
of a legal category of persons which had, only two centuries before, included
every race and skin colour on the planet (as it still did among the Turks and
Arabs.)
The British, with
the zeal of the converted, shifted without missing a beat in 1807 from being Europe’s leading slave traders (a
position taken over from the Portuguese) to being self-righteous crusaders
against the slave trade (much to the astonishment and suspicion of other
nations.) They soon made slaving a capital offence, and used their naval
dominance to arrest any ship they found carrying slaves, or even equipped with
shackles. Other nations, including the USA,
were furious at Britain’s
high-handed actions and refused to accept the British navy’s right to search
all ships. Though the Americans had also banned the importation of slaves in
1807, they did little to stop their ships engaging in the trade to other
countries. There were endless diplomatic quarrels over which ships the British
were allowed to intercept, and agreements had to be negotiated with each
country. Despite these obstacles, the Royal Navy West Africa Squadron freed
about 160,000 slaves from about 1300 captured ships over a sixty year period to
1870. This number represents about 8 per cent of the total of two million
slaves shipped during that time (though they may have deterred a lot more of
the trade by increasing its risks.) 55 Britain abolished slavery
itself throughout the empire in 1833, and began pushing for a worldwide ban.
British diplomatic pressure gradually persuaded other nations to go along with
the ban on the slave trade and to join in the naval patrols to catch slavers.
The last to come round were the Spaniards. Cuba
and Brazil
remained the biggest destinations to the bitter end (Brazil abolished slavery
in 1888, about the same time as the Turks, whose slaves were still mostly
white, mainly Georgians.) The British also continued to put pressure on the
African princes to abolish the slave trade, but with less success. King Gezo of
Dahomey
(a descendant of Tegbesu) replied to British requests in 1840 to give up the
slave trade and switch to palm oil with an eloquent defence of what the British
now considered an abomination:
The slave trade has been the
ruling principle of my people. It is the source of their glory and their
wealth. Their songs celebrate their victories and the mother lulls the child to
sleep with notes of triumph over an enemy reduced to slavery. Can I, by signing
... a treaty, change the sentiments of a whole people? 56
Faced with a cultural
practice this deep-rooted, peaceful persuasion was clearly not going to work. A
British naval blockade of the coast had more success in urging the advantages
of palm oil. But it was only when
European colonial rule was gradually imposed on most of Africa
starting in the 1880’s (partly as a result of an anti-slavery campaign by
British missionaries like Livingstone) that this ancient custom was finally
banned over most of the continent and gradually stamped out. However, it was
never completely eradicated in the brief sixty to seventy years of colonial
rule in most of sub-Saharan Africa.
When the main
colonial powers left Africa around 1960, both
slavery and the slave trade revived there. Scores of thousands of blacks are
still kept openly as slaves by the Muslim Afro-Arabs in Mauretania (where the Atlantic
trade first began), and slave raids by Arabs on Africans formed an integral
part of the long civil war in Sudan.57 Some post-colonial regimes
made no attempt to stop the revival of slavery. Niger only banned it again in 2003,
and nearly a million slaves are thought to be held there. Estimates of the
numbers of slaves in the world today vary, with most human rights organizations
advancing figures between twelve and twenty million. The Anti-Slavery Society,
using a very restrictive definition which appears to be limited to chattel
slavery (where legal ownership is asserted), estimates there are 2.7 million
slaves in the world, but accepts claims that there may be 27 million if a wider
definition is used, including bonded labour, pawn slavery, forced labour and
servile concubinage (all of which, curiously, fit the definition of slavery
they actually give.) 58 A
large proportion of these slaves are in Africa – ranging from
traditional girl slaves offered at the age of four to voodoo priests
(originally used for human sacrifice or as temple prostitutes, but now simply
used as sex slaves) to the boys kidnapped and trafficked from poorer countries
such as Benin and Togo for sale in oil-rich states like Nigeria and Gabon. 59
There are also child-soldier slaves, sex slaves, or domestic slaves sold by
their parents for a few dollars. The International Labour Organisation
estimates there are fifty million child-labourers in Africa.
60 An unknown number of these may, in effect, be slaves (forced to
work and prevented from running away.) An estimated two hundred thousand sex
slaves (mostly children and adolescent girls) are exported from West Africa
every year to the multi-cultural streets of Europe, a traffic controlled
largely by Nigerian women (and destined largely to satisfy the sexual needs of
single immigrant workers.) 61 That is about three times the number
of slaves exported annually from Africa across the Atlantic at the height of
the slave trade in the 18th century. 62
Of course Africa
is not the only continent from which women and children are now trafficked as
sex-slaves (the Slavs, Europe’s original
slaves, are once again paying a heavy toll.) But in West Africa what is
striking is the complicity of many mothers, who sell their children to sex
traffickers out of greed, or pressure their daughters to go to “work” in Italy so that
the whole family can buy a nice house. 63 This modern slavery
(carried on in conditions of cruelty, squalor, rape, torture and degradation
that have been thoroughly documented) is a reality just as horrific as the
slavery of the 18th century sugar plantations, and is practised on a
much larger scale. Yet the only fact registered in the mind of the average
Westerner on the subject of slavery is the conviction of eternal white guilt and
eternal African victimization in a transatlantic trade which was banned by Britain two
hundred years ago, and effectively stamped out a hundred and forty years ago.
Every TV documentary on slavery in Africa is a
breast-beating orgy of white guilt. In the journalists’ muddled minds,
the European racial prejudice that developed in the 19th century (as
ignorant soldiers were given absolute power over colonial “natives”) is projected
backwards as though it were the origin of slavery itself. It is time to ask whether the obsession with
the horrors of the slave trade of the remote past is obscuring our
understanding of slavery in the present. Because present-day African slavery
does not fit into the West-hating world-view of neo-Marxist academics and
journalists, but has its roots instead in African culture, it is being ignored
in the West. It is quite simply ideologically inconvenient for leftist
intellectuals to deal with it. Yet it is in the cavalier attitude to the
enslavement of their own children of many African mothers today that we should
perhaps look for an explanation for the overstocked slave markets of Senegambia five hundred years ago. The same tales of
casual betrayal into the hands of traffickers by greedy relatives and
neighbours can be found then as now. Africans are not going to be able to deal
with this scourge today until they face the truth of their own past, and shake
off the paralysing delusion of being history’s martyrs, the eternal
innocent victims of other nations. And this delusion is constantly fed by the
breast-beating orgies of guilt of Western academics, politicians and
journalists. These neo-Marxist myths are
a serious obstacle to combating the continuing evil of African slavery in the
present. The servile, grovelling apology to Africans for slavery by the French
President Jacques Chirac on 10 May 2006 is only the latest piece of ignorant
Western pandering to the African victim complex. There were certainly a lot
more black slaves in the streets of Paris listening to that ludicrous apology
than there ever were in the 18th century, but who gave a thought for
them? They are in the brothels run by West African women traffickers, or
working for the drug gangs who have brought them in as “refugees”, or working
for African and Arab diplomats in the embassies in the fashionable quarters of Paris. To apologize for
slavery to a race which from the 16th to the 19th century
probably held more people in chattel slavery than the rest of mankind put
together, and made more money out of selling slaves than any other race in
history, is not simply absurd – it is grotesque. All Chirac has done is
reinforce the general ignorance of history, comfort today’s slave traders (many
of them African) and intensify the victim-complex that paralyses not only African
elites, but above all the blacks of America, Britain and France, most of whom
have come to believe in the historic martyrdom of all Africans as the very
basis of their sense of identity.
11)
SELF-CRITICISM BECOMES SELF-HATRED
That the nations
who were the first ever to abolish slavery should feel obliged to apologize for
this practice to those peoples who resisted abolition most tenaciously and kept
the institution going for longest is typical of the abject moral masochism into
which Europeans have fallen in the past thirty years. The origin of this
attitude is in fact a peculiar form of neo-Marxist racism: a belief that
Europeans, with their superior intellects, ought to have known better. The fact
that Europeans (alone of all peoples on earth) arrived sometime in the 18th
century at the notion that the universal, time-honoured practice of slavery
might be morally wrong, is used as an argument that they ought to have known
this earlier still. In other words the moral superiority over other peoples
arrived at by Europeans in the Enlightenment is believed by the neo-Marxist to
have been inherent in Europeans from the beginning of time – which makes their
participation in universal crimes and cruelties more heinous than that of other
peoples. The truth is Europeans were just as cruel, ignorant and unjust as
anybody else until Enlightenment thinkers made a superhuman effort to raise
them above the general level of barbarism. It is racism – a belief in the
inherent moral superiority of the European race and an exaggerated view of its
intellectual advances over others – which makes Western neo-Marxists heap upon
their own race a special guilt for universal human cruelties such as slavery.
To this may be added a peculiar leftist belief that the Christian religion
(which the left never ceases to vilify as a jumble of bigotry, superstition,
religious wars, and auto-da-fés) ought to have taught Europeans the “great law
of love” (as Tolstoy calls it.) The leftists then go into paroxysms of
self-flagellation because it didn’t (at least until Montesquieu and Wilberforce
came along in the 18th century.) There is, in short, no greater
manifestation of sheer ignorance, intellectual muddle and moral confusion than
the abject guilt-complex, the condemnation of their own race as morally worse
than all others, which has afflicted Western leftists on the subject of slavery
for the past forty years.
Exactly the same
grotesque sense of guilt afflicts the modern university-educated (or
half-educated) Westerner on the subject of colonialism. The neo-Marxist leftist
sees the imperialist impulse of Europeans to colonize other parts of the world
as a crime unique in history, an unprecedented urge to conquer and dominate
others, proof of some peculiar vice of our race (“the white race
alone … eradicates autonomous civilizations”, as the high
priestess of the self-flagellators, Susan Sontag, put it at the start of her
career of anti-white racism.) Yet the
imperialist impulse is probably the single most common urge that has ever taken
hold of any powerful ruler of any race since history began. From Alexander the
Great to Ghengis Khan to Suleyman the Magnificent, the conqueror’s urge appears
to have been universal (and its destructive fury was far more manifest among
the Mongol armies than the European colonizers.) The European nations arose out
of the ruins of the Roman empire, which had dominated Europe and the
Mediterranean world for five hundred years, and they looked back on it as a high point of history they
would never reach again. The vestiges of Roman civilization provided the
emerging European nations with their systems of law, political administration,
architecture, engineering, road-building, as well as their literature, art,
science, philosophy and half their languages. Despite the fact that the Roman empire had conquered other European peoples in
rivers of blood, it was revered by their descendants as the sacred wellspring
of civilization. European nations were thus programmed from their own traumatic
birth to see empire and civilization as almost synonymous. The eastern half of
the Roman empire continued as a major centre of art and culture for another
thousand years until in 1453 its capital, Constantinople,
fell to the Turks. This new rising power, the Ottoman Turkish empire, then
conquered most of eastern Europe and ruled it for four hundred years. Even
before that Russia and Ukraine had
been subjugated and colonized by another Asiatic invader, the Mongols. Spain had been ruled for nearly seven hundred
years by an Arab empire, finally driven back across the Mediterranean in the
year of Columbus’
voyage. Meanwhile, within Europe itself, nations had been forged into
successive empires, including the Holy Roman (Germanic) Empire founded by
Charlemagne, the Angevin empire of Henry II of England
over half his native France,
and the vast kingdoms of Hungary
and Poland-Lithuania, by far the largest country in Europe
for the last half of the 15th century. In short, the history of Europe was nothing if not a history of empires, either of
Asian peoples over Europeans, or Europeans over one another. Above all the
education of Europeans from the 14th century onwards in classical
philosophy, literature and history meant that their whole frame of political
and historical references was the world of Greece
and Rome, both
of whose histories were played out, to differing degrees, in terms of conquest,
empire and colonization. Roman history, in particular, taught them to see
empire as the very foundation of civilization, and the imperial drive as a
civilizing mission (as it was to every Roman historian.) Modern Europeans did
not therefore invent the notion of empire; they inherited it from the past not
only of their own culture, but of every culture they had ever been in contact
with, including the Asiatic cultures that had ruled vast swathes of Europe for
centuries.
Yet despite this
inherited conviction of the civilizing mission of empire, in spite of seeing
the history of the world as nothing but the rise and fall of successive
empires, Europeans set out on their own first enterprise of empire-building
beyond their shores amid a chorus of protest and moral condemnation from their
own intellectual class. The first great imperial adventure of Europeans outside
their own sphere, the Spanish conquest of the Caribbean islands, Mexico and Peru, was the object of passionate
moral denunciations by the priests and Dominican monks that accompanied the
Conquistadors. Antonio de Montesinos, Bartolomeo de Olmedo (Cortez’s chaplain)
and Bartolomé de las Casas denounced the cruelty of the Spanish conquest and
the injustice of the treatment of the Indians with a vehemence that still
shocks today. Montesinos preached to the Conquistadors on Christmas day 1511 in
Hispaniola a sermon that still resonates
across the ages: “By what right or justice do you keep the Indians in such
horrible servitude? Are they not men? Have they not rational souls? Are you not
bound to love them as you love yourselves?” 64 It is impossible to
imagine the Nazis in Poland,
the Stalinists in Ukraine,
the Japanese in Nanking, or the Maoists in Tibet sitting and listening to a
sermon of this kind without shooting the priest on the spot. That the
Conquistadors tolerated this protest is the measure of the moral superiority of
the 16th century over the 20th. De las Casas’ Brief Report on the Destruction of the
Indies, or Tears of the Indians of 1552, which became a best-seller all
over Europe, was the first great document in the whole tradition of human
rights advocacy, anti-imperialism and anti-racism. It founded the so-called
“Black Legend” about (probably exaggerated) Spanish atrocities in the New
World, which Spain’s
enemies would eagerly seize upon. 65 These accusations were taken up
later in the 16th century by the Frenchman Montaigne in a ringing moral
denunciation of European aggression against the New World:
“So many cities destroyed, so many nations exterminated, so many millions put
to the sword … to obtain pearls and pepper!” 66 A new moral
perspective which condemned imperialistic conquest as a genocide of other
peoples and a destruction of other cultures thus came at once to trouble the
ambitions of the new European empire-builders on their very first expeditions.
A tradition was launched of exaggerating the crimes of the European conquerors
and exalting the innocence of the victim peoples which has lasted until this
day. From De Las Casas’ and Montaigne’s eloquent denunciations of
the Spanish Conquistadors, to Samuel Johnson’s scathing condemnation of
the colonization of America,
or Rousseau’s idealization of the noble savage, Europe’s intellectuals
attacked the whole process by which Europe was
inflicting its civilization upon the world. No other empire was ever assailed
in this way by its own thinkers from its very inception. Even Tacitus, while he
admired many aspects of the culture of the Germans and the Celts, saw it as Rome’s divine mission
to civilize the barbarians, and rejoiced in the short-sightedness of these
nations in accepting the loss of their own freedom for the sake of warm baths
and efficient plumbing. This unquestioning acceptance of their divine mission
to rule was characteristic of all previous conquering civilizations, including
the Arabs and the Turks. But it was countered in the case of European empires
by a passionate and sustained opposition voice, which identified not with one
civilization as the carrier of human progress, but with all cultures as
different expressions of the human spirit. No other civilization has so eagerly
and admiringly studied the cultures of the colonized. This dissident note
swelled to become a critical, jarring accompaniment of the entire history of
Western imperialism. Even though it was counteracted in the Victorian period by
a noisy enthusiasm for bearing “the white man’s burden” (a product of Darwinist
ideas of backward races as well as a humanitarian concern to stamp out
primitive practices such as slavery),
the undercurrent of opposition to colonialism eventually prevailed. It finally
achieved the voluntary dismantling of European empires at the very apex of
their power, and brought about the permanent discrediting of imperialism. It is
paradoxically this dissident voice, this self-criticism, the mark of a higher
sense of humanity and a pluralistic vision of the world, which, at the very
moment of its triumph, turned into the strident and fanatical extremism of
anti-Western self-hatred which Susan Sontag expressed so succinctly in the
formula: “The white race is the cancer of human history.”
The very success
of the new universal humanism of Western civilization in achieving the
dismantling of its empires led in its universities to a crisis of guilt and
breast-beating over the existence of those empires in the first place. Instead
of congratulating itself on ending colonialism, the West began to flagellate
itself for having engaged in it. It somehow forgot that imperialism had been
the universal behaviour of powerful nations since the beginning of time. It
suddenly saw itself not as the last (relatively benign) practitioner of empire
(finally bringing it to an end) but as
the wicked inventor of it. This soon created a reverse image of the notion of
the “civilizing mission” cherished by our naive Victorian forefathers.
Leftist academics now saw the West as an evil empire, which had embarked for
centuries on a dark mission of diabolical destruction and genocide. According
to this view (still current on the academic left today), the imperialistic
drive of the Western European nations to conquer and colonize large parts of
the world over the last four centuries was an enormous, unmitigated crime. The
notion that European imperialism brought anything good, that it was the
purveyor of a more technically advanced civilization, was rejected as an
expression of racist contempt for non-European cultures. The very belief in
progress which the nineteenth century took for granted – the idea that it
is better to have printing presses, clocks, railways, post offices,
electricity, running water, modern medicine, radio and telephones, than not to – was viewed as
nothing but Eurocentric cultural prejudice. The idea that the civilization that
introduced these aspects of modern life to other peoples may have been doing
them a favour (that very few of them would now like to be without these
amenities) was seen as a smug, racist justification of tyranny, cultural
destruction and genocide. The notion that the West introduced any higher
political or humane values – that the practice of good government, the rule of
law, impartial law-courts, mass education, religious tolerance, and the
suppression of such picturesque local customs as slavery, torture,
widow-burning, foot-binding, child-marriages, not to speak of human sacrifice
and cannibalism, brought positive benefits to the peoples of other continents – was now regarded
as the height of racism and hypocrisy. In fact it was a racist calumny of the
gentle, peace-loving, sex-egalitarian cultures of all non-Western peoples,
since it was us (we now learned) who were solely responsible for all the evils
and miseries of the planet. Every cruel dictatorship, every starving peasant,
every feudal exaction, every savage custom, every murderous tribal enmity was
the product of Western imperialism and nothing else. Without Western
colonialism it appears that humanity would have lived forever in a universal
golden age of peace and prosperity. Such was the ruin we had brought upon the
planet that we had to spend the rest of history beating our breasts every time
we passed a person of another race in the street. And of course the first form
our penance must take was to allow other races into Western countries in
unlimited numbers in order to put an end to our wicked Eurocentric culture as
fast as possible.
What is
astonishing for a view of largely academic origin was the colossal ignorance of
history it was based on, and the lack of any perspective as to what kinds of
behaviour were typical of all dominant nations in the past. It is as though the
conquering urges of all mankind were to be imputed solely to the European race,
because its dominance was the most recent. Yet a glance at the record would
have shown that more Europeans have spent more of their history being oppressed
by other races than doing any oppressing. More than half the European
population (including the Russians, Ukrainians, Serbs, Slovenes, Croats,
Greeks, Hungarians, Romanians, Spaniards, Portuguese) spent between two and six
hundred of the last twelve hundred years under the brutal colonial rule of
Asian or North African conquerors – a rather longer period than
the more recent reign of the Western empires over other races. The only unique
thing about the European race is that it had no sooner got the upper hand and
begun colonizing other peoples in its turn, than it called the whole process
into question on moral grounds and gradually put an end to it.
This
took nearly two hundred years in the case of the non-Western nation ruled for
the longest by Britain, India, and sixty to eighty years in most parts of
Africa – though of course the Americas and Australasia, where
millions of European settlers had gone to live, founded independent nations,
and become the majority in those countries, could hardly be evacuated. Much of
the cultural damage of colonialism could not be undone, but its extent was
largely a reflection of the enormous gap in cultures and development. It was
not easy to integrate the modern and the medieval, let alone the Neolithic. The
Moghul empire probably destroyed as much of the culture it found in India
as the British did; but it replaced it by something that looked superficially
similar, so we do not see it as a cultural vandalism nearly as radical as that
of the West. But this cultural transformation was often embraced by the natives
as progress, even if the manner of it was resented as oppression. To pretend
that pre-modern cultures could have survived intact as a living anthropological
museum while other parts of the world moved into another era of history is
simply unrealistic. Humanity is one, and parts of it cannot be shut off forever
from the technological advances made by the rest, and the changes these bring,
for good or ill. Once the Maori or the American Indians knew that muskets
existed, they could not be prevented from obtaining muskets, which then did
enormous damage within their traditional warrior cultures. Nor could they be
sheltered from illnesses brought from outside to which they had no resistance.
The Atlantic slave trade made the coastal kingdoms of West
Africa rich and powerful, and increased their domination over
those in the interior, but any form of foreign trade which gave them muskets
would have done the same. Whether the slaughter of their tribal wars would have
been greater or less without the possibility of selling their captives is
impossible to say. All races of mankind are part of the same common story, and
cultural catastrophe to one or another is merely the tragic result of peoples
in different time warps sharing the same planet. Yet whatever its
destructiveness in the Caribbean, Mexico and Peru, nothing in the last two
hundred years of Western colonialism remotely compares with the cultural
mayhem, the “eradication of autonomous civilizations”, the mass
exterminations, inflicted by the communist empires of Russia and China – regimes admired
and defended by leftists like Susan Sontag, even as they murdered more human
beings than all other tyrannies of recorded history put together.
Europeans
cannot escape the dark shadow of the common past of the human race, or their
own part in the universal evils of tyranny, slavery and oppression. Anyone who
reflects on the past of mankind as a whole can only shudder at the level of
barbarism we have all emerged from. But to denounce the European race as the
principal perpetrator of what were in fact universal evils, which it alone
finally brought to an end, is simply perverse. No such denunciation would even
be conceivable without the concepts of liberty and human rights that Europeans
developed. The paradox is that in making moral progress European civilization
condemned its own past by the moral standards it then established. This has
inspired a peculiar and perverse indignation at the fact that it did not
observe those standards earlier. Instead of satisfaction that our ancestors
took a step forward in civilized values, there is moral outrage at the state
they were in before they took that step.
Instead of seeing the abolition of slavery as an achievement, the modern
leftist sees it only as a terrible indictment of what went before. This is a
perverse and deliberate amnesia as to what conditions in the past were like,
and how universal cruelty was in every race that ever lived. It took great
power of mind to break a pattern of behaviour as old as time, especially when
it was extremely profitable and convenient. No other race in history ever
abolished slavery, or even had the slightest doubt about its morality. If there
had been no European colonialism, we can be fairly sure that all of Africa,
North and South America, Polynesia, and much of Asia
would still have slavery on a massive scale even today. The Indians would
probably still be burning widows, the Chinese binding girls’ feet and the
Africans and Aztecs practising mass human sacrifice. And these things would
still be happening because the very notion that customs (and even morality)
should change with the times depends on the European idea of progress, which
would never have got outside Europe’s borders without
the expansion of its empires world-wide.
12)
THE MYTH OF GENOCIDE IN AMERICA
But one
consequence of colonialism that could not be undone was where settlers
gradually displaced indigenous peoples, leading to their decline in numbers,
the loss of their culture, and in some cases to the extinction of particular
tribes. This circumstance has given rise to the most intense fits of
self-flagellation among American leftist intellectuals. In the 1967 essay in
which Susan Sontag proclaims that “the white race is the cancer
of human history” she justifies her racial self-hatred by the
statement that America
was “founded upon a genocide” – the “extermination” of the
Amerindians. That these people have not in fact been exterminated, and today
number about three million in the USA, which is the average of the
various estimates of their numbers when the Europeans first arrived, appears to
have escaped her attention. True, their numbers fell drastically by the end of
the 19th century, before rising again, but this fall was largely due
to the ravages of new diseases such as smallpox, influenza, measles, and
whooping cough, to which they had no resistance (and for which medicine till
the 20th century had no cure.) 67 An even more drastic
decline happened over the 19th century to the Maori of New Zealand,
even though we know that the colonial wars killed only a few hundred (a
fraction of the numbers killed by their own tribal wars.) Disease, not
extermination by white settlers, was responsible for most of the decline in
American Indian numbers, just as it was for the Maori. And we can hardly regard
disease as an act of genocide, or Europeans would bear a considerable grudge
against the Asians who gave us the Bubonic plague. It is undeniable that the
American Indians were displaced, their land stolen, their culture corrupted,
their tribal organization shattered, their religion discredited, their military
power broken, and their pride humiliated. Exactly the same could be said of the
Ancient Britons or Welsh when the Angles and Saxons invaded Britain. And
the Ancient Britons undoubtedly inflicted the same cultural mayhem on the
pre-Celtic peoples whom they conquered over a thousand years earlier. Does Ms
Sontag seriously believe that the American Indian tribes acted any differently
towards the tribes that preceded them in the occupation of their regions of America? If
there was one constant in the lives of American Indians, it was war. The Sioux,
it has been noted by one of their modern spokesmen, were at war with nineteen
different tribes during one twenty-year period in the 19th century.68
It is highly likely that even after the Europeans arrived in America, far more Indians died in
inter-tribal warfare than at the hands of the whites.
But of course it
is the European settlement itself which for leftists like Sontag constituted
genocide. She defines this genocide as “the unquestioned
assumption of the right of white Europeans to exterminate a resident,
technologically backward coloured population in order to take over the
continent.”69 We have already commented on the hysteria of
the word “exterminate” for a people thriving
today, and living longer and more comfortable lives than their forebears when
Sir Walter Raleigh hove into view. Nor is it clear that European settlers
generally assumed a “right” to exterminate the Indians
(though warfare at the time had an exterminationist character on all sides.)
Relations between the English settlers and the
Indians were for some years quite amicable (the settlers could not have
survived otherwise), and only quarrels over territory led to war. When it did
so, the settlers’ aim was generally to defend or expand their
territory, or increase their security, not to exterminate the Indians. In such
a vast continent it was assumed there would always be room for all. But the huge numbers of immigrants who
arrived over the next two centuries and began moving westwards soon threatened
the livelihood of the natives and provoked more and more clashes, leading to
massacres on both sides. Indian atrocity stories abounded, and despite
exaggerations they were based on a very real cultural custom of torturing
prisoners to death. Exterminationist language was sometimes used by generals
fighting Indian wars in the late 19th century, but it was not
generally approved. By then American writers like James Fenimore Cooper had
produced a far more favourable, not to say romanticized, popular image of the
noble Indian. Such massacres as occurred were either by maverick settlers, or
by troops that lost control. There is simply no evidence of any official
Nazi-style policy of extermination.70 As for “technologically
backward”, in the early years the natives were far more
successful farmers than the settlers were (they had to give the latter food to
help them survive.) In military technology the Indians were very quickly on an
equal footing, equipped with the latest flintlock muskets, through trade with
the English settlers or the French, and they became excellent shots. There were
no battles in America of Maxim guns against spears, and the Indians were for a
long time confident of their military superiority. In the first major war, King
Philip’s War in 1675, they very nearly exterminated the settlers. As for the
notion of the inalienable rights of “a resident population” of some three
million people to monopolize the third largest continent on earth till the end
of time, it shows a curiously absolute concept of territorial ownership. We are
told today that no European country, no matter how overcrowded, has the right
to close its borders against the hordes of immigrants clamouring to get in, and
yet apparently three million Amerindians had the exclusive right to a huge
continent for the duration of the planet’s existence. How does Ms
Sontag imagine this territorial right of the Indian tribes was established?
Surely it was established by conquest? Surely the tribes that were on the Atlantic
coast when the whites arrived had seized that territory from others before
them, and those tribes from others before them, until we get all the way back
to the first hardy trekkers from Siberia. Why
did whites not have the right to do the same? Did their skin colour, or perhaps
their technological superiority, or their literate civilization impose an
obligation on them to stay cooped within their narrow native lands while a
handful of “technologically backward coloured people” monopolized the
third largest and emptiest continent of the planet? To put it in simple
Brechtian terms, who is making better use of the land now called America: the
three hundred million people of all racial origins now living there in peace,
freedom and plenty? Or the three million “technologically backward
coloured people”, scratching a precarious living from hunting and
subsistence farming, and making tribal warfare to the point of mutual
extermination? In whose hands would we prefer it to be today?
The losers of
history are entitled to their resentments. As a descendant of two loser
nations, the Irish and the Scots, I may in self-indulgent moments resent the
more powerful neighbouring people that colonized my ancestors’ lands, made
their lives a misery and drove my grandparents and great-grandparents to
emigrate to the ends of the earth. But to elevate this resentment into a moral
indictment is something else. To pretend that the English did anything to us
that we had not already done to others before us is pathetic self-deception. To
pretend that the resentment of history’s losers constitutes a
position of moral superiority from which judgement may be passed on the victors
is ignorant, self-pitying nonsense. If we had won we would have done the same
to them. And you would all be speaking Gaelic. And if the American Indians had
pushed the settlers back into the sea, Ms Sontag would have gone on speaking
Lithuanian (or eventually, Russian, Polish or perhaps German.) And the third
largest continent on earth would still be inhabited by a mere three million “technologically
backward” buffalo hunters and subsistence farmers. How would
the world be better?
Of course this
argument is not a justification of the right of conquest, or fascist
international ethics, in our own age. The era of conquest is over. Indeed, the
definition of fascism is precisely the attempt to return to the conqueror’s ethos which all
nations accepted until the end of the 19th century, but which new
moral attitudes and notions of international law rejected in the 20th
century. Mussolini could not understand why the British condemned what he was
doing to Abyssinia, when they had done the same to Sudan forty years earlier. It was
the forty years that made the difference. The world had changed, and fascism
was the refusal to accept the change. It was a failure to understand that
morality and internationally accepted standards of behaviour evolve with time.
What was generally acceptable to world opinion in the 1890’s was not in the
1930’s. (Israel
has something of the same time problem, when it tries to justify its expansion
on the pattern of 19th century settler states, or Bismarck- ian
border changes, in violation of 20th century international law.) But
modern leftists like Sontag are making a mistake analogous to fascism. Just as
fascists tried to apply 19th century morality in the 20th
century, Sontag tries to apply late 20th century morality to the 17th
and 18th centuries. But behaviour we would consider morally
unacceptable today was considered normal then. Every territory was up for grabs
and nations took what they could. The accepted practices of the times must
surely determine our moral judgements – at least in part. At the
end of Othello Shakespeare has the
villain Iago led away to be tortured to death, with evident approval: does this
make Shakespeare a sadistic monster? Would we put him in the same moral
category as somebody who advocated torturing criminals to death today? No,
because the times have changed. And nor do we put the white settlers flocking
to America in the 17th century, and carving out colonies for
themselves in a vast, sparsely inhabited continent, in the same moral category
as the Fascists invading Abyssinia or the Nazis invading Poland. It is the age
that makes the difference to morality. And that is why, when we find in the
writers of the past, such as Montaigne in the late 16th century,
ringing denunciations of European acts of colonial aggression (such as that of
the Spanish Conquistadors), we treasure them, not because they objectively
classify these acts as evil in their own time, but because they show the first
signs of the evolving moral conscience that would lead us to condemn such acts
as evil today.
13)
JUDGING THE PAST: IS MORAL LAW TIMELESS?
The problem with
moral indictments of the past – such as the sweeping condemnation of European
colonialism which is now obligatory in every Western university and school – is
to decide: what are the moral standards by which the past is to be judged? Is
the past to be judged by our standards or by its own? And if the latter, how do
we establish what the standards of the past were?
This takes us
deep into the complex question of whether morality is eternal and universal or
time-bound and culture-bound. Thinkers in the ancient world brooded a great
deal over this problem. Aristotle distinguished natural justice and legal
justice, and thought that the former was universal and could be known by
everyone, whereas the latter varied with the laws of each state. The great
Roman jurist Gaius reflected this general viewpoint when he stated in the
preamble to his Institutes that the
law has two sources: the laws of states and the universal moral law common to
all peoples. But he did not say how they were related. Other classical thinkers
sought to define this relationship, and generally ended by giving the primacy
to one or the other. Cicero, both a lawyer and a philosopher, was the most
eloquent proponent of the view that primacy must be given to natural moral law,
which is timeless and common to all human beings:
True law is
right reason in agreement with nature .… We cannot be freed from its
obligations by Senate or People, and we need not look outside ourselves for an
expounder or interpreter of it. And there will not be different laws at Rome
and at Athens, or different laws now and in the future, but one eternal and
unchangeable law will be valid for all nations and for all times. (De Republica, Book III)
This is a text of
extraordinary resonance – from the claim of Muslim Shar’ia law to be universal
and timeless, to St Thomas Aquinas’ notion that the natural moral law has been
revealed by God to every human soul, or to the Protestant gloss on this,
emphasising individual conscience as the only guide to what is right. Closer to
our own day, it is the principle by which the Allies judged at Nuremberg that Nazi functionaries had no
right to obey tyrannical laws, even if they were the law of the land – in
short, that governments (“Senate or People”) could not free us from the
obligation to follow our moral conscience, which is a universal law. More
recently German courts have decreed that East German border guards had no right
to apply the shoot-to-kill laws of their country against escapers to the West,
because these laws were clearly immoral. Martin Luther King cited the same
classical sources when he claimed that law must be in conformity with natural
justice or it was not valid. But if Cicero is
right then how do we deal with the fact that there are indeed different
concepts of morality and justice “at Rome and at
Athens”? Is it
true that our own moral conscience constitutes a universal moral law which is
the same “for all nations and for all times”? Would Cicero have shared the same moral view of
homosexuality as Aquinas, or the same view of slavery as us? What of cultures
where cannibalism was accepted, or widow-burning, or honour killings? What of
the universal acceptance of torture, as well as slavery, until Europeans
abolished both of them at the start of the 19th century? What of the
extreme variation in sexual codes, where homosexual acts or adultery or
abortion have been capital offences in certain ages and countries, and have
been legal and accepted in others? It is
quite clear that notions of moral law do vary with time and place. In which case
where does the universal moral law lie, and who is to define it? How do we know
what it is?
Over and against Cicero’s universalist
position, there is the opposite view, that of cultural relativism. The Germanic
invaders of Europe in the 5th
century, who ruled over a population of disparate cultures, at first accepted
pluralistic legal systems, which allowed each person to be judged by his own
tribal laws: a Frank by Frankish law, a Burgundian by Burgundian law, a
Romanized Gaul by Roman law. It involved apparent injustices, as the same crime
was punished quite differently, depending on who had committed it. But the
ancient Germans felt it was fairest to judge each person according to the laws
and moral standards of his own culture. Can we do the same with ages? Is each
age a different culture, and should we judge the actions of its inhabitants
according to their own cultural norms? But when we look at history are we
always dealing with neatly separable cultures, with clear dividing lines
between ages, or is it not often the same civilization in constant, gradual
evolution? How can we say what the moral
standard was by which actions were to be judged at any given moment of the
past? Can we fix cut-off dates, after which certain types of behaviour suddenly
became unacceptable? At what point in the 18th or 19th
century did those who supported slavery (in America
or Europe) become moral reprobates? Or those
who supported public executions? Or torture? Or duelling? Or the flogging of
convicts? Or capital punishment for theft? Or the social exclusion of “fallen
women”? Or the denial of women’s right to vote? And in what year were these
things still morally acceptable because they were the norm? At what point in
the 20th century did it become wrong to regard homosexual acts as
disgusting and criminal? Or to see abortion as murder? Or pre-marital sex as
immoral? In what year did it become morally wrong to cane a schoolboy? Is it in
practical terms possible to define the limits of a “temporal culture” – an age
with its distinct morality? And yet somehow we do feel that morality has
changed over the ages, even if precise dates for those changes are very
difficult to define.
Even more to the
point, on what grounds can we morally judge another age or culture as a whole?
Can we condemn a whole culture for things it accepted? Was the cooking and
eating of slave children practised by the Aztecs or the Maori wrong by some
universal standard? Or must we regard it as merely a cultural practice, as
acceptable in its own society as our eating of lamb chops? Was Indian
widow-burning wrong by some universal standard? Or was it merely a cultural
practice? What of Pakistani honour killings even today? If we feel obliged to
condemn these things, on what objective criteria is our judgement based? Surely
it is merely subjective, applying the standards of our culture to theirs? What
is the basis of Cicero’s
“eternal and unchangeable law, valid for all nations and all times”? Is it not
merely our law, the most recently accepted moral code? Or is it a question of
majority opinion, taking all the ages and cultures of the world together? Very
few cultures accepted cannibalism or widow-burning; though most accepted
torture and slavery. Is it majority opinion across ages which is the universal court
before which an entire age and its notions of morality can be condemned? Is
this universal law merely a sort of common denominator, obtained by looking at
the laws of the majority of all ages and cultures till now? But even so,
doesn’t such a universal moral law evolve over time? Would our concept of it
not differ greatly from that of Cicero?
Or from that of the human beings who will live two thousand years from now?
Surely we cannot accept that torture and slavery are right merely because the
majority of cultures and ages in human history (including Cicero’s) accepted them? And what of the
criminalization of abortion and homosexuality by the vast majority of cultures
that have ever existed? Is this majority view the one that must prevail? Or
since we have legalized these things, must we condemn as evil all the peoples
of the past who criminalized them? Yet can people be condemned by a moral law
they have never heard of, invented by other people far in the future? Can a
universal law include notions that have not yet been thought of? If in some
future age the killing and eating of animals is condemned as wrong, are we all
guilty for eating meat today? Or will that guilt only exist for those who
transgress that new moral code once it is generally accepted? Can we be judged
and condemned according to moral laws that do not yet exist?
It appears that neither the
relativist position of the ancient Germans, by which we would have to view
Aztec cannibalism and human sacrifice as morally right within their own
culture, nor the absolutist position of Cicero,
by which we judge all ages according to the same universal moral code, is
satisfactory. In practice we apply both a universalist approach and a
relativist one. We judge the customs of various other ages and cultures as
wrong and barbaric, while understanding and partly excusing individuals who
were merely conforming to them, without manifesting any special viciousness of
their own. In an age that accepted slavery (every age and culture till the 19th
century) we judge individuals according to their moral attitude to that
institution. We praise those who expressed their repugnance for it, as
Jefferson and Washington did, even if they could not get enough support to
abolish it. We praise Montaigne as an enlightened man for denouncing torture,
cruel executions, colonial conquests and the European sense of superiority to
other cultures, long before these things were denounced by other thinkers. In
short, we judge people in the past by whether they were on the path of progress
toward a modern sensibility, or stuck firmly in a sense of morality utterly
alien to ours. We judge them both by our standards and those of their own age,
and from this double vision we make a complex and subtle judgement, favouring
our own moral code, but allowing for the ignorance and prejudices of other
times.
What we are driven to
adopt finally is an in-between position, neither absolutist nor relativist,
which is close to the more subtle position of Aristotle. He believed that we
are not prisoners of our own cultural attitudes and time-bound laws. We can
have access to a higher natural law through philosophy, our understanding of
man’s nature and his purpose on earth. But this understanding may itself be
imperfect and subject to correction. We can thus criticize the laws of our own
age as just or unjust, but our criticism will be subject to the degree of our
own understanding of perfect justice. Human beings may thus differ in their
perception of where true justice lies, but are capable of improving that
perception. Aristotle thus holds out hope that we may come to understand true
justice, but he does not believe all human beings have instant access to it at
all times, as Cicero
seems to imply. True justice thus transcends the laws and morality of our age
but remains subject to fallible human perceptions, which may vary from one age
to another. We may never reach the
absolute of justice, but we know when we are closer to it and when we are
further away; just as we may never reach the sun, but we know that the tropics
are closer to it than the poles. Justice is a finality towards which we tend,
as all living things tend towards their fulfilment. This is the heart of
Aristotle’s philosophy and his way of solving the dichotomy of the relative and
the absolute. Among things on earth there is no perfection, but we know the
direction in which perfection lies. Just as we know when a plant is growing
well or badly, even though there is no perfect plant. The absolute exists but
we have only a relative knowledge of it, and make relative progress towards it.
We are not then lost in relativity, even though we can never reach the
absolute.
This natural law will give us a standpoint from which we may
criticize the morality of our culture or the laws of our society, but this
natural law may not be perceived the same way in all ages. We arrive then at
the conclusion that there is a universal moral law that applies within each
age, and even across different cultures in that age, but it may be perceived
differently from one age to another. The Romans engaged in the atrocious
massacre of innocent civilians in war as a reprisal for resistance. But no
other culture in their time (neither Greeks, Celts, Germans, Carthaginians,
Persians or Parthians) acted very differently, so they had no standard by which
they could judge that what they were doing might be wrong. For the Nazis to
return to these practices, knowing full well that other Western societies,
including their own of ten years before, now condemned these things, was wrong
by a standard that they knew about and were therefore still subject to. We must
therefore judge Nazi massacres of civilians more severely than Roman ones.
Their claim that they had deliberately abandoned our “decadent” moral code does
not exempt them from its force. This must lead us to question whether it is
ever justifiable to turn back the clock of moral evolution, and adopt more
cruel practices than those hitherto accepted by our age. The adoption of mass
civilian bombing in the Second World War, the French army’s use of torture in
Algeria, the recent return to capital punishment in America, and the use of
Chinese slave labour by Western manufacturing companies, are four controversial
cases where Western nations took a step backwards on the path towards more
humane moral codes. Should we condemn them all?
Can morality evolve only one way?
All these questions underline how difficult it is to judge the
actions of those in another age or culture. We can neither blindly apply the
morality of our society to theirs, nor blindly accept their morality as the
only one they can be judged by. But having seen in the last two centuries in
the West the greatest evolution in moral codes that has perhaps ever occurred – outlawing torture,
slavery, public executions, duelling, the beating of children, condemning every
form of inequality and discrimination, and legalizing and even normalizing not
only adultery and fornication but abortion and homosexual acts, which in
previous ages were capital offences – we have no choice but to accept that morality changes with the
times. This only makes more glaring the absurdity involved in using the moral
and humane standards of Western civilization today to attack Western
civilization’s past, without regard to the moral attitudes that prevailed at the
time. Those who attack our past seem to have little understanding that that
past was the stepping stone to the present, and without it our present
attitudes would never have been formed. Morally denouncing our own past is like
despising the ladder we climbed to get to where we are now. The neo-Marxist
left speaks scornfully of the Eurocentric world-view. A more serious distortion
of perspectives is a present-centred world-view, which assumes that the moral
standards of the Western present can be applied to past ages without regard for
the standards of those times. That would be like the scientists of today
scorning the ignorance of Archimedes or Aristotle for not knowing what is known
now, instead of revering (as they do) those early thinkers for taking the first
steps that led to our present scientific knowledge. “How could Thomas
Jefferson, who condemned slavery, have been a slave-owner himself?” fumes the modern
leftist. “What
a bigoted, hypocritical, racist oppressor!” That is like a modern scientist saying: “How could Aristotle
have been so ignorant as not to know about the circulation of the blood or the
equal speed of all falling objects!” In fact, the wonder is not that he knew so much less than us, but
that he knew so much more than his contemporaries. And that is also how we must
judge the people of the past in moral terms: not whether they were less humane
and enlightened than us, but whether they were more humane and enlightened than
others of their time.
14)
RE-IMAGING THE WHITE RACE AS OPPRESSOR FOR THE MULTI-CULTURAL CLASSROOM
But the modern
cult of Western self-hatred was not merely the result of a muddled conception
of morality and how it can be applied to the past. It was also a form of
political expediency. The liberalisation of immigration laws in most Western
countries in the 1960’s under the impetus of the new anti-racist ideology
meant a sudden change in the demographics of Western schools and universities.
The rise of the multiracial and multicultural society posed enormous problems
to teachers, who had to deal with an entirely new situation in the classroom.
They had to explain the new society to its own children, now in large number
non-white, and make them understand how they had got there and where they
fitted into it. This led to an attempt to reshape the very sense of identity
and history of Western nations. It is a commonplace for leftist educationalists
in both Britain and France to
assert that these countries have always been “countries of
immigration”, as if the present situation is nothing new. This
is quite simply a lie. Until the mid-19th century, immigration into both
countries was negligible. Before the internal migration of Irish people into
the mainland of the United Kingdom
after the famine of the 1840’s, and Italians and Poles into France at about the same period, there had been
no significant foreign immigration into either country for over eight hundred
years (since the arrival of the Normans
in both.) Neither the immigration into Britain of Jews fleeing Russian pogroms
in the 19th century nor of Huguenots fleeing French pogroms in the
late 16th century or aristocrats fleeing the French Revolution added
more than a few thousand souls to the population, scarcely a significant
contribution. In contrast, non-white immigration has been responsible for over
half of population growth (around six million people) in both countries over
the past fifty years. This is an unprecedented demographic change, which the
educationalists and official spokesmen simply lie about, because it is a change
imposed on the British and French peoples without democratic debate (except in
terms which criminalized one side of the debate.) The transformation of all
Western societies was so rapid in the second half of the 20th
century that whole educational programmes had to be overhauled to bring them
into line with the new realities. It became essential to teach children that
the present situation was normal and had always existed. Or if it hadn’t, that was only
because of past white wickedness in keeping out peoples of other races, who all
had a God-given right to come and live in Western countries if they wanted to,
because of the evil crimes of colonialism.
This demand for a
new conception of the nation and its past, a rewriting of history, was particularly strong in America after the Vietnam war. As
the new influx of non-white immigrants changed the demographics of American
classrooms, the teaching profession (now heavily female and feminist) became
profoundly uncomfortable with the conventional history of Western civilization.
Teachers discovered to their horror that the heroes of history (from Plato to
Shakespeare and from Voltaire to Einstein) were all white males! How could that
be the truth? It could only be the result of white patriarchal bias in telling
the tale. That version couldn’t possibly be taught to the multiracial and
multicultural classes of the 1980’s. How could these children
have white role models imposed upon them? It was as bad as giving them blonde Barbie dolls to play with. The truth
had to be rewritten for a multi-cultural audience. This became especially
important in the universities, where the policy of preferential college places
for the “racially disadvantaged” was leading to
large non-white minorities in the classroom. (It is only in America that
the grandson of an Ethiopian slave-owning cotton baron, from a country never
colonized, will receive preferential university placing, on the basis of his
colour, over the more qualified granddaughter of a white Appalachian
coal-miner, who died of lung disease at forty, leaving his family destitute.)
And so the professors came up with a new version of history in which Western
colonialism was depicted as an enormous shameful saga of injustice, racism and
oppression, which was finally being redressed by immigration and
multiculturalism. This multiculturalism was the only way the white race could
expiate its evil colonizing past, and was hence a process of redemption for the
white criminals of history. What the long-term consequences would be of
inflicting one people on another as a sort of punishment for past sins does not
seem to have worried the self-righteous multiculturalists. The whites had to be
made to accept it and to learn that their resentment of this territorial
invasion put them in the same moral category as Hitler. In the immediate it
meant that Western history and culture had to be downplayed, condemned as
inherently racist and oppressive, and space had to be made for the wonderful
cultures of the immigrants, the oppressed peoples of the earth, now at last
allowed their rightful place at the table. Above all, world history had to be
retold as the story of the oppression of humanity by one dominant race and sex – white men.
Students had to be taught that the struggle to overthrow this evil elite and
its wicked racist, sexist culture was the great moral drama of the age.
The first thing that had to be changed was therefore the
books that were going to be taught. Since all races and both sexes are equal,
they must all have made equal contributions to civilization and this must be
reflected in the works selected for study. The first task was clearly to
eliminate the racist, sexist bias whereby all the great works read, from Homer
and Plato to Goethe and Joyce, were written by Dead White Males. A more diverse
and inclusive picture of humanity had to be presented. But these Dead White
Males were not to be replaced by the great classical writers of other cultures – Confucius or Lao
Tzu or Omar Khayyam or the 11th century Japanese poetess Murasaki
Shikibu (author of the first love novel, The
Genji.) This old stuff was not relevant. Nor was it good enough to replace
them with the best living African, South American or Asian writers: Wole
Soyinka, Mario Vargas Llosa, or Jung Chang. No, these authors might well be
non-Western, but they were not anti-Western, which was what was needed. Instead
the Dead White Males must be replaced by those “committed” black, female
and Third World writers engaged in the true
struggle against the racist and sexist tyranny of Western culture. Aristotle,
Shakespeare, Locke and Voltaire must be replaced by Franz Fanon, Alice Walker,
Malcolm X and Rigoberta Menchu. The last-named Third World icon, a Guatemalan
activist, was the virtual creation of a French Marxist – the wife of
Régis Debray (remember mass-murderer Che’s companion in Bolivia?) – who ghost-wrote
her “autobiography” on the basis of interviews with her in her
fashionable Paris
apartment. This was clearly the authentic Third World
voice needed (her story suitably doctored to remove her convent school
education and her father’s large land-holdings, and to convert her into an
oppressed peasant mouthing Marxist slogans.)71 The politically
correct Nobel Prize committee, its wet finger in the air testing the wind, duly
awarded the Nobel Prize for peace to a fabricated Third
World activist, the virtual creation of French Marxist leftovers.
This ensured Rigoberta’s consecration as a new “great author” to be included
in the core curriculum of leading American and European universities (it helped
that she wrote like a ten-year old, which made her accessible to students who
found Shakespeare’s language and Aristotle’s logic a little
too demanding.) This unlikely literary masterpiece gave leftist English
professors (not great experts in history or politics) the opportunity to
brainwash their charges with the evils
of American foreign policy in central America – and to support
the French Marxist Debray’s disastrous policy of fomenting Maoist guerrilla
warfare among Latin American peasants, which has caused hundreds of thousands
of lives to be lost from Guatemala to Colombia.
Even where the
works of Dead White Males like Shakespeare could not be entirely eliminated
from the curriculum (because of residual racist, patriarchal resistance), the
goal in studying them must be to uncover the evil of racism and sexism in every
line these authors wrote. They were to be exposed as hypocritical collaborators
in an oppressive system, by “deconstructing” their works to lay bare the
vicious prejudices that lay beneath. This was done by using the latest voodoo
literary technique invented by the French “post-modernist” charlatan
Jacques Derrida, which allows you to read into works whatever you want to.
Since there is no definitive meaning of a text, any reading is as good as any
other. The reader brings his own unique meaning to the work by “deconstructing” it in function
of his own experience and viewpoint. And if his reading is “de-centred” – that is,
concentrates on some accidental detail irrelevant to the main theme – it is all the
more original. For example, we can take the line “Get thee to a
nunnery!” and use it to read Hamlet as a play revealing Christianity’s repression of women’s sexuality – and this
is just as “true” as seeing it as a play about the despair of a
dissident prince in the face of a corrupt society. In this way a generation of
young minds would be encouraged to read Shakespeare in a “de-centred” fashion, as a
coded revelation of a racist, sexist society, and could thus be liberated from
the distorting vision of the white patriarchy. The young of minority races in
particular would be awakened to a sense of their eternal oppression by this
racist, sexist elite, which was both keeping them down and insidiously trying
to assimilate them into its evil culture.
From an
educational point of view, what is happening is a striking combination of the
craven desire of teachers to flatter the students’ own (limited)
experience, and tailor what is taught to suit it, with a Marxist strategy of
transforming adolescents’ natural sullenness into hatred of their own
civilization. The trend to replace Shakespeare and Keats with rap music lyrics
in order to make literature more “relevant” is a product of
the shift in power in the classroom from teacher to student. But if the student
is now “empowered” (feet on desk, blowing
smoke rings at the teacher) then he no longer learns from the teacher’s experience of
the world. He imposes his own experience as the new trendy reality which the
teacher must learn, and the student learns nothing at all. The study of rap
music lyrics in school simply confines the student within the limits of his own
linguistically impoverished world, instead of expanding it to take in the
poetic tradition. Post-modernist “deconstruction” techniques at
university continue this process of impoverishment and limitation of the
student’s mind in an even more insidious way. Instead of trying to understand
what the great moral and intellectual issues were for the writers of the
seventeenth century (thereby gaining an insight into very different ways of
looking at the world), students are pushed to read all their works in the light
of the issues of today (as defined by their leftist professors) – racism, sexism,
colonialism, class oppression. Every text they look at must be scanned for the
same hidden ideological meanings, whatever age it comes from. This ensures that
there is no escape from the totalitarian monoculture of neo-Marxism, which spreads
its poisonous and distorting worldview even back into the masterpieces of the
remote past.
15)
WESTERN SELF-HATRED RIDES TO THE RESCUE OF THE COLLAPSING MARXIST WORLD-VIEW
One might have
expected that the fall of the Soviet empire in 1991 would have undermined the
entire neo-Marxist ideology and led to a shift to the centre and a new moderate
consensus in the world-view of the American intelligentsia. That is to reckon
without the intensity and bitterness of the culture war between left and right which
has dominated the American intellectual scene ever since McCarthyism in the
1950’s. The right wing had lost the civil rights battle, the sexual
revolution, the Vietnam War, and the feminist struggle. For the leftists to
lose the greatest struggle of the age, the Cold War, was a shock. Of course it
did not lead them to question their world-view because their sympathy with the Soviet Union had long been tempered by reserves – not so much for
its appalling extermination of opponents but for its revisionist dilution of
the pure Marxist ideal. There was, however, some confusion and dismay, not
merely at the fall of Soviet communism but at the shocking embrace of American
conservatism by the newly liberated peoples. This seemed to confirm that the
wacky right-wing views of The Reader’s Digest and The Voice of America had been right all
along in describing their condition. This public relations disaster had to be
covered up at once by a counter-attack. The triumph of the right had to be
spoiled. Neo-Marxism had to be reaffirmed as the only acceptable ideology of
Western academia. So the leftists turned back to those earlier struggles (which
they had won) over race, sex and gender with a determination to fight them all
over again and get their victory engraved in stone. The feminist offensive of
the 1990’s against sexual harassment, date rape, and male
violence was accompanied by the rise of gay liberation, a renewed campaign
against racism, and a new trial of the American past (the Americans had
interned Japanese-Americans during the war! Horror! Racism! War crime!
Equivalence with the gulags!) The crimes of Nazism were dragged back into the
spotlight, with a venomous suggestion that the Western governments fighting
Hitler had really been his accomplices. They had done nothing to stop the
Holocaust! They had stood by and watched! It was the Allies’ crime as well!
Even the great Anglo-American moral victory over Nazism had been a sham! In
short there was nothing but cynical evil in the whole of Western history.
Now this new
spotlight on the Holocaust and attempt to blame the West for it was partly
inspired by the needs of Israeli foreign policy after the 1967 war (and above
all after the decision of Likud after 1980 not to give back the occupied
territories in exchange for peace but to settle them instead.) They needed to
blame Europe as a whole for the Holocaust so as to undermine European calls for
Israel
to end its Lebensraum policy. How could a continent guilty of genocide of the
Jews have the gall to criticize Israeli expansion? But this new myth of general
European guilt was not limited to the regimes that collaborated with the Nazis.
It even extended to the Allies who poured out their blood in the war to defeat
Nazism. Ariel Sharon, the architect of Israel’s Lebensraum
policies, took up the slogan “The world was silent while the Jews were murdered.” By this he could
only have meant the Allies at war with Hitler, since the occupied countries
were hardly in a position to say anything. This accusation had first been made
by a certain number of traumatized concentration camp survivors, and by
journalists like Arthur Koestler, dismayed at how little impact the reports of
the Holocaust in 1943 and 1944 made on the media.72 The
unwillingness of the New York Times
to give these allegations the front page coverage their horror merited is
susceptible to a number of interpretations, from anti-Semitism to scepticism
about an over-the-top atrocity story unlikely to be believed in the absence of
hard evidence. But the media unwillingness to play up the stories of the death
camps (which was more than made up for in 1945 when the camps were liberated
and graphic photos were published all round the globe) soon became the popular
myth, now found in every article on the subject, that the “the world stood
by and did nothing” while the Jews were murdered. The hundred and
twenty thousand British and American pilots who died bombing Nazi Germany chose
a curious way of standing by and doing nothing. So did the one million Western
and nine million Soviet soldiers who died fighting the Nazi armies on land. But
for some embittered concentration camp survivors it was not enough that the
Allies defeated Nazism. They should have stopped the Holocaust itself. How this
could have been done nobody has ever explained. Of course the bitterness of
Jews lining up to be murdered as they saw Allied bombers flying overhead on
their way to military targets is understandable. “Don’t they know, don’t they care?” they must have
thought. But the simple truth is, there is nothing the bombers could have done
to stop it. Bomb the railway lines leading to Auschwitz?
Railway lines can be repaired in a matter of hours with unlimited slave labour.
And the waiting trains delayed by the repairs would have become coffins. (Does
anyone imagine that the deportees in the
stationary trains waiting for the rails to be repaired would have been fed and
watered?) Bomb Auschwitz itself? Besides the
fact that this would have killed thousands of prisoners and been a war-crime
for Nazi propaganda to exploit, what would have prevented the Nazis shifting
the extermination to another one of their two thousand concentration camps, or
dispersing it to a dozen of them? How could the Allies have tracked these
shifts, in the days before satellite photographs? Some commentators have
pointed out that the only American bombers that could reach Poland (and only
from the airfields captured in Spring 1944 when most of the genocide had been
completed) were heavy B24’s that did not have the accuracy to hit gas chambers
or crematoriums without hitting prisoner barracks.73 But even if
they could have hit the gas chambers, what would have stopped the Nazis going
on with the mass shootings of Jews, which were just as fast and efficient?
Daniel Goldhagen in his book Hitler’s Willing
Executioners regards the gas chambers as secondary to the will to exterminate. “It was a more
convenient means, but not an essential development. Had the Germans never
invented the gas chamber, they might well have killed almost as many Jews.” 74 To imagine that destroying some technical infrastructure could have
put an end to a programme of genocide is a delusion. The stark fact is that
nothing can be done to stop a military superpower exterminating millions of
people under its control except what was done – wage total war
against it, defeat it and occupy it. Unfortunately for the victims, that took
time, and for many the victory came too late. But to adopt the conspiracy
theory of history as certain Jewish Holocaust survivors have done is merely to
succumb to the same kinds of paranoid thinking as that of their persecutors.
The accusation that the Allies did nothing to save the Jews from the gas
chambers when they could easily have done so is a contemptible lie. And it is a
lie that has been constantly repeated by leftist journalists for the past
twenty years – either out of the masochistic pleasure of wallowing
in unjustified guilt, or else, more insidiously, out of a neo-Marxist impulse
to spit on the graves of the Allied war dead, because the defeat of Nazism made
capitalist governments look too good. The attempt to blacken the Allies with
complicity in genocide is the mirror image of the attempt to whitewash the
Nazis by denying the Holocaust. But while extreme right-wing Holocaust denial
has never gained a mass following (the evidence of the Holocaust is simply too
great) the extreme left-wing theory of Allied complicity in it has become the
most successful urban myth of all time. Every article about any atrocity
anywhere will unfailingly mention that “the world did nothing while
the Jews were murdered”. Meanwhile, the real war crime of the Allies, the
burning alive of millions of civilians in the unnecessary carpet bombing of
German and Japanese cities, has been largely overlooked in the controversy over
a false accusation.
But this
controversy could not have been timed better for the needs of the neo-Marxist
intellectuals as their Soviet bastion crumbled and they had to face the fact
that they had supported for seventy years a totalitarian hell that had murdered
an estimated fifty-four million people.75 Every means was good to
take the world’s attention off their own guilt. They had spent
forty years denying and ridiculing the stories of the gulags brought out of Russia and China by traumatized escapees. This
did not stop them expressing appalled indignation that the Allies had doubted
the stories of the Holocaust for two years till they liberated the camps.
Magazines like The Readers Digest,
which published sensational stories like “Escape from Red China” detailing the
real horrors of Mao’s regime in the 1960’s, were vilified
by the intellectual left as hysterical, lying, war-mongering fascist rags that
no thinking person could take seriously. And yet the mild scepticism expressed
by many Americans in 1943 that the German enemy was murdering millions of Jews
was now treated by this same intellectual left as an absolute proof of
anti-Semitic bigotry and Allied complicity with the genocide. By their own
standards, how should we judge the leftist intelligentsia’s “scepticism” about Stalinist
and Maoist extermination camps? As proof of complicity and approval. There was
a good deal more solid evidence for the Soviet and Chinese gulags in the 1960’s than there was
for the Nazi death camps in the early 1940’s. Which was the real crime
of blindness to the evidence of colossal mass murder because of sympathy with
the mass-murdering regime? Allied scepticism about the Holocaust for two years,
even while they made total war on the Nazis? Or leftist intellectuals’ denial of the
communist gulags for forty years, while they supported communism
world-wide?
But these
rational considerations did not stop the left from mounting a new hysteria on
the subject of the Holocaust, with the constant subtext: the entire West was to
blame for this, it was not merely the Nazis but Western civilization which did
this. Europe murdered the Jews. America
applauded. That is what every Western student is now in essence taught. And the
cause of this horror was not seen as totalitarianism (which might come a little
too close to the Marxists for comfort), but rather “racism” – the supposed
vice of their right-wing enemies (that is, those who opposed mass immigration
as unemployment began to soar.) And all of this was to divert attention from
one thing: the mind-boggling crime of the Western leftist intelligentsia in
supporting the communist regimes when they knew what was happening under them.
To cover up their own guilt, to create hysterical diversions, the leftists did
not hesitate to make the amalgam between the Nazis’ mass-murder of
Jews and the oppression of blacks in the United States. The result was to
condition the public in a kind of grotesque equivalence. The four thousand
blacks lynched in America since the Civil War, when added together with the six
million Jews which America had stood by and watched murdered (while it was
making total war against the Nazis, but that doesn’t count), somehow
added up to a crime just as unspeakable as the fifty million people done to
death in the USSR and the seventy million done to death by Mao. 76 The
McCarthy witch-hunt, in which three Americans were condemned to death for
espionage after open trials, and a few
dozen Hollywood actors and directors lost their jobs, was blown up till it
assumed the proportions of a totalitarian purge sending thousands to the gulag.
In short, the Marxist counter-offensive to hide their own guilt meant
exaggerating the wrongs and evils of their country’s past until they
invented a new historical America,
painted in the lurid colours of brutality, genocide, and inhuman oppression,
which had never existed outside their imaginations. And the naked self-interest
of female, black and gay academics to exploit their own opportunities by
playing up the past oppression of their groups and posing as the only possible
redeemers of a morally depraved society, pushed American universities to a
degree of cultural and national self-hatred that was without precedent in any
dominant power the world has ever seen.
The reason for
the phenomenal popularity among university professors of Rigoberta Menchu’s largely
fabricated story of Central American atrocities becomes clear. The little voice
asking what the Marxist professors had known about the fifty million victims of
Stalin and the seventy million victims of Mao while they were preaching Karl
Marx to their students had to be drowned out by concentrating the students’ minds on the “real” crimes of the
century – the crimes of American foreign policy in arming and
supporting regimes which murdered and tortured a hundred thousand Guatemalan
peasants during a thirty-year guerrilla
war. Graphic accounts of peasants tortured to death by capitalism and “imperialism” had to be
branded on the minds of the students to make them forget the hundred million
people done to death in the name of Karl Marx while American professors sang
his praises. Compare the number of US colleges where Rigoberta Menchu’s infantile,
appallingly written Marxist tract has been on the reading list as a “great work” for years with
the number which feature Solzhynitsyn’s A Day in the Life of Ivan Denisovitch or The First Circle or Jang Cheng’s Wild Swans, the real masterpieces of the age describing the real
crimes of the century, and you will measure the intellectual and moral treason
of American academia – treason not against their government, not against
democracy, but against the truth. Future ages will be amazed to reflect that
the greatest crimes in human history – the murder of a hundred and
twenty million people by Stalin and Mao – scarcely received a mention
in the curricula of leading American universities during the century in which
they occurred and were graphically exposed.
But beyond the
struggle to hide, obscure or distract attention from the systemic mass murder
of the Marxist regimes by focusing exclusively on the sordid complicity of
their own government with brutal banana republic dictatorships, there was a
wider ideological agenda. The aim of the radical leftist academics, as though
in revenge for the defeat of their Marxist dream, was to destroy the Western
dream – to undermine and discredit the whole historical
vision of the moral and humanistic progress of Western civilization out of
feudal cruelty and tyranny towards enlightenment, justice and humane
government. This whole moral tale of progress was to be exposed as pure
hypocrisy from the start. They sought to depict George Washington and Thomas
Jefferson as slave-owners and therefore hypocrites; to reveal that liberal
philosophers like John Locke invested in the Royal Africa Company, which
engaged in slave-trading, and were therefore tainted; to point out that the
Quakers had accepted slavery before campaigning against it, etc, etc. In short,
the goal was to destroy any notion of moral progress, of gradual enlightenment,
of increasing humanity and compassion, which might possibly represent Western
civilization or its thinkers in a positive light. One is left wondering how
this horde of hypocrites, frauds, racists, moral cowards and vile collaborators
with barbarism ever managed to abolish evils like the slave trade at all – or why they
should have wanted to. The goal of leftist academics was in this way to
insidiously undermine every positive in Western history: to expose every
statesman as a hypocrite, every philosopher as a cynical liar, every reformer
as an accomplice of the evils he pretended to oppose. It is in short a kind of
gutter cynicism, the world-view of the yellow press. On one level this was
merely inverted sentimentality – the immature conviction of the wounded idealist
that since the world is not ideal then it is squalid from top to bottom. The
fact that the heroes of history were flawed characters is something the
adolescent mind of the leftist cannot accept. The idea that it took even more
moral and intellectual courage for a slave-owner to question evils which he was
brought up with, which formed part of the fabric of his world-view, is not
something that the neo-Marxist dogmatist can admit. Since all the world is divided
between absolute evil and absolute good, defined in purely class terms, there
can be no inner struggle of individuals towards enlightenment, but merely the
defeat of one side by the other. Since Marxism sees life not as tragedy but as
the crudest moral melodrama, the protagonists cannot have complex motives or
inner conflicts, and above all cannot evolve, cannot struggle towards the
truth, and cannot redeem themselves.
In the same way,
since moral character to a Marxist is synonymous with ideological position, we
cannot speak of the moral degeneration of a Marxist ruler like Stalin or Mao.
While their doctrine remains correct, they may condemn tens of millions of
people to slavery more atrocious than that endured by any African in America, and
still remain progressive icons. On the other hand, a slave-owning landowner
like Jefferson cannot be anything but a
hypocritical reactionary. He is condemned by his class identity, no matter what
political dilemma he wrestled with, or how earnestly he sought the abolition of
an institution he detested.
16) THE DISAVOWAL OF PROGRESS AND THE EMBRACE OF
A NEW RACISM
This entire cult
of self-hatred, the urge of modern American leftists to degrade their own
history, contrasts strikingly with the way previous ages had dealt with the
problem of evil in their own recent past. The English Victorians were serene in
looking back at the previous century, when criminals had been disembowelled
alive in public and the pieces of their bodies hung like meat on the city
gates, because they accepted the idea that they had made moral progress since
then. This idea of progress enabled them to distance themselves morally from
their benighted ancestors. Far from contorting themselves with guilt over what
their great-grandparents had done, they congratulated themselves for having
climbed so far and so quickly out of the gutters of barbarism and cruelty.
American leftist academics of the last forty years have denied themselves the
idea of moral progress, hypnotized by the industrialized death camps, the
terrible weapons of death modern science has produced, and the sordid
compromises of American Cold War foreign policy. And having denied moral
progress they live fixed in a sort of eternal historical present, where they
react to the atrocities committed by their ancestors of three hundred years ago
as though they were happening today. They read of a lynching or an Indian
massacre or a witch-burning of a bygone century with a feeling of the same
moral self-disgust and self-hatred, the same rage to flagellate themselves and
their race or sex, as if it had happened only yesterday and they were reading
about it in today’s newspaper. So in contrast with the smug
Victorians, looking back on a cruel past with a satisfying sense of progress
made, American leftist academics look back at the crimes committed by their
forefathers as justifying the peculiar loathing for their own race and culture
which they feel in the present (“the white race is the cancer
of human history”.) They cannot see the dawn of enlightened thinking
as a slow progression and a long heroic struggle, because they have denied
themselves a narrative view which necessarily implies progress. Since
humanitarian ideals were voiced in the 18th century, at the same
time as terrible crimes such as slavery persisted, then the ideals, they
conclude, must have been false and hypocritical (and the slave-owners
Washington and Jefferson were vile impostors.) They cannot see those proclaimed
ideals as the first shots fired in a moral war which led gradually to the
abolition of the evils. Not for them the grandiose pronouncement of Hegel: “The History of
the world is none other than the progress of the consciousness of Freedom.” 77 Because if they once admit the idea of
progress they will be led to complacency and self-congratulation on how far
they have come, and their psychological perspective demands self-disgust and
self-loathing – as befits the members of a race which is “the cancer of
human history.”
The only
alternative to this narrative view of moral progress is the racist view that
American leftist academics have espoused for thirty years: everything that
comes from white civilization is bad, and everything from the wonderful Third World proletariat is good. The American
constitution, they have informed us in recent decades, owed far more to
Iroquois political structures than to the wicked European thoughts of Locke and
Montesquieu. Moreover, European thought itself is nothing but an enormous theft
of African thought: the Greeks stole all their thought from the Egyptians, now
compulsorily regarded as a Black People, and medieval Europe
depended on that other Black People, the Arabs, for their access to the texts
of ancient times. This tripe is taught partly as a sort of “noble lie”, in Plato’s sense, in order
to give minority populations, numerous among their students because of their
preferential university places, a sense of their true historic dignity.
Commentators have observed the curious result that few minority students seem
to come out of these university programmes with any reinforced sense of their
worth, but rather with a reinforced sense of grievance. Having been taught a
pack of lies at university, they are astonished that nobody in the outside
world seems to believe it, and are even more convinced of the racist oppression
they live under.
One of the premises of the leftist viewpoint is that all
cultures, as well as both sexes, must
have contributed equally to human progress and enlightenment. Just as this has
led feminists to a historical quest for the wonderful intellectual
contributions made by women and suppressed by the wicked patriarchy, so it has
led the multi-culturalists to ransack history to find the equal contributions
of other cultures, which white colonialism erased from memory. The attempts to
reconstruct the lost contributions which the African peoples (by the laws of
equality) must have made to civilization have reached comical levels. We have
gone beyond the claim that Cleopatra (a descendant of the Macedonian Greek
general Ptolemy, and part of a narrowly racist dynasty where brothers and
sisters married) was really Black. We have even gone beyond the “Black Athena” thesis that the
Greeks got all their knowledge from the “Black” Egyptians (who
on their wall-paintings have the light-brown skin of most other Mediterranean peoples, and whom some
African-Americans think they resemble only because they themselves are half
European in ancestry. It would of course be surprising if Greek democratic
ideas or empirical methods sprang from a totalitarian theocracy.) There are now
serious claims made, and fiercely defended by the more militant
African-Americans, that Shakespeare, Beethoven and Haydn were all black men,
and that this fact has been concealed by an enormous white conspiracy. One of
the proponents of this view believes that “in the 15th and 16th
century…. with the European slave trade in full swing, Afrikans were stripped
of every aspect of their humanity, and in most of western civilization were no
longer considered human. This triggered a wholesale interpretation of history
that methodically excluded Afrikans from any respectful mention.” 78
This is not in fact the way Shakespeare presents Othello, or any other black
character, and there is simply no evidence that this ever happened. The only African blood we know of among great
European writers, the one eighth Ethiopian ancestry of the Russian poet
Alexander Pushkin, was proudly proclaimed by him to the whole world and features
prominently in even the briefest biography ever written of him. The “octoroon”
Pushkin married one of the great beauties of the Russian aristocracy, cut a
flamboyant figure in high society, and was fêted in his lifetime as the
greatest poet in Russia. The notion that Europeans would have been
ashamed of African blood is a peculiar African-American prejudice, part of a
culture which has no memory or concept of Africans as having been anything
other than slaves. The theory of an enormous conspiracy to write Africans out
of history expresses a collective paranoia of lunatic dimensions. It appears to
be widespread among African-Americans, not merely among the usual half-educated
devourers of conspiracy theory history like the readers of The Da Vinci Code, but even among radical black academics. This is
a dangerous way of gathering a popular following. Once you start inventing lies
to comfort people, their appetite grows for even more whopping lies to comfort
them even more. People end up living in an entirely imaginary world, and are
full of rage that it is not acknowledged by the real world. And as they wrap
themselves in their own version of history and of reality, they will soon begin
to question the moral ties that bind them to the people of a parallel universe.
That
the ignorant are now dictating what they will be taught is an extraordinary
turn-around in the idea of a university. “Teach us the history that
comforts us!” they cry. Only it doesn’t really comfort
them. It only excites even further their sense of injustice. This
dissatisfaction leads them to demand an even more luridly distorted version of
the past, where their race’s glorious achievements are only equalled by the
enormity of the conspiracy which suppressed all knowledge of these wonders from
human memory. The demand for more and more outrageous lies will sooner or later
come up against the limits of conscience of all but the most unscrupulous or
fanatical professors. Soon only the academic Quislings of a totalitarian
ideology will remain in place, and the rest will desert the humanities and take
refuge in the exact sciences, where two and two cannot be made to be five in
order to please an “oppressed” minority. The American university is emerging
from its forty years of ideological civil war in a state of moral and
intellectual collapse.
17)
THE FUTURE OF THE GREAT IDEOLOGICAL DIVIDE
Whether it is
capable of renewing itself in the new era that we are entering upon is an open
question. The terrorist attacks of September 2001 were perhaps a turning point
in history in that both the ideologies of left and right have split up the
middle in the confused reactions to that shocking event. The self-hating
neo-Marxist left, which had encouraged the Third World for forty years to see
the West as tyrannical exploiters, could hardly contain their glee at the
striking down of three thousand agents of Western imperialism at their desks.
But some of their comrades were appalled by this reaction. The event became for
them a shocking revelation of the true nature of the neo-Marxist ideology they had
espoused, and its profound hatred of Western values. Some leftists at once went
over to supporting the war on terror and even the war on Iraq to remove a bloody dictator.79
On the right, meanwhile, the intemperate calls for a global “war of
civilizations” and the launching of an arbitrary attack on the
most secular regime in the Arab world inspired equal misgivings. A split
appeared there too – between the neo-conservatives, with a global agenda
to spread liberty and shopping malls by force if need be, and a more
traditional conservatism that thought only trouble could come from forcing
Western values upon others, in violation of international law.80 This
made for some strange bedfellows, as humanist leftists allied with neo-cons to
applaud the removal of a cruel dictator, while traditional conservatives allied
with Marxists to deplore the breach of international law in an unprovoked war.
Are these curious new alignments temporary confusions? Or are they a sign of
the impending disintegration of the old ideologies of left and right? Only time
will tell.
But the paradoxes
go deeper. The Western neo-Marxist left, which has spent the last forty years
urging the Third World to strike back at the colonial oppressor, has, like an
apprentice sorcerer, raised up in the Muslim world an anti-Western demon (or
perhaps jinni) of terrifying malice. But it is a demon which feels more hatred
for the Western left than for the Western right. The paradox is that although
the leftists agree with the Islamists’ hatred of Western
civilization (Sontag’s “the white race is
the cancer of human history”), these leftists are themselves the very element in
Western civilization which the Islamists hate the most. For it is the left which has pushed for
radical feminism, sexual liberation, and homosexual liberation to be seen as an
essential part of Western culture, and it is this sexual agenda that is most
repugnant to Islam. Many Muslims are now convinced that adopting Western
democracy will open the gates wide to mass promiscuity, pornography, sodomy,
lesbianism, abortion, gay marriage and the collapse of the family. Cohorts of
feminists, paid by Western governments, have already descended on Baghdad to try to
organize “gender equality” as a basic part of the new
Western order. One would have thought that the priority would be to get these
societies into the early 20th century, that of democracy and an end
to government corruption and police torture, before taking them into the 21st
century of gay pride parades. But that is not the view of the left. While it is
the right, therefore, which has been pushing the notion of the war on terror
and the clash of civilizations, it is paradoxically the gay and feminist left
which is making that clash of civilizations a reality. The average Texas Southern
Baptist probably shares far more core moral values with a Muslim fundamentalist
than he does with a militant lesbian abortionist. But the image of the West
being beamed into Muslim countries by Hollywood
and MTV is that of sexual “liberation”, not church-going Texan
families, opposed to abortion, gay marriage and pre-marital sex. It is thus the
sexual liberationist left which is provoking Islamic hatred of Western culture,
even while it is the neo-conservative right (pushed by its Israeli sympathies)
which is gung-ho for waging a war of civilizations.
It is equally a
paradox that it is the left that has pushed most consistently for immigration
into Western countries of the huge Muslim populations that now form the fertile
recruiting ground of Islamic fundamentalist terrorism. (Of course the
capitalist right has also quietly supported immigration, in order to keep
labour plentiful and wages low, but it is the left that has made it an
ideological hobby-horse, denouncing as racists the workers who opposed
immigration back in the 1960’s as a threat to their jobs and a cultural invasion
of their territory.) Only in the last couple of years has the progressive left
suddenly awoken to the fact that the populations which its anti-racist,
pro-immigration ideology has massively imported into Europe
are not really favourable to its values. For the Dutch homosexual militant Pim
Fortuyn to become leader of a populist anti-immigration party because Islam is
hostile to gay rights was an earthquake in the world-view of the progressive
left all over Europe. And with Pim Fortuyn’s political
murder, the pro-immigration, multicultural, West-hating left and the feminist
and gay liberationist left have suddenly glimpsed their basic incompatibility,
and they are still reeling from the shock.
This sudden clash
between the two main branches of neo-Marxism – the anti-racist,
pro-immigration, multiculturalist ideology and the feminist-homosexual
liberationist lobby – would be one of the more hilarious spectacles of
the age if what is at stake were not so important. For how this clash plays out
will determine to a large extent the future of the Western world. The
multiculturalists are of course the willing pawns of expansionist Islam, urging
European governments to build mosques by the hundred (while no new church can
be built anywhere in the Islamic world, and saying Mass is a criminal offence
in Saudi-Arabia) and dragging before the courts anyone (like Brigitte Bardot)
who criticizes the Islamization of Europe or opposes immigration. But,
paradoxically, the feminist-homosexual lobby, while their beliefs are opposed
to Islam, are in practical terms working in its favour by undermining the
Western birth-rate. As families collapse and birth-rates fall under the
onslaught of feminist brainwashing of women against motherhood and destruction
of the rights of fathers, the multiculturalists then call for more immigration
to make up the shortfall, and the imams happily preach to an ever-expanding
Muslim population in the West. They arouse them to ever more fanatical hatred
of the decadent, sexual liberationist culture around them – the other face
of the leftist lobby which has let them in. Feminism, while apparently
espousing principles quite opposed to Islam, is thus ensuring Islam’s triumph. The
feminists have forgotten that culture wars are above all demographic wars, and
their undermining of motherhood and family has condemned the West to lose the
demographic battle in advance. Radical feminism may be seen as simply the
suicide impulse of a people. When a civilization is ready to die, it preaches
sterility and belittles motherhood. Since this feminist movement is likely to
result in the collapse of our civilization and the disappearance of Western
peoples from the planet over the next two
or three centuries, it is time we examined it more closely, and analysed where it came from, how it
developed, and whether there is any chance of countering its disastrous
effects.
18)
FEMINISM: THE LAST PHASE OF MASCULINIZATION
Contemporary
feminism is of course a branch of neo-Marxism, seeing the female sex in the
role of the oppressed proletariat. But on another level, feminism is the final
stage of that process of masculinization which began with the mid-nineteenth
century ideologies of violence, and reached a climax in the cult of total war
and the militarization of Western man in the 20th century. Women
were admitted only slowly and reluctantly to this process of masculinization.
It was thought necessary to preserve them from it, to keep at least part of the
human race displaying the gentler qualities that Western men had decided to
crush out of themselves in their pursuit of war, conquest and industrial
economic competition. However, the need to employ even middle-class women in
the factories and offices during the First World War to replace the mobilized
men broke down this carefully preserved separation of characters and spheres.
This great watershed in Western civilization not only resulted in the extension
to women of political rights and access to the higher professions, but also
prompted a certain number of women to reject their traditional role and live
like men in every way. The inter-war years saw a plethora of women adventurers,
pilots, explorers, intellectuals, writers, actors and artists, living largely
outside the social rules that applied to the rest. But they remained a minority
of non-conformists – the majority kept to the old division of roles for
another forty years. Then with the rise of the neo-Marxist ideology in the 1960’s, leftist
college women suddenly invented a new identity for themselves as a cruelly
oppressed class – and urged the mass of women to rise up against
their oppressors, the male sex, who were keeping them in the domestic servitude
of motherhood and family. The feminists demanded not only the right to the same
economic and social roles as men, but also the right to develop the same
character – the same aggressiveness, competitiveness, career obsession and
ambition for power. It was a necessary part of this agenda to reject the
feminine character as a slave-cult, an image imposed upon women to make them
submissive and obedient, to confine them within a domestic, family role where
they were dependent on men and therefore powerless. And this rejection of
femininity and adoption of masculinity by women burnt the bridges behind men.
There was now no going back for men, no retreat from the ultra-masculine
character they had developed in the century of war. If they tried to retreat,
they would be outflanked by women. The final imprisonment of Westerners in an
ultra-masculine culture was achieved by feminism. It has guaranteed the
supremacy of the values of work, competition, power, aggressiveness, and war,
as well as sexual promiscuity (all of these things being linked to male
hormone.) And it has meant the eclipse of the feminine values of nurturing,
love, tenderness, compassion, faithfulness, the desire for children and the
urge to form stable couples (all of which are linked to female hormone.) Woman’s traditional
character, with its maternal and family orientation, is now fast disappearing
in the industrialized countries. As Western birth-rates collapse, and our own
extinction as a race and civilization is programmed for the near future, it is
important to see the stages by which this final, fatal development has
occurred.
19) FEMINISM AS URBAN MYTH
Feminism in its
late 20th century incarnation, as we saw, is another off-shoot of
1960’s New Left Marxism. Like the anti-racism ideology, it is constructed on a notion of
the eternal oppression of one group of humans by another. Both ideologies are
based on a systematic falsification of history. Just as it is common today to
find blacks (and leftist whites) who are convinced that the Europeans
introduced slavery into Africa, so it is common to find women (and leftist men)
convinced that, throughout most of the past, women in the Western world were
sold as chattels, and beaten or raped with impunity by any man that chose to
abuse them. When pressed to specify when this period was, they become
hysterical and begin screaming about the old English law that defined the width
of the rod a man could use to beat his wife. This particular old English law
has never been found, despite being cited hundreds of times by feminists over the
past 30 years. It is worth looking at this for a moment as an illustration of how the feminists have constructed their
fictitious version of history and brainwashed an entire generation with it.
This particular
fiction can be traced to Del Martin, who wrote a book on wife-beating in 1976.
She claimed that English law allowed men to beat their wives with a rod no
thicker than a man’s thumb – and added the phrase “ a sort of rule
of thumb.” This led to an instant urban myth that the
derivation of the old expression “rule of thumb” (referring to a
carpenter’s use of his thumb for rough measurements) was in
fact this legendary law allowing wife-beating. This grotesque invention became
a staple of feminist magazine articles in the years after 1976. It even figured
in an American government report of 1982 on violence against women, which
imputed the “rule of thumb” to the famous English
jurist William Blackstone, whose Commentaries
on the Laws of England of 1765
codified the common law accepted on both sides of the Atlantic.
This imputation to Blackstone was supposed to show how deeply the entire legal
culture of the Anglo-Saxon world accepted violence against women until recent
times. It was retailed by numerous commentators as undisputed fact until in
1994 Christina Hoff Summers took the trouble to read Blackstone and discovered
he had never mentioned anything of the kind. What Blackstone said was that
although “reasonable domestic chastisement” had been allowed
in the past (since a man was held legally responsible for his wife’s actions), from
the reign of Charles II in the 17th century “this power of
correction began to be doubted, and a wife may now have security of the peace
against her husband” – that is, the protection of the law against him – though he
admitted that among “the lower rank of people the courts of law will
still permit a husband to restrain a wife of her liberty in case of any gross
misbehaviour.” 81 This does not,
of course, prove that wife-beating was not frequent, as burglary is frequent in
many places today. But it does mean that it has not been legal under
Anglo-Saxon law for at least three hundred years, contrary to the persistent
assertions of the feminists. As for the alleged rule about the thickness of the
rod allowed, it is an urban myth, variously imputed by anecdote to one
reactionary judge or another, but for which there has never been the slightest
scrap of evidence. In fact recent scholars have discovered that attitudes to
wife-beating in 19th century America were much the same as they
are now. Such behaviour was illegal (the earliest statutes against domestic
violence – by both sexes – date from 1655) and
perpetrators were publicly reviled. When not chastised by the law (flogging and
fines were common), wife-beaters were dealt with by relatives and neighbours in
the roughest possible way.82 In short, the feminists’ aim, in which
they have succeeded, was to convince public opinion and government officials of
an outright falsehood – that America’s traditional culture was
one of legalized violence against women – in order to further their
own extremist agenda of revenge. It is hard to know how much of their
systematic misrepresentation of the past is merely the result of hysterical
collective self-pity, like the legends of martyrdom of certain nationalist
movements, and how much is deliberate lying. Certainly the selective quotation
of Blackstone in the government report of 1982 is so skilful it was clearly
designed to deceive by those who knew that what they were saying was false. The
tissue of myths, superstitions and outright inventions that makes up the
feminist view of the past seems to be a combination of the accidental accretion
of errors and confusions, and the cynical lies of a manipulative, power-hungry
sect.
This process of
hysterical exaggeration and falsification has been characteristic of the
feminist movement from the beginning. There are much older examples of it. In
586 at a provincial church council in Macon,
France, a
proposal was made that the word “man” (the Latin “homo”) should be used
only for the male sex, and another word should be used for the female, in the
interests of clarity. Statements such as “Queen Ingoberg was a man of
great wisdom” were common at the time, and some people felt they
were grammatically odd. Latin, having no articles, does not distinguish “man” (humanity) from “a man” (a male adult.)
The concern being expressed was similar to that of modern feminists who reject
the use of words like “mankind” or “man” for the human
race, because of their male connotations. The proposal was overruled, because
the other members of the council quoted Genesis: “And God created
man, male and female He created him”. The word “man” must therefore
continue to be used for both sexes. This fairly intelligent debate over gender
language entered feminist mythology in a totally garbled form. During the
French Revolution, a pro-feminist convention delegate named Charlier, defending
the women’s clubs against a proposal to close them, asked with
indignation if they were still living in the time of “that ancient
council where it was decreed that women were no longer part of the human race.” In 1848, a
feminist from Bourges
remembered it as “a council which met to debate the great question:
whether women had a soul.” 83 The decrees of the council of Macon do not in fact mention either
the word “woman” or the word “soul” (we owe the
story of the debate over the word “homo” to a brief
account by Gregory of Tours, but it is not mentioned in the decrees the council
produced.) How on earth did this grotesque misconception arise?
Charlier may have
been vaguely remembering a debate launched in the late 16th century
by a scholar from Brandenburg named Valens Acidalius who published a satirical
and joking “disputation” proving that women were not
human – it was an obscure satire of the Socinians, a sect
that interpreted the bible literally, and it again involved a play on the
double meaning of “man” (the human race and a male adult.) Now ingenious
arguments to prove impossible propositions were an intellectual sport at that
time, and were read as entertainment. Contemporary theologians, however, did
not see it as a joke. They vigorously attacked the pamphlet as a heretical work
(since indeed it was heresy to deny that women were human – what would that
make the Virgin Mary? – besides being a manifest absurdity, since the
female of a species necessarily belongs to the species.) The work, given
notoriety by the outrage it provoked, was then published in various countries
as an amusing display of specious logic, often with a refutation by the
Lutheran scholar Simon Geddicus bound with it. Half a century later a
translation of it (under the comical pseudonym “Horatio Plato”) reached Italy, where it
sparked another furious reply by a female scholar, Angelica Tarabotti. Pope
Innocent X got to hear of “Horatio Plato’s” heretical work
and, not seeing it as a joke either, placed it on the index of forbidden books
in 1651. So far, then, we have a misogynous joke which was condemned by all
establishment scholars and banned by the Pope. So much for establishment
misogyny. The next step was taken by Johannes Leyster, a Lutheran pasteur from
Hesse, who in 1676 published a work called The
Triumph of Polygamy (advocating this
practice) where he made the connection with the council of Macon – claiming that at
this council a cleric had argued that women could not be called human beings (homines – which means both
human beings and men.) Leyster is the one who seems to have confused the debate
over gender language at Macon
(whether women should be called men) with the recent frivolous and satirical “disputation” proving women
were not human. Leyster was followed by a Dutch Calvinist called Pierre Bayle
who seized on this story of Macon as a stick to beat Catholicism, and then a 19th
century anti-clerical called Aime-Martin who changed the story into a debate
over whether women had souls (possibly muddling it with the Spanish debate at
Valladolid in 1550 about the souls of Amerindians.) The famous debate at the council
of Macon over
whether women had souls is now a fixture of feminist propaganda – it is taken as a
fact of history that women in the Middle Ages were thought not to have souls.
In reality the assertion was never made and the debate never happened. It is an
enormous game of Chinese whispers played over the centuries, where the will to
misunderstand for polemical purposes prevailed absolutely over any quest for
truth. And the same story could be told (though it would tire the reader) about
other famous misogynous statements, whether by Aristotle or Acquinas, where the
smallest hint of belittling women has been gleefully seized upon by feminists,
with a contemptuous disregard for scholarship or for the simplest facts of what
was actually said. In the case of Acquinas, the tactic of the feminists is as
crude as taking the statement Acquinas sets out to refute (“The female is a
defective male” – a common misunderstanding of Aristotle’s biological
theory of the sexing of the foetus) and ascribing it to Acquinas himself. 84
The feminist
movement has thus put together, over the past century and a half, an elaborate
folklore of myths, legends, falsehoods and distorted facts, all designed to
prove the terrible oppression and subjugation of women in all ages. Now when
writing of this kind appeared in the 19th century, when women were
denied political rights and were struggling to obtain them, the bitterness
which led to grotesque exaggeration of the wrongs they had suffered was
understandable. Many 19th century feminists were self-taught, had
been denied access to universities (the first women’s colleges only
opened in 1848 at the University of London and in 1873 at Cambridge) and their somewhat approximate
scholarship and lack of ability to tell fact from fiction can be excused. One
may compare their situation with nationalist movements like that of the Irish,
which lived on legends of past oppression, which were often believed in a very
exaggerated form by people deprived of education by British rule. (In neither case
does exaggeration mean that oppression did not exist.) But when a movement is
no longer in a situation where it is deprived of access to accurate knowledge
of the past, where its voice is no longer suppressed but is only too well
heard, its continued cultivation of myths, pious legends of persecution, and
gross distortions of history gives rise to a dangerous paranoia. What was a
movement of liberation becomes a movement of paranoid hatred and revenge. This
is what nationalist movements such as the Provisional IRA and the Basque
separatists became over the last third of the 20th century. It is
what feminism became during the same period. A wallowing in self-pity for
grossly exaggerated wrongs becomes the justification for very real wrongs by
one’s own side. And while the wrongs perpetrated by the feminists are not
of the bomb-throwing kind, they are just as damaging to human beings – in their
successful campaign to bias the entire legal system against husbands and
fathers, and to destroy countless individual lives, as part of their goal of
destroying marriage, fatherhood and the family. Unlike extremist nationalist
movements, whose hatred is a temporary means towards a change of national
borders (after which reconciliation with the enemy will be possible), for
radical feminism hatred of men is not a means to an end but the end itself.
Their goal is the permanent poisoning of relations between the sexes, so that
marriage and family, those evil expressions
of “patriarchy”, will be abolished. The spreading of grotesque atrocity
stories about the enemy is for radical feminists not an isolated aberration but
a systematic strategy.
20)
THE FEMINIST REWRITING OF HISTORY
But the
repetition of wildly exaggerated stories about past oppression is for all feminists,
even those who would not define themselves as radical, a matter of loyalty to
the cause. To admit that a story might be false is to concede humanity to the
oppressor. The stories, even if known to be inventions, are seen as something
that could easily have been true, given the degree of oppression that went on,
and are therefore worth repeating as instructive fables. They are useful in the
same way that the medieval stories of Jews killing Christian babies were
useful, in whipping up hysteria and a sense of grievance – the prerequisite
for a movement of revenge. The pious acceptance of sentimental legends of
female martyrdom has led to the growth of a fantastically distorted vision of
the past as a scene of unrelieved persecution of women, which makes it quite
impossible for those under its influence to see men as anything but evil
oppressors, driven by a pathological hatred of women. Logically, they feel,
that hatred must still exist on some deep level within all men, or these events
cannot be explained. And thanks to feminist academics, promoted through
positive discrimination and given their own Women’s Studies
departments to purvey their paranoid ideology, this view has been
systematically imposed on the students of Anglo-Saxon universities (and elsewhere)
in the name of some sort of redress for past injustices. It is as if the right
to grotesquely exaggerate past wrongs were part of a moral compensation for
them, and anyone who challenges the truth of what they say is a wicked denier
of a sort of female holocaust. Today many Westerners have been brainwashed with
a view of the past which is not the product of historians but of fanatical and
ignorant ideologues.
Much feminist
writing about the past reminds one of this passage in George Orwell’s 1984, where the hero is reading a
children’s history textbook issued by the communist
government:
In the old days
(it ran), before the glorious Revolution, London
was not the beautiful city that we know today.
It was a dark, dirty, miserable place where hardly anybody had enough to
eat, and where hundreds and thousands of poor people had no boots on their feet
and not even a roof to sleep under. Children no older than you had to work
twelve hours a day for cruel masters, who flogged them with whips if they worked
too slowly and fed them on nothing but stale breadcrusts and water. But in
among all this terrible poverty there were just a few great big beautiful
houses that were lived in by rich men who had as many as thirty servants to
look after them. These rich men were called capitalists…… The capitalists
owned everything in the world and everyone else was their slave. They owned all
the land, all the houses, all the factories, and all the money. If anyone
disobeyed them they could throw them into prison. 85
Now Orwell, a militant
socialist until shortly before he wrote this, a volunteer to fight fascism
alongside revolutionary socialists in the Spanish civil war as well as a
sometime tramp and campaigner for the unemployed, was a man highly sensitive to
the oppression of the working class. He was able to recognize the exact degree
of reality of many of the injustices described in this account. Yet despite the
accuracy of most of the details, it is the whole picture which is quite simply
wrong. It offended his sense of truth (as it offends ours) to see a complex
society reduced to this grotesque one-dimensional caricature, as if there had
been nothing going on in the age of Dickens, Mill and Gladstone, or that of
Milton or Shakespeare or Chaucer, except unrelieved oppression. But this
caricature precisely parallels the feminist caricature of history. That is
exactly the way most radical feminists view, or rather reconstruct, the past – through the
selection of negative details, many of which are accurate, but which they
present as the whole picture, in a way that is a grotesque falsification
because of what it leaves out.
This kind of
falsification arises because these feminists (like Orwell’s fictional
Marxists) are not seeking to present the whole picture, but to find support in
the past for an ideology of hatred and revenge in the present. Now the
consensus among educated people seems to be that this distortion of the past
can’t do much harm, so we should let them get it off their chests – that somehow the lies will
be found out sooner or later, and this fanaticism will simply evaporate. But it
is not clear where most of the younger generation are going to be exposed to
the truth, unless they become historians themselves. A generation of this kind
of brainwashing makes it sink in permanently: it becomes simply the worldview
of the age, endlessly retailed in every newspaper and magazine, like the “rule of thumb” story. If we
were to reproduce a feminist version of the communist children’s history book in
Orwell, it would go something like this:
Before the 20th
century, all Western women were kept as chattel slaves of men. They had no
property rights or legal rights, and could be bought and sold like cattle. The
selling of a woman to a man for his personal use was called marriage. This
consisted in the rape of an innocent and frightened girl by a stranger she had
been sold to, but the poets pretended it was all based on something called love
and wrote lots of mushy poems about it. Married women were made to work in the
kitchen and could be beaten by their husband whenever he chose. The law even
specified how thick the stick was that a man could use to beat his wife. If she
ran away the law would bring her back to him by force. No woman was allowed to
study at university or work as a doctor or scientist or lawyer or professor, or
do anything but act as her husband’s personal slave and have
children. But a husband could divorce her and take her children away whenever
he wanted to.
This is an average version
of the caricature of the past that radical feminists believe in, and teach to
the next generation. And of course most items in this account have an element
of truth in them, at least for some periods of the past, just as the account in
Orwell of capitalists and workers was for the most part technically true. But
we have to ask the question: does this picture correspond to the reality of the
lives of Jane Austen, Charlotte Bronte, George Sand, Florence Nightingale,
Marie Curie, and before them to Madame de Stael, Lady Mary Wortley Montagu,
Elizabeth Vigée le Brun, Fanny Burney, Ninon de Lenclos, Christina of Sweden,
Catherine the Great, Aphra Behn, Sophonisbe Anguissola, Elizabeth I, Catherine
of Aragon, Christine de Pizan, Eleanour of Aquitaine, etc. Is this honestly the
way they perceived and experienced life? Surely if things had been this bad we
would have heard more bitter complaints from them? What is wrong is the
emotional colour of the account. It is partly accurate but wholly untrue. It is
half a story. We could equally well construct the other half, again in the
style of the children’s textbook :
Before the 20th
century, most women of the propertied classes did not have to work. Men had to do all the work for them,
sometimes for long hours in dingy offices and counting houses, while the women
sat at home and had tea with their friends. Although men had to earn the money,
it was generally women who decided how to spend it. They spent a lot of time
buying pretty clothes for themselves and expensive furnishings for their homes,
while the men worked to provide them with the money. Women’s only real job
was to have children. They didn’t even have to bring them up, since they usually had
a nurse to look after them, and at seven the boys (and later the girls) were
sent away to boarding school. Housework was done by servants. When war came the
men had to go away and fight and get killed, while the women stayed home and
had affairs with other men. If the husband discovered his wife was having an
affair, he often had to fight a duel with her lover and was sometimes killed,
whereupon she was free to enjoy his property and live a life of idleness and
pleasure. Women spent a lot of time at theatres and operas and they read more
novels than men. Often they wrote novels too, because they had a lot of time on
their hands while the men were working to keep them. Most of their novels were
about love, and they expected men who were in love with them to treat them like
goddesses. Men in love had to propose to women on their knees, recite them
poetry, and beg to be allowed to kiss their hand. A man had to promise to keep
a woman in luxury and idleness for the rest of her life if she would agree to
marry him. Women were considered superior beings and men had to open doors for
them and stand up when they came into the room. If a ship was sinking, the
women had to be saved first.
Now this version is about as
true as the other one. It is also a careful selection of facts to support a
certain biased view, while leaving out all the rest. If you put the two
versions together, you get an idea of the complexity and contradictions of the
past, and the extraordinary paradoxes of the man-woman relationship. But to
allow only one of these half-true versions of women’s history (the
feminist one) to be propagated in the schools and universities is
indoctrinating the young in an enormous falsehood.
Now this is not to deny that in many ages of the past,
and over most of the world including Europe, the traditional division of roles
between the sexes put women at a serious disadvantage in the realms of
education, civil rights (sometimes including property rights), and freedom to engage in professional,
political and intellectual activities – simply because all these
things were considered part of the “men’s realm”, while the women’s realm was home
and family. This social system gave some women a sense of injustice,
frustration and personal wrong. But it was also a system that was accepted as
natural and actively defended by many other women (in most ages probably the
majority), who considered it to be to their advantage in fulfilling their
primary goal in life, to marry and have children. In the 19th
century, when the feminist struggle was under way in earnest, the sharpest
division was not between men and women, but between women who wanted to change
their traditional role and women who did not. The greatest obstacle to Florence
Nightingale’s career was not men (who generally supported her)
but the women of her family and other conventional women, who saw her ambitions
as unnatural and threatening to all women, by devaluing the traditional female
role.86 To pretend that this division of roles was imposed by the
arbitrary and wilful tyranny of men, acting in concert against all women, is a
grotesque distortion of history. It was part of an inherited way of life, a
division of labour considered natural by all cultures, and believed in and
transmitted by both women and men for thousands of years. However absurd and
unjust this system may appear to us, it was rooted in the very real biological
and economic needs that prevailed throughout most of humanity’s existence.
Giving birth to enough children to keep society going (often requiring at least
ten pregnancies to allow for miscarriages, stillbirths, infant mortality,
childhood illnesses and losses in wars and epidemics) was an enormous task that
incapacitated women for many other activities. Many woman spent at least twenty
years of their average fifty-year life-span either pregnant or breast-feeding – just to keep the
population from declining. It is this irreducible biological fact that was the
basis of their exclusion not only from a military role but also from many of
the professional activities developed over the ages by men (though not from all
of them.) That this division of roles was absurdly rigid in many ages, that it
became a superstition rather than a practical arrangement, and that it changed
too slowly as social, economic, medical and demographic conditions evolved over
the last two centuries, may all be admitted. But it did eventually change, at
least in the West, as more and more men as well as women came to see it as
unnecessary and outdated. Yet to hear the description of this historical
process by a radical feminist academic today is not to hear an account of
enlightenment gradually prevailing over inherited prejudices and ancestral
customs so that the roles of men and women could be adapted to new
circumstances. It is rather to hear an account of a wicked class of human
beings, the male sex, having their evil power challenged by a class of
eternally oppressed victims, rising up in a wrathful crusade to end the age-old
tyranny of the Beast of the Apocalypse. The tone of most feminist writing is
one of perpetual indignant accusation against the entire male sex, past,
present and future, with special emphasis on the iniquity of Western men in
particular. That this is the race of men who did eventually give women equal
rights in all domains appears to be lost on the modern feminist, because feminism
is a branch of the neo-Marxist cult of hatred of Western civilization. It is
axiomatic for this cult that Western man was worse in all respects than the
wonderful cultures of the Third World he so
wickedly oppressed. The fact that these wonderful cultures included such
practices as foot-binding, widow-burning, harems, slavery, forced marriages,
child marriages, polygamy, female circumcision, and the veiling and virtual
imprisonment of women in their homes – customs which Western man
in his ignorant colonial racism often tried to put an end to – does not sow any
doubt in the feminist mind that Western man is and always has been the
principal enemy of women’s freedom. And nothing Western man ever did can
possibly be accepted as a step in the right direction. Feminists will never be
persuaded to see the glass of women’s position as half full at
any time in Western history. To them it was always half empty. No progress
made, no right acquired at any period of the past ever elicits satisfaction. It
only provokes more rage that all the rights enjoyed by Western women in the 21st
century were not instantly available to women in the Cro-Magnon period. Because
the notion of progress that prevailed in the 18th and 19th
centuries has been denied by the breast-beating fashions of modern academia,
the result is a peculiar a-historicism. The injustices or cruelties of a
thousand years ago inspire as much indignation and partisan anger as if they
had happened last week. There is no satisfaction that we have all emerged from
a benighted past. Rather this past is an eternal present, something for which
abject apologies, compensation, even revenge, must be exacted, by relentless
vilification of those who happen to be the same sex as the offenders of a
bygone age. The leftist academics having abolished the notion of progress as a
wickedly self-satisfied delusion, Western men are condemned to an eternal sense
of guilt, where the crimes of three hundred years ago are branded on our
foreheads as an ever-present reminder of our collective turpitude. The main
goal of the feminists is never to allow the oppressors’ descendants in
the male line ever to forget or ever to be forgiven.
It is because of
the distortions operated by feminist ideologues upon the whole history of
relations between the sexes that one is tempted to set the record straight,
however briefly and sketchily. The present state of relations between men and
women in the West cannot be understood clearly if we are under the influence of
the grotesque version of past events imposed on everyone today by the radical
feminists.
One is led to the
exercise of a brief re-sketching of the broader lines of history, not because
this will uncover new facts but because it may help to reorganize the known
facts in our minds. Our view of the past is not determined by what we know, but
by how we relate these facts to one another – and by which organization of
facts is recognized in public discourse as the accepted version of things. The
function of the historian may be to bring to light new facts. That of the
historian of ideas is to put them in new relationships, and outline a rather
different organization of the facts, with different conclusions to be drawn
from it. The historians with the widest knowledge often seem reluctant to make
clear judgements, and they seldom impinge on current debates about the past,
which are dominated by those with political agendas. As a result the average
educated person’s emotional attitude to the past today has not been
formed by professional historians at all. It has been shaped exclusively by
ideologues, usually of the neo-Marxist persuasion, or by one-subject historical
investigators driven by a powerful political obsession. Hence the view most
educated people have of relations between men and women in the past has been
formed almost entirely by the militants of the feminist movement. It is a
tissue of myths, half-truths and hysterical falsehoods, which the accounts of
historians (precisely because they are enormously detailed and complex, and avoid
simple judgements) seem powerless to counteract.
This makes it
extremely difficult to deal with the history of feminism, without in fact
examining the past condition of women in a somewhat more analytical way. It is
only by understanding how women’s position changed over the centuries that one can
come to some critical judgement both of the process of women’s emancipation in
the West, their fight for political rights, and the later movement of “women’s liberation”,
which fought for a change of social roles and of the very concept of womanhood.
The key to all understanding of the past is perspective, and it is perspective
that we must now try to achieve on this emotive subject.
NOTES
CHAPTER
FOUR
1) Jeremy Paxman, The English,
A Portrait of a People (London,1998), pp.176-181 2) Christopher Hibbert, The
English, A Social History 1066-1945 (London,1987)
p. 402 3) Ibid., quoting Lawrence Stone, The
Family, Sex and Marriage in England,
(1977) p. 325 4) Sir Nathaniel Wraxall, Historical
Memoirs of my Own Time (1815), quoted by Hibbert, op.
cit., p.339 5) Genevieve Leroy, Vivian Muguette, Histoire de la Beauté Feminine à travers les
Ages, Paris (1989) p. 245. 6) Hibbert, op. cit., p.339 7) Ibid., p. 455
8) Jonathan
Gathorne-Hardy, The Public School Phenomenon (London,1977)
p. 70
9) Ibid., p. 70.
10) Hibbert, p. 455
11) Gathorne-Hardy, p. 69 (and passim
as a source for much of this section)
12) Peter Gay, The Cultivation of
Hatred (New York, 1993) p. 40
13) Stephen Fry, Moab is My Washpot (Arrow, London, 1998) pp.
17-19
14) Stendhal, La
Vie d’Henri Brulard.
15) Robert Graves, Goodbye to All
That, London
(1929) p.189-90
16) Byron, Don Juan, Canto I.
17) Paxman, op. cit., both quotes (Saussure and Fiévée) on p. 221
18) Ibid., p. 217
19) See Mary Astell’s Some Reflections Upon Marriage(1700)
20) Amy Louise
Erickson, Women & Property, in Early Modern England,
(London, NY,
1993) p. 108. See also p. 109 for the
German traveller cited a few lines above.
21) Graves,
op. cit., p. 43
22) Ibid., p. 75
23) Konrad Lorenz, On Aggression
(Bantam, 1967) pp. 168-9
24) Barry Norman, The Film Greats
(London, 1985)
p. 130
25) Charles Dickens, Hard Times,
(Penguin) p. 50
26) Irving Welch, Ecstasy
(Vintage, 1997) p. 100
27) A.C. Baugh and T. Cable, A
History of the English Language (Routledge 2002) p. 140
28) Ibid., pp.137,139
29) Shakespeare, Richard II,
V, iii, line 123. (OUP, Complete Works,
1963)
30) Jean Pictet, L’Epopéé des
Peaux-Rouges (Rocher, 1994) p. 144-5; p. 159. Various
websites describe King
Philip’s War, incl.
www.hampton.lib.nh.us/hampton/history/dow;
www.historyplace.com/specials/kingphilip
31) Guenter Lewey “Were American Indians the Victims of Genocide?”, Commentary, on website:
http//hnn.us/articles/7302; 11-22-04:Historians/History; p. 9
32) Leslie A. Fiedler, Love and
Death in the American Novel, pp. 37, 210, 274 etc.
33) Faulkner, Light in August (1932,
Penguin, 1960) p. 14-15
34) Peter Gay, op. cit., p. 98
35) Ibid., p. 103
36) Ibid., p. 105
37) Ibid., p. 104
38) Ibid., p. 107
39) Ibid., p. 96
40) Ibid., p. 114-5
41) Ibid., p. 121
42) Ibid., p. 549
43) Ibid., p. 112
44) Ibid., p. 115.
45) Ibid., p. 439
46) Ibid., p. 445
47) Ibid., p. 446
48) Ibid., p. 438
49) B. & T. Roszak, Masculine/Feminine (Harper, 1969) p. 92.
50) Ibid., p. 92
51) Ibid., p. 91
52) Ibid., p. 91
53) Ibid., p. 92-3
54) Ibid., p. 91
55) Ibid., p. 93
CHAPTER FIVE
1) Alexander Pope, Essay on Man,
Book 1, lines 235 ff
2) Sedgwick’s letter to Darwin
that his theory “might brutalise and sink the human race”
quoted in Adrian Desmond and
James Moore, Darwin (Penguin, 1992), p. 487.
3) Herbert Spencer, Social
Statics (1850, US
ed 1865), p. 353-4, quoted in Gay op. cit.
4) Desmond & Moore, op.cit., p. 653; p. 267.
5) Ibid., p. 266
6) Darwin,
The Descent of Man (1871)
(Prometheus, NY, 1998) p. 138
7) Ibid., p. 641
8) Ibid., p. 139
9) Desmond & Moore, op.cit., p. 90
10) Ibid., p. 295
11) Ibid., p. 5
12) Ibid., p. 217
13) Ibid., p. 448
14) Ibid., p. 450
15) Gay, op. cit., p. 41
16) Ibid.
17) Ibid., p. 43
18) Ibid., p. 43-44
19) Darwin,
The Descent of Man, p. 138-9
20) Ibid., p. 642.
21) Gay, op. cit., p. 47
22) Hitler, Mein Kampf (New
York, Mariner Books, 1999) p.255
23) The Autobiography of Charles
Darwin, (Barlow, 1958, Norton 1969) p. 120
24) Desmond and Moore Darwin, p.265
25) Ibid., p. 267
26) Ibid.
27) Hitler, op.cit., p.131-132 (I have changed “value of the
individual” to “quality of the
individual”, which makes his
meaning clearer; he is talking in biological or health terms,
not in terms of human
rights, or the value placed on individuals by society. It is pointless
to quote a translation which distorts or
obscures the meaning, and good translations of Mein Kampf are impossible to
find.)
28) Ibid., p. 134 (I have changed the clumsy translation “more brutal and
more natural
people”, given for “brutal-natürlicher”, into “more
brutal-natured”; one could also say
“more naturally
brutal”.)
29) Ibid. (“Humanity” is changed to “humanism” to avoid
confusion with the meaning
“mankind”:
he is talking about a compassionate attitude, not about the human race.)
30) Alan Bullock, Hitler, A Study
in Tyranny. (Pelican, 1962) p. 656-7
31) Ibid. (quoting Hitler’s Table Talk)
32) Desmond and Moore, Darwin, p. 522
33) Gay, op. cit., p. 56
34) Desmond and Moore, Darwin,
p. 269
35) Mein Kampf, p. 296-9
36) Hesiod, Works and Days,
p.67, ll 277 - 281
37) Nietzsche, Thus Spake
Zarathustra (Penguin 1961) p. 42.
38) Ibid, p. 61
39) Desmond and Moore Darwin, p. 653
40) Pierre-Paul Grassé, Evolution
of Living Organisms, (NY, Academic Press, 1977) p. 8
41) Ibid., p. 3
42) Ted Steele, Lindley, Blanden Lamarck’s Signature (Sydney, 1998) especially
the chapter:
Response to Neo-Darwinist Extremism, p. 208
ff
43) Jonathan Weiner, The Beak of the Finch, (Vintage 1994),
p. 129
44) The Autobiography of Charles
Darwin, p. 120; Darwin,
p. 264- 7
45) Darwin,
The Descent of Man, p. 188
46) Desmond & Moore, Darwin,
p. 522
47) Robert Ardrey, The
Territorial Imperative, (Collins, 1967) p. 90; Lorenz, op. cit.p. 33
48) Ardrey, p. 100, citing the research of David Lack, The Life of the Robin, 1944
49) Weiner, op cit., p. 78
50) Ibid., p. 83
51) Ibid., p. 104
52) Ibid., p. 282; on the kea, p. 237
53) Lawrence P. Greksa, “Evidence for a genetic basis to the enhanced
total lung capacity of
Andean Highlanders” Human Biology February, 1996
54) Weiner, op. cit., p. 118
55) McGowan, The Raptor and The Lamb,
(London, 1997)
p.12
56) Ibid., p. 15
57) Ibid., p. 33-4. Quotes George Schaller, The Serengeti Lion (Chicago 1972).
58) McGowan, op.cit., p. 113.
59) Lee Spetner, Not by Chance,
Shattering the Modern Theory of Evolution (NY 1997) p.67
60) Weiner, op cit., p. 273
61) See Michael Giglieri, East of the Mountains of the Moon,(New York 1987)
62) David Lack, cited:
http://web2.uwindsor.ca/courses/biology/weis/55-324/lecures8.htm
63) Darwin,
The Descent of Man, (Prometheus NY,
1998) p. 639
64) Ibid., p. 607
65) Ibid., p. 617
66) Ibid., p. 621
67) Ibid., p. 642
68) Ibid.
69) Steven Gangestad and
Jeffry Simpson, “The Evolution of Human Mating: Trade-Offs and
Strategic Pluralism” at www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.gangestad.html.
70) Matt Ridley, The Red Queen,
p. 288
71) “The Ius primae noctis as
a male power display”, Jorg Wettlaufer, in Evolution
and
Human Behaviour vol 21, Nr. 2,
(2000) p. 111-123. at www.fibri.de/jus/arthbes.html
72) Bonnie Anderson & Judith Zinsser, A History of their Own, Vol II (Penguin 1990)
p.285 (citing E.A.Wrigley,
Population and History (NY 1969) pp.
186-88)
73) Historians Tenney Frank, A.M.Duff and Charles Merivale made much of
the replacement
of Rome’s
population by descendants of slaves, especially Middle Easterners. Frank
estimated 90 per cent of Rome’s
urban population were eventually of slave origin.
“Race Mixture in the Roman Empire”, American Historical Review, vol 21, 704-5.
74) J.M. Roberts, The Penguin
History of the World, (Penguin 1990) p. 676.
75) Bacon, “Of Marriage and Single Life” Essays, (Wordsworth
Classics, 1997) p. 22
76) Darwin,
Descent p. 141-2
77) Richard Dawkins, River Out of
Eden (New
York, 1995) p. 2
78) Ibid., p. 3
79) Karl Popper, Logik der
Forschung, (Vienna,
1935); trans. The Logic of
Scientific
Discovery (London, 1959);
80) Richard Milton, Shattering
the Myths of Darwinism (Rochester,
Vermont, 1997)
81) Desmond & Moore, Darwin, p. 475
82) Weiner, op cit., p. 206
83) Ibid., p. 54; also Milton,
op cit., pp. 149-51
84) Steele, Lindley, Blanden, Lamarck’s Signature (Sydney 1998),
p. 12-13.
85) Richard Milton, op. cit., p. 157
86) Lee Spetner, Not by Chance,
Shattering the Modern Theory of Evolution (NY 1997)p.122
87) Milton,
op. cit., p. 99-101
88) Ibid., p. 214.
89) Ibid., p. 123-4.
90) Ibid., p. 123.
91) Ibid., p. 124.
92) Ibid., p. 128-9
93) Ibid.
94) Ibid., p. 129
95) Christopher McGowan, The
Raptor and the Lamb. Penguin 1998, p. 23.
96) Ibid., p.12.
97) Ibid., p. 15
98) Dawkins, Darwin and Darwinism
: www.bbc.co.uk/education/darwin/leghist, p.5
99) Desmond & Moore, Darwin, p. 448
100) Weiner, op cit., p 79
101) Gangstad & Simpson, op cit. section 4.5; see note 69.
102) Richard Milton., op.cit., p. 268
103) Ibid., p. 267
104) Shakespeare, As You Like It,
Act II, Scene 1, ll.16-17
105) Hesiod, Works and Days ll.
278-82, Penguin)
106) See Gordon Muir & John
Court, “Fraud of the Century”, Catholic
Medical
Quarterly, May 1992. Elizabeth
Wright, “Kinsey, Science or Crime” Issues &
Views,
Winter 1999; Judith Reisman & Edward Eichel, Kinsey, Sex and Fraud (Lafayett, 1990);
Reisman, Kinsey: Crimes and
Consequences, (Crestwood, 1998)
107) Dawkins, River out of Eden
(Basic Books, 1995) p.6
108) Desmond & Moore, Darwin, p. 267
109) Weiner, op cit., p 206; pp. 196-9
110) Ibid., p. 164-5
111) Ibid., p. 168
112) Ibid., p. 179
113) Ibid., p. 285
114) Ibid., p. 284
115) S. Conant, Evol. Ecol.
(1988) 2, 270 – 282; See Stuart L Pimm, “Morphological Change
in an Introduced Bird” Tree vol 3, no 11, Nov
1988, p. 290 (on web.)
116) Weiner op cit., p. 110)
117) Ted Steele, Lindley, Blanden Lamarck’s Signature (Sydney, 1998) pp. 166 -9
118) Ibid., pp. 169-172
119) Milton,
op cit., pp. 227-8
120) Steele, op cit., p. 191; for foot bones, see p. 192-5.
121) Spetner op cit., p. 198, citing the works of Wilson and McDonald; Milton, op.cit., p.184
122) Spetner, op cit., p. 204
123) See articles by John Komlos, including “Anthropometric History,
What is it?” OAH Magazine of History 6 (Spring 1992) on
www.oah.org/pubs/magazine 124) John Komlos “On English Pygmies and Giants : the Physical Stature
of English Youth in the late 18th and
early 19th Centuries” University
of Munich, website:
http:// Ideas.respec.org.
Also Komlos, “Shrinking in a Growing Economy? The Mystery of Physical Stature
during the Industrial Revolution.” Same website.
125) Steckel, Richard, “New
Light on the Dark Ages; The Remarkably Tall Stature of
Northern European Men during the
Medieval Era.” Social Sciences History, vol 28, no
2, pp 211-228 (Duke Univ Press)
http://muse.uq.edu.au. Using skeletons
found, he
argues Northern European height
declined from 173.4 cm to 167 cm between early
Middle Ages and 17th C.
126) Komlos, “Shrinking in a Growing Economy? The Mystery of Physical
Stature
during the Industrial
Revolution.” Website: http:// Ideas.respec.org.
127) Spetner op cit., p. 16,
citing Wynne-Edwards, V.C. “Self Regulating Systems in
Populations of Animals”, Science (1966) vol 147, pp. 1543-8; Evolution through Group Selection
(London Blackwell 1986) On animal
infanticide see an amusing article: “One Thing They Aren’t : Maternal” by
Nathalie Angier, New York Times, May
9, 2006
128) Horizon, BBC World, October 26 2003; “The Snowball
Earth” by Paul Hoffman
and Daniel Schrag, Harvard scientists, August 8, 1999, at website:
www.eps.harvard.edu/people/faculty/hoffman/snowball
129) “The Scorecard on Globalization 1980-2000. Twenty
Years of Diminished Progress”,
by Mark Weisbrot, Dean
Baker, Egor Kraev and Judy Chen. July 11, 2001. Website:
www.cepr.net/globalization/scorecard
CHAPTER
SIX: MARXISM
1) Jung Chang & Jon Halliday, Mao,
The Unknown Story (London 2005);
their estimate is
confirmed by R.J.Rummel, Hawaii University,
on weblog, who puts total deaths from
communism at 148 million; on
Stalin, Norman Davies, Europe
(Pimlico, 1997) p. 1329.
2) Paul Johnson, Intellectuals (Harper
Perennial, 1990) p. 55 A Russian critic,
Georgi
Marchenko, has drawn
attention to Marx’s youthful drama about Satanism, “Oulanem”,
and suggested a close
identification between the young Marx and his devil-worshipping
hero.
www.forerunner.com/predvestnik/X00013_Karl_Marx.htm
3) Marx, “Bruno Bauer, The Jewish Question” Karl Marx Selected Writings, (NY, Hackett 1994)
p.22
4) Marx, op cit., p. 23, 26.
5) Ibid., p. 23
6) Edmund Burke, Reflections on
the Revolution in France,(London 1790), in English Poetry and Prose of the Romantic
Movement, ed. G.B.Woods, (1950) p. 1226.
7) Mikhail Bakunin, Statism and
Anarchy in Karl Marx Selected
Writings, p. 338
8) Johnson, op. cit., p. 62
9) Johnson, op. cit., p. 73
10) Marx, Capital, (World’s Classics, OUP
1995) p. 170
11) Ibid., p. 171
12) Ibid., p. 172
13) Ibid., p. 175
14) Ibid.
15) Ibid., p. 179
16) KM Selected Writings, p.325.
17) Norman Davies, Europe, A
History (London,
1997) p.972
18) Johnson, op cit, p. 71
19) Ibid.
20) Ibid.
21) Ibid., p. 62
22) Lenin Lessons of the Moscow
Uprising, 1906; quoted in Regis Debray, A
Critique Of
Arms (Penguin, 1977) p. 27
23) Johnson, op cit., p. 72
24) Jean Ziegler (interview with Télévision Suisse
Romande, 2003)
25) Arthur Koestler, Darkness at
Noon (1940) in Bricks to Babel (Picador, 1980)
p. 193-4
26) Ibid, p. 197
27) Ignazio Silone, The God that
Failed (Harper, New York 1949) p.106 (essays with Arthur
Koestler et al) cited on
website: http://users.cyberone.com.au/myers/koestler
28) Jean Ziegler, L’empire de la Honte, (Fayard 2005). Interview GHI, Geneva, 11.5.2005
29) Susan Sonntag, “What’s Happening to America”, Partisan
Review, Winter 1967;
reprinted in American Cultural Studies, J. Hartley
and R. Pearson (OUP 2000) p. 37.
30) Preface to Franz Fanon’s Les Damnés de la Terre (Paris, 1961)
31) Arnold Beichman, “Barbarians at the
Lectern” Hoover Digest, 2002, no 2. Website:
www.hooverdigest.org
32) Hugh Thomas, The Slave Trade,
(Picador 1997) p. 25
33) Ibid., p. 26
34) Ibid., p. 38; Johannes Bronsted, The Vikings (Penguin, 1985) p. 264-5
35) Hugh Thomas, op. cit., p. 37
36) Ibid., p. 807
37) Ibid., pp. 88 - 93
38) Ibid., p. 92
39) Ibid., p. 352
40) Ibid., pp. 559-60
41) Ibid., p. 559
42) Ibid., p. 560-4
43) Ibid., p. 21
44) Ibid., p. 467
45) Ibid., pp. 377-9
46) Ibid., p. 465-6
47) Pushkin “The Negro of Peter the Great” in The Queen of Spades and Other Stories
(Penguin 1962)
48) Thomas, op. cit., p 464
49) Ibid., p. 463
50) Ibid., p. 511
51) Ibid., p. 550.
52) David Barton, “George Washington, Thomas Jefferson and Slavery in Virginia” Website
www.wallbuilders.com
53) Ibid.
54) Thomas, pp. 469-74
55) Ibid., p. 784
56) Ibid., p. 697
57) Ibid., p 791.
58) www.anti-slaverysociety.addr.com See also Kathleen Fitzgibbon, “Modern Day
Slavery?
The scope of trafficking in persons in Africa” (Senior
reporting officer for Africa, U.S. State
department) in African SecurityReview Vol
12, No 1, 2003 ; website www. iss.co.za
59) www.anti-slaverysociety.addr.com
60) ILO Geneva
“Global Child Labour Trends 2000-2004”, April 2006.
61) Jonathan Clayton, “The Lost Children of Nigeria’s Sex Trade”, The Times, posted April 4,
2004 on website : blackchat.co.uk/theblackforum
62) On numbers see Thomas op.cit. pp. 796, 805, et passim.
63) Clayton, op. cit.
64) Biography
Bartolomé de las Casas, at elvis.rowan.edu; also on http://oregonstate.edu
65) Ibid.
(elvis.rowan.edu)
66) Montaigne “On
Coaches” Essays (trans Ives, NY
Heritage Press, 1946) pp. 1235-45.
67) Guenter Lewy, “Were American Indians the Victims of Genocide?” Commentary; see
website:
http//hnn.us/articles/7302
11.22.04 Historians/History
68) Vine Deloria, “Indians Today, the Real and the Unreal”, in American
Cultural Studies,
J. Hartley and R. Pearson
(OUP 2000) p. 44
69) Sontag, op cit., p. 32
70) See Lewy, op.cit. for an intelligent discussion of this.
71) On this whole subject, see Dinesh D’Souza’s excellent book,
Illiberal Education, (New
York 1991), especially the chapter “Travels with
Rigoberta”, p. 59 ff. Also his article:
“Fraudulent
Storyteller Still Praised”, Isms et
Ologies, website : www.boundless.org
and David Horowitz, “I, Rigoberta Menchu,
Liar”, Frontpage Magazine, Feb 26, 1999.
Website: www.frontpagemag.com
72) Arthur Koestler, “On Disbelieving
Atrocities”, in The Yogi
and the Commissar in Bricks
to Babel (Picador,
1982)p. 231. Also
73) Michael C. Desch, “Abusing the
Holocaust” in The
American Conservative (April 12
2004)
website: www.amconmag.com
74) Goldhagen, op.cit., p.533 argues that shooting was just as fast as
gassing, and the latter
was adopted not
for speed but for the psychological comfort of the Nazi killers. “Had the Germans
never invented the gas chamber, then they might well have killed almost as many
Jews.”
75) Norman Davies, in his monumental Europe,
(London, Pimlico, 1997), p. 1329, puts the
total number killed in the USSR,
excluding war dead but including Ukrainian famine
victims, at 54 million. It seems high,
but he gives a detailed breakdown.
76) On lynching numbers: “At the Hands of Persons
Unknown: Lynching in America”,
Constitutional Rights
Foundation, website: www.crf-usa.org/brown50th/lynching
77) Hegel, The Philosophy of
History, in The Age of Ideology
(NY, Mentor 1956) p. 90
78) “Beethoven: Revealing his True Identity” www.africawithin.com/kwaku/beethoven
2003 Kwaku Person-Lynn.
Also a seminar chaired by Professor Ann duCille, “Was
Shakespeare Black?” at
Wesleyan,
www.wesleyan.edu/alumni/event2001/
For a hilarious look at
this theme see interviews with US black activists in one of Louis
Theroux’s Wacky Weekends, BBC, 2004.
79) Christopher Hitchens, British-American leftist journalist, began to
support the Iraq
war,
while his right-wing
brother Peter opposed it.
80) See for example Patrick Buchanan’s Where the Right Went Wrong, (New York 2004) for
a conservative attack on
the neo-conservatives’ war in Iraq.
81) Christina Hoff Sommers Who
Stole Feminism? (New York
1994) website
www.canlaw.com/rights/thumbrul
82) Elizabeth Pleck, Domestic
Tyranny (NY, OUP 1987)
83) Alain Decaux Histoire des Françaises (Perrin, 1998) p. 89-90
84) On this whole argument see Do
women have souls? The Story of Three Myths by
Michael Nolan.
www.churchinhistory.org
85) George Orwell, 1984, in Penguin Complete Novels (1983) p.785
86) Bonnie Anderson & Judith Zinsser, A History of Their Own (Penguin 1988)
Vol II, p. 169
|